Seeskin, Kenneth. Maimonides on the Origin of the World.
McLaughlin, Thomas J.
SEESKIN, Kenneth. Maimonides on the Origin of the World. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2005. vii + 215 pp. Cloth, $55.00--This
work, rich in arguments and scholarship, is so clearly written that one
is tempted to quote from it at length. As Seeskin notes, questions about
the world's origin are directly related to what the world is, what
God is, and what human reason can know. Such questions also involve a
fundamental principle of religious faith. Maimonides's discussion
of the world's origin, one of his major contributions to
philosophy, has been subject to considerable disagreement. Seeskin
examines a variety of interpretations and argues that according to Maimonides, "the world was brought into existence out of nothing in
the first instant of time. In short, motion and time are created
together" (p. 2). Seeskin calls this view creation ex nihilo and de
novo. It implies, according to Maimonides, that God need not have
created the world at all, but did so by His own free choice and wisdom.
Following an introductory chapter discussing basic issues about God
and the world's origin, a chapter each is dedicated to Plato,
Aristotle, and Plotinus respectively. The general strategy of these
chapters is to examine each philosopher's understanding of the
world's origin and then to consider Maimonides's view of them
and the use he made of them. Thus, Seeskin offers interpretations not
only of Maimonides but also of several other major figures in ancient
and medieval philosophy. Each thinker is a kind of foil. Plato, on
Maimonides's view, held that the order and structure of the world
were created de novo, but not ex nihilo since the world was formed from
preexistent matter that is eternal. Maimonides viewed Aristotle as
having held that both the structure and matter of the world are eternal.
The world, according to Aristotle, is not created either de novo or ex
nihilo. Plotinus' View, which came to Maimonides through Affarabi
and Avicenna, denies creation de novo since all things necessarily and
eternally emanate from the One. Emanation does not deny creation ex
nihilo in the sense that everything owes its existence to God, but does
deny creation ex nihilo in the sense that emanation, especially of
matter, proceeds through intermediaries. Although Maimonides praises
emanation as a "type of causality that does not involve physical
contact" (p. 119), emanation posed numerous difficulties for him.
Fundamentally, however, emanation is a foil for Maimonides's claim
that the world is contingent. Unlike Aquinas, Maimonides, held that an
eternal world cannot be freely willed by its Creator but is created
necessarily. Thus, if the world is eternal, God could not have chosen
not to create it.
Maimonides argues that some basic features of this world are
contingent and, therefore, are products of a free agent. Seeskin's
discussion of this argument from particularity actually involves a
number of arguments, including a valuable examination of
Maimonides's view of science, especially astronomy. Maimonides
accepted Aristotle's scientific account of the terrestrial realm
but viewed his astronomy as deeply flawed. Drawing heavily upon the
Mutakallimun, especially Alghazali, Maimonides argued that the celestial
bodies have characteristics for which there is no necessary cause, such
as the number and size of the celestial spheres, the direction in which
they revolve, or the distribution of the fixed stars. Maimonides also
argues that the incompatibility of Ptolemy's astronomy with
Aristotle's shows that for many celestial phenomena necessary
causes had not been discovered. One could maintain that necessary causes
for these phenomena eventually would be discovered, and that the
problems posed by the incompatibility of Ptolemaic and Aristotelian
astronomy would be solved; however, Maimonides thought that the failure
to discover necessary causes was most reasonably regarded as indicating
the difficulties inherent in the subject matter of astronomy, the
contingency of celestial phenomena, and the limits of human
understanding. As Seeskin discusses in some detail, Maimonides regarded
the failure to discover necessary causes of many celestial phenomena and
the arguments for the contingency of such phenomena as seriously
weakening the case for eternal emanation and strengthening the case for
creation de novo.
Seeskin argues that although Maimonides claimed that many celestial
phenomena are contingent, we must not think of him as maintaining that
they do not have causes or that God created them arbitrarily. The
spheres and their motions are ordered and purposeful. In this,
Maimonides opposed Alghazali as well as Avicenna. He held that God acts
for a reason, even if that reason is unknown to us; but that reason does
not necessitate God's choice, and creation is a free act that God
need not have willed.
Although Maimonides thought that the case for eternal creation was
weak, he did not think it refuted, nor did he think that creation de
novo, though the most reasonable view, could be demonstrated. As Seeskin
points out, Maimonides, like Aquinas, argued that creation ex nihilo and
de novo is intelligible and possible. However, unlike Aquinas,
Maimonides argued that it need not be accepted as true on revealed
grounds alone.
A further chapter examines Maimonides's view on miracles and
the end of the world. Creation de novo is consistent with the
possibility of miracles but raises the question as to whether or not the
world must end. Maimonides's argument that it need not end
crucially depends upon the claims that the existence of the world is
from God and that creation is not a natural process.--Thomas J.
McLaughlin, St. John Vianney Theological Seminary.