Johnson, Wayne G. Morality: Does "God" Make a Difference?
Taliaferro, Charles
JOHNSON, Wayne G. Morality; Does "God" Make a Difference?
Lanham: University Press of America, 2005. ix + 238 pp. Cloth, $65.00;
paper, $35.00--In some philosophical circles, ontology (or metaphysics)
is considered public enemy number one when it comes to ethics. Hilary
Putnam, for example, argues that ontology is as extraneous to ethics as
it is to mathematics. In his recent book, Wayne Johnson takes the
opposite position, arguing persuasively that ethics requires an
ontology, a broad metaphysical framework that accounts for the normative
force of ethics. Morality; Does "God" Make a Difference? is
written with clarity and would make an accessible guide to classical and
contemporary moral theory.
Chapter 1, "A Theory About Moral Theories," sets forth
Johnson's central theme: "Normative ethical systems are best
understood as attempts to seek out and justify ways of living a
fulfilled human life in terms of the kind of fulfillment one believes to
be possible given one's beliefs about human nature and the ultimate
nature of all things. Furthermore, any normative ethical system must
also indicate just how one's own quest for fulfillment is related
to the experiences of other people and sentient beings, given, again,
one's view of human nature and the ultimate nature of all
things" (p. 8). Chapter 2, "The Point of Morality," makes
the case that morality is an unavoidable enterprise as persons seek to
adjudicate competing wants, needs, and desires. The search for
fulfillment inevitably raises concern for fair-minded reflection on
appropriate and inappropriate modes of fulfillment.
Chapter 3 provides a useful, reliable guide to major moral theories
and worldviews. This would be highly useful for undergraduates in their
first or second course in philosophy. Chapter 4 offers a balanced
overview of religion-based ethics. While chapters 3 and 4 are largely
descriptive, chapter 5 argues that theism does make a difference
ethically. Here and elsewhere, Johnson remains neutral in arguing for or
against theism. His principle aim is to argue for the relevance of a
theistic, naturalistic, or some other type of ontology. I find this
section entirely successful. As Johnson points out, ethics comes to be
profoundly shaped by whether or not you believe that the cosmos has a
loving, good creator, or that there is an afterlife, or that there is a
unity between God (Brahman) and nature, and so on.
Chapter 6 considers how different ontologies offer competing
accounts of moral obligations and rights. This chapter and the next are
especially concerned with the relationship between persons and their
communities, and then the relationship between different communities.
Johnson opposes ethical relativism. In chapter 8, Johnson exhibits the
way in which different ontologies give rise to different accounts of
moral psychology. In chapter 9, Johnson offers a subtle analysis of the
virtues and vices of grounding ethics in evolutionary biology. True to
the spirit of this remarkable book, Johnson's principle aim is to
elucidate the connection between ontology and ethics while remaining
neutral in terms of his declared ontological preference. The final
chapter invites readers to the broader field of philosophy of religion,
where one may weigh the reasons and values behind religion-based
moralities.
This is a fine book that would work well for an introduction to
ethics. Lest that seem like a faint praise, I must add that I believe
this book also mounts a powerful case against books like Ethics without
Ontology by Hilary Putnam (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2004).
Although Johnson does not mention Putnam (who is widely considered one
of the most distinguished living American philosophers), I believe
Johnson's arguments and exposition of the philosophical landscape
present a formidable challenge to Putnam and his followers.--Charles
Taliaferro, St. Olaf College.