Niederbacher, Bruno. Glaube als Tugend bei Thomas von Aquin: Erkenntnistheoretische und religionsphilosophische Interpretationen.
Meconi, David Vincent
NIEDERBACHER, Bruno. Glaube als Tugend bei Thomas von Aquin:
Erkenntnistheoretische und religionsphilosophische Interpretationen.
Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 2004. 194 pp. Cloth, $36.00--Echoing much of the
neo-Thomistic revival of the twentieth century, Fides et Ratio [section]
76 sketches the two main characteristics of a Christian philosophy: it
is a type of thinking which simultaneously employs yet always seeks to
purify reason and, secondly, it does not close itself off to the
concerns and content of revelation. In this way, Pope John Paul II calls
for a contemporary understanding of faith which is seen as a virtue
freeing human reason from presumption, "the typical temptation of
the philosopher." In his latest, Bruno Niederbacher likewise calls
for such learned docility in both the human soul as well as in the
modern Academy. Divided into six main sections, this work concentrates
on two main arguments. First, he shows why Thomas held that faith
enables assent to what is and thus proves to be a necessary virtue for
correct thinking and action and, secondly, what significance such a
claim has for us today.
After a brief introduction (pp. 9-16) defining terms and mapping
out this project, chapter 2 (pp. 17-42) takes up the initial question of
what Thomas means by credibile. Here Niederbacher first dissects the
Thomistic concept of goal-oriented action, primarily as it is develops
throughout the earlier questions of ST I-II and only then takes up the
question of absolute happiness and the role of faith in obtaining such
beatitude. A nice job is done in juxtaposing the philosophical
understanding of the human person's attainment of an uncreated good
with the answer given by theologians and their insistence on the need
for revelation. Chapter 3 (pp. 43-89) analyzes the act of faith by means
of standard epistemological categories, concentrating mainly on
Thomas's use of the classical Augustinian credere Deo, credere
Deum, and credere in Deum. As Niederbacher progresses he cleverly shows
how Thomas maneuvers his understanding of faith between an irrational
decision and a necessary rationalism; rather, it emerges as a free and
reasonable act of both intellect, and will ordered toward the end for
which the human person was made in principio. More should have been said
here of the divinely granted life which begins such a process but
Niederbacher has unfortunately, albeit understandably, decided to
bracket any detailed discussion of the mechanics of grace.
The fourth chapter (pp. 90-150) treats the virtue of faith and
proves to be the most welcomed section. Here both the role of faith in a
well-integrated human life as well as why the gifts of the Holy Spirit
are an essential part of Thomas's understanding of the beata vito
are taken up in turn. In ninny significant ways, Niederbacher mirrors
Paul Wadell's The Primacy of Love (Paulist, 1992) in showing
Thomas's genius in uniting the virtues and all the qualities one
desires for himself and finds attractive in another. It was refreshing
to read how Niederbacher incorporated two otherwise forgotten aspects of
Thomas thought: the human emotions as worthy of philosophical
speculation as well as the importance of the community in which one
finds himself, as that which models and transmits the virtues. There are
also insightful parallels in this section between Alvin Plantinga's
recent account of Warranted Christian Belief and Thomas's account.
The fifth (pp. 151-65) and the sixth (pp. 166-75) chapters conclude
this work by respectively taking up the questions of epistemological and
religious relevance of Niederbacher's analysis thus far. Bringing
such virtue epistemology into the contemporary discussion of how one
justifies cognitive and religious convictions (Rechtfertigung von
Uberzeugungen), Niederbacher chooses to focus on two current debates:
Foundationalism versus Coherentism and Internalism versus Externalism.
Within this discussion, he successfully shows how Thomas's
understanding of faith can contribute to modern virtue epistemology,
especially as it is developed by Linda Zagzebski. To end this work by
treating questions of epistemic justification in today's struggle
to understand the human person as both homo sapiens as well as homo
odorants shows how Thomas's confidence in rational assent is able
to engage the many concerns left in modernity's wake.
No doubt the past few years have brought an increase in
philosophical works on the relationship between faith and reason, but
not many in the academy, especially philosophers, have taken up the
question of why faith should be considered a virtue. Niederbacher, of
the Department of Christian Philosophy at the University of Innsbruck,
has thus produced a very welcomed text for those interested in engaging
Thomas's account of virtue and knowledge with the modern world.
Niederbacher's German prose is accessible, writing clearly and with
many examples directed toward those not well-versed in the discussion at
hand. This volume is the most recent addition to the celebrated Munich
Philosophical Studies series.--David Vincent Meconi, S.J., University of
Oxford.