Grosholz, Emily R. Representation and Productive Ambiguity in Mathematics and the Sciences.
Roberts, David Lindsay
GROSHOLZ, Emily R. Representation and Productive Ambiguity in
Mathematics and the Sciences. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
xviii + 313 pp. Cloth, $63.00--This book provides a series of case
studies supporting the author's claim that ambiguous representation
can be central to advances in both mathematics and science.
Chapter 1 briefly treats two exemplary cases and shows then to be
imbued with ambiguity: the study of projectile motion by Galileo in the
early seventeenth century and the chemical formulas proposed by Jacob
Berzelius in the early nineteenth century. Here and throughout Grosholz
makes abundant use of C. S. Peirce's distinction between iconic and
symbolic representations (that is, those linked to their objects by
similarity and those linked by convention), while emphasizing that these
two modes will often blend and interchange. Grosholz also here lays out
an intellectual genealogy, beginning with the logical positivists,
especially Carnap, whose reductionist program she evaluates as
"essentially syntactical" (p. 20). The following generation of
semantic philosophers (Nancy Cartwright, Ian Hacking, and others) were
in turn succeeded by Grosholz's own cohort, who augmented the
philosophy of science toolkit with pragmatic considerations, bringing
historical context to the forefront. Grosholz claims some credit for
including philosophy of mathematics within this pragmatic turn, an
extension she sees some otherwise likeminded colleagues (Ursula Klein,
Robin Hendry) as having been hesitant to make.
Further groundwork is laid in Chapter 2, "Analysis and
Experience." Analysis, for Grosholz, is "the search for
conditions of intelligibility" (p. 33). She acknowledges numerous
intellectual debts (she is commendably explicit and generous in this
regard throughout), from Leibniz, Locke, and Hume to Jean Cavailles,
Herbert Breger, and Carlo Cellucci. Leibniz looms especially large;
Grosholz is firmly in the camp of those committed to rescuing him from
the stunted interpretations of Louis Couturat and Bertrand Russell.
Leibniz for Grosholz is not a logicist but rather a pragmatic user of
multiple modes of representation, helping to demonstrate "why the
philosophical project of fmding the sole correct representation of
mathematics is misguided" (p. 48).
Chapters 3, 4, and 5 present close readings of cases involving the
interfaces among biology, chemistry, physics, and geometry: constructing
and testing an antibody mimic, understanding the transposition of genes,
and investigating benzene via molecular orbital theory. Although
Grosholz is engaged by the scientific cases in their own right,
especially as they illustrate the subtleties of theory reduction, she
makes clear that a major motivation for including them is to emphasize
commonalities with mathematical practice, and to insist that mathematics
should not be considered a unique outlier when compared to the physical
and biological sciences.
Descartes, Newton, and Leibniz are treated in Chapters 6, 7, and 8,
respectively. Grosholz views Descartes as a genius who persuasively
promoted the false hope of ultimate clarity in mathematics and science.
His mathematical practice, often inconsistent with his methodological
pronouncements, is found to be rich in productive ambiguity.
Newton's Principia is likewise rich. A tour of some key
propositions from that book reveals the crucial ambiguity of the
diagrams found therein, as Newton shifts back and forth between geometry
and mechanics, and between the finite and the infinitesimal. Grosholz
defends the importance of diagrams against Kantian snobbery. In the
Leibniz chapter she emphasizes that "what a diagram means depends
on its context of use" (p. 219). Appropriately, the book is
abundantly illustrated with figures taken from primary sources being
considered.
Chapter 9 begins with a survey of Jules Vuillemin's approach
to the philosophy of mathematics and then proceeds to examine De
Rham's theorem, which, by employing multiple modes of
representation, demonstrates an isomorphism between two sets of
algebraic invariants associated with a smoothly triangulated manifold.
Nancy Cartwright's views on the abstract and concrete are used to
interpret the philosophical significance of this episode.
In the last chapter Grosholz argues that "there cannot be
complete speech about mathematical things," (p. 259) and criticizes
the foundational proposals of both Bertrand Russell and Penelope Maddy.
She looks at mathematical results connecting logic, topology, and
algebra, such as the theorem of M. H. Stone, (not W. H., as the book
would have it), which asserts that any Boolean algebra can be
represented by an algebra of sets associated with an appropriately
constructed topological space.
Grosholz's overall position is clear, and each case provides
her opportunity for cogent remarks, but probably few readers will find
all the case studies equally illuminating or understandable. At times
the work resembles a scrapbook of Grosholz's intellectual interests
more than a connected argument. Many intriguing questions are left
unasked. There is never a hint that investigators at different times or
places (all cases are from standard Western science and mathematics)
have been better or worse at utilizing ambiguous representation, and no
indication that investigators have, or have not, learned to master
ambiguity from acquaintance with their predecessors. If scientists and
mathematicians are conscious or unconscious of ambiguity does this have
any practical consequences?--David Lindsay Roberts, Prince George's
Community College.