Sellars, Wilfrid S.: In the Space of Reasons: Selected Essays of Wilfrid Sellars.
deVries, Willem A.
SELLARS, Wilfrid S. In the Space of Reasons: Selected Essays of
Wilfrid Sellars. Edited by Kevin Scharp and Robert B. Brandom.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. xxviii + 491 pp. Cloth,
$45.00--The editors of this volume boldly proclaim Sellars to be the
greatest American philosopher since C. S. Peirce. They are probably
right, but this is a minority opinion, as the state of Sellars's
oeuvre attests. The original publishers of Sellars's principal
books have let them go out of print. A small house, Ridgeview
Publishing, originally published Naturalism and Ontology, and has
valiantly republished Sellars's other works and even added
collections of Sellars's early essays, his work on Kant, and
editions of Sellars's lectures on Kant and on epistemology. Slowly,
Sellars is emerging from his relative neglect. Sellars's well known
essay, "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind" [EPM] is now
available in two editions: one from Harvard, edited by Brandom, and
another from Hackett, with a substantial commentary by deVries and
Triplett. With In the Space of Reasons more of Sellars returns to the
list of a major academic publisher.
This volume aims to collect "the papers most important for
understanding the core of [Sellars's] synoptic philosophical
vision" (p. vii). It clearly bears the stamp of Brandom's
focus on "the metaphysics of intentionality." Seventeen essays
are included in 5 parts: "Language and Meaning,"
"Abstract Entities," "Mind, Language, and the
World," "Science and the Mind," and a final section of
historical essays on Kant. Sellars published around 100 essays, so this
is still very much a selection. Six of the essays originally appeared in
Sellars's 1963 collection Science, Perception and Reality [SPR]. Of
the other 11 essays here, only one predates SPR, "Inference and
Meaning" (a major influence on Brandom). The essays complement each
other across as well as within the sections. Sellars had a comprehensive
philosophical view, but his individual essays contain no more than
partial perspectives of the complex whole viewed in the light of a
particular issue. Read together, the multi-dimensional solidity of his
philosophy emerges.
The essays form a good introduction to Sellars's vision, and I
am particularly pleased that attention is given to his treatment of
abstract entities, but there are omissions. Sellars's historical
essays (other than a few on Kant) and his essays in ethics are notably
absent. These are two areas that separate Sellars from other American
luminaries, for example, Quine and Davidson. That Sellars's
extensive historical writings (never merely philological exercises)
could not be included is understandable. But omitting Sellars's
essays on ethics and values is a tremendous pity, for at the very core
of Sellars's synoptic vision is the distinction between empirical
description and normative prescription, and it is in these essays (for
example, "On Reasoning about Values") that he examines the
logic of prescriptive discourse.
Given the influence of EPM on contemporary epistemology, it is
surprising that epistemology is not more prominent in the collection,
perhaps via "The Structure of Knowledge". Similarly, though
Sellars was an important philosopher of science widely known for his
scientific realism, there are only traces of these issues here.
These are regrettable omissions, not because Scharp and Brandom
chose the wrong essays, but because no one (reasonable) volume could do
justice to Sellars's thought. Let us hope this volume does well
enough to justify a second volume in which these omissions can be made
good.
One omission is culpable: there is no bibliography of
Sellars's works. Even a partial bibliography of other significant
works would have been tremendously helpful. Thankfully, a complete
bibliography along with a large number of secondary resources is
available on line at the "Problems from Wilfrid Sellars"
website: http://www.ditext.com/sellars/. On the positive side, the
volume is thoroughly indexed, which will be extremely valuable for close
work on these essays.
The editors' introduction to this volume is brief and consists
mostly of thumbnail sketches of the essays. These thumbnails are
sometimes frustratingly sketchy and occasionally inaccurate. At one
point it is claimed that in his treatment of singular distributive
terms, Sellars believes "'the lion is tawny' is
sense-equivalent to 'all lions are necessarily tawny'"
(p. xvi), but this is a much stronger claim than Sellars himself ever
commits to. The editors also claim that Sellars's famous
Ryleans--protopersons who have not yet become conscious of their own
psychologies--"perform only linguistic acts, not actions" (p.
xx), which is contradicted by Sellars on page 271. Sellars's theory
of perception is called a "version of direct realism" (p.
xxii), but surely it is more accurate to call it a version of critical
realism. The thumbnail of "Philosophy and the Scientific Image of
Man"--Sellars's best known paper after EPM-does not
distinguish properly between the Original Image and the Manirest Image
and claims that Sellars thinks the scientific image falls short in not
being able to "explain social activity," whereas Sellars
really thinks that the scientific image lacks "the language of
community and individual intentions" (p. 408). The point of the
language of intentions is not to interpret or explain the world, but to
change it.
The bottom line is unmistakable, however: Here are central works of
the most profound and fertile American philosopher of the post-war era:
everyone should have these essays.--Willem A. deVries, University of New
Hampshire.