LEE, Mi-Kyoung. Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus.
Gilbert, Christopher
LEE, Mi-Kyoung. Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to
Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2005. 254 pp. Cloth, $74.00--Mi-Kyoung Lee has
produced an engaging study of the development of skepticism in ancient
Greece. Although arguments against the possibility of knowledge--and
responses thereto-were common during the Hellenistic period, the great
works of the Classical period hardly give skepticism a second thought.
Were great minds like Plato and Aristotle blithely unaware of the threat
posed by skepticism? Lee's answer is that the questions and
arguments of Hellenistic period skeptics were not unprecedented, for a
nascent form of skepticism had already been debated in the Classical
period. The relativism of Protagoras' measure doctrine--"Man
is the measure of all things"--was a challenge to Classical
epistemologies, for it implied that no one could ever be mistaken about
anything. Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus all recognized this
challenge, and their responses to it shaped the debate over skepticism
in the Hellenistic period.
Sifting through the testimony of later philosophers, Lee explains
how Protagoras's measure doctrine should be understood. On the
basis of views that other thinkers attributed to Protagoras and their
responses to those views, Lee argues that Protagoras did not defend a
theory about truth itself, such as truth-relativism (nothing is true
simpliciter, things are only true relative to particular individuals in
particular contexts). Rather, the measure doctrine asserts
fact-relativism--the idea that every property or state of affairs is
relative to particular individuals. Thus, Protagoras had a
nonrelativized notion of truth, but he claimed that things actually are
as they appear to us; each and every human being can determine what is
true simply by consulting his own beliefs.
Although Protagoras did not develop a full-fledged relativist epistemology, Plato did. In the Theaetetus, Plato offers a "Secret
Doctrine" on behalf of Protagoras. This doctrine, which Plato
introduces so that he can then refute it, is a set of metaphysical
theses meant to explain and justify Protagoras' measure doctrine.
At its heart are two ideas: (1) the Heraclitean claim that all things
are constantly changing, and (2) total relativity--the claim that
"nothing is anything by itself, but is so only relative to
something else" (p. 86). In Lee's view, Plato's Secret
Doctrine and his attack thereupon constitute, hot a conclusive
refutation of Protagoras, but a Classical experiment in thinking about
relativism.
Aristotle is more explicit than Plato on the skeptical implications
of relativism. In Metaphysics book 4, chapter 5, Aristotle identifies
three beliefs as leading to the conclusion that the truth about things
can never be known: (P) the Protagorean measure doctrine; (H) the
Heraclitean idea that all is in flux; and (C) the contradictionist claim
that everything both is and is not the case. Aristotle responds to the
skeptical implications of these ideas, hot by attacking skepticism
itself, but by identifying and undermining the faulty assumptions that
lie behind beliefs (P), (H), and (C). All three beliefs test on the
mistaken idea that thinking is like perceiving--that the mind's
thinking is a purely passive affection caused by the objects of thought.
Beliefs (P), (H), and (C) also presuppose that all of reality is
matedal--that to be is to be perceivable. Lee thus demonstrates that
Aristotle was "genuinely interested in engaging with and fending
off [skeptical] challenges to his own realist and objectivist
assumptions" (p. 253).
Although neither a relativist nor a skeptic, Democritus was the
Classical philosopher whose ideas were most akin to those of Protagoras.
Democritus held that a thing has a sensible quality if and only if it
appears to have that quality to some perceiver. So sensible qualities
really are as they appear to us, for that is all sensible qualities
are--our sense perceptions tell us only how things affect our senses,
not what things are like in themselves. In order to know what things are
like in themselves, Democritus argued, our minds must grasp that which
is too fine for the senses to discern--namely, atoms and the void.
Democritus thus embraced a qualified version of the Protagorean measure
doctrine. The senses are (incomplete) measures of truth because
knowledge is impossible without sensation--without sense data, our minds
would have nothing about which to think. Human beings (as both sensing
and thinking things) are complete measures of truth because when we
think carefully about the things that cause our sensations, we are
capable of understanding the truth about those things.
This book is thoroughly researched, well argued, and clearly
written. Lee's analysis of epistemological issues is technically
rigorous, but she gives plenty of everyday examples to make the finer
points clear to nonspecialists. I would especially urge anyone
interested in Plato's Theaetetus to read Lee's fifth chapter,
which offers an excellent explication of a very difficult section of
that dialogue.--Christopher Gilbert, Cuesta College.