首页    期刊浏览 2024年10月05日 星期六
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Hanewald, Christian. Apperzeption und Einbildungskraft: Die Auseinenandertzung mit der theioretischen Philosophie Kants in Fichtes fruhes Wissenschaftslehre.
  • 作者:Pozzo, Riccardo
  • 期刊名称:The Review of Metaphysics
  • 印刷版ISSN:0034-6632
  • 出版年度:2004
  • 期号:March
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:Philosophy Education Society, Inc.
  • 摘要:HANEWALD, Christian. Apperzeption und Einbildungskraft: Die Auseinenandertzung mit der theioretischen Philosophie Kants in Fichtes fruhes Wissenschaftslehre. Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie, vol. 55. New York: De Gruyter, 2001. 297 p. Cloth, $109.20--This volume is a revised version of a dissertation defended at the University of Cologne in the winter term of 1999/2000 under the direction of Klaus Dusing. It is divided into two parts, respectively on the first version of Fichte's Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre (1794) and on its second version, the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo (1798/1799). It works thus on a small scope, since it concentrates on the years Fichte spent in Jena and leaves out his later development. This decision is methodically impeccable, because the choice of a small number of seminal texts makes the carrying out of sound research so much easier. Hanewald offers important insights that bear on (a) the systematic interpretation of certain passages of Fichte's two books; (b) the localization of Fichte's sources, first and foremost in Kant's theoretical philosophy, namely in the Critique of Pare Reason and Critique of Judgment (in itself, this is an original approach, given that all literature has been led, or misled, by Fichte's remark that he had been awakened to philosophy by the Critique of Practical Reason); and finally (c) the laying out of the philosophical problem of the role played by the procedure of apperception and the faculty of imagination in constituting transcendental idealism.

    Hanewald questions three main interpretations of Fichte's relation to Kant, namely, (1) that the Wissensehafstlehre illegally trespasses the limits by the critique of reason, (2) that Fichte is the one who brought Kant's transcendental philosophy to its completion by finding out and by remediating Kant's systematic loophole, and finally (3) that Fichte's correction to Kant does not go far enough and has to wait for its completion through Hegel. There is something true in these mainstream interpretations, and something that needs to be corrected, says Hanewald. In order to reconstruct in the most exact way where Fichte stands with regard to Kant, the first thing to do is to put into brackets what Fichte himself says about the primacy of practical philosophy, for instance in the detailed stances on Kant from the Erste und Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, which do not represent anymore the stand of the first Wissenschaftslehre and rather mirror that of the Wissenschafstlehre nova methodo, as one can see, for example, as regards the role played by the pure ego as the principle of philosophy. This means that one should rather proceed by directly comparing Kant's and Fichte's argument and look for agreements and disagreements, which is what Hanewald effectively does. For example, while for Kant the unity of manifold representation must precede the identical serf-reference of identity, for Fichte the contrary is the case, namely, that identical self-reference is the presupposition of all synthesis. Besides, Fichte explores other forms of serf-referential ego, from which he deduces among others the relation of subjects and accidents. In this case Kant cannot obviously be counted among Fichte's sources, because for Kant the category of substance is tied up with what is permanent in the flux of the accidents, which is something that finds expression in the schema of the permanence of time. Among the merits of Hanewald's book is that it shows that the role played by the intellectual intuition in the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo marks a significant development from the first Wissenschaftslehre and at the same time a significant distance from Kant's theoretical philosophy.--Riccardo Pozzo, The University of Verona.
  • 关键词:Books

Hanewald, Christian. Apperzeption und Einbildungskraft: Die Auseinenandertzung mit der theioretischen Philosophie Kants in Fichtes fruhes Wissenschaftslehre.


Pozzo, Riccardo


HANEWALD, Christian. Apperzeption und Einbildungskraft: Die Auseinenandertzung mit der theioretischen Philosophie Kants in Fichtes fruhes Wissenschaftslehre. Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie, vol. 55. New York: De Gruyter, 2001. 297 p. Cloth, $109.20--This volume is a revised version of a dissertation defended at the University of Cologne in the winter term of 1999/2000 under the direction of Klaus Dusing. It is divided into two parts, respectively on the first version of Fichte's Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre (1794) and on its second version, the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo (1798/1799). It works thus on a small scope, since it concentrates on the years Fichte spent in Jena and leaves out his later development. This decision is methodically impeccable, because the choice of a small number of seminal texts makes the carrying out of sound research so much easier. Hanewald offers important insights that bear on (a) the systematic interpretation of certain passages of Fichte's two books; (b) the localization of Fichte's sources, first and foremost in Kant's theoretical philosophy, namely in the Critique of Pare Reason and Critique of Judgment (in itself, this is an original approach, given that all literature has been led, or misled, by Fichte's remark that he had been awakened to philosophy by the Critique of Practical Reason); and finally (c) the laying out of the philosophical problem of the role played by the procedure of apperception and the faculty of imagination in constituting transcendental idealism.

Hanewald questions three main interpretations of Fichte's relation to Kant, namely, (1) that the Wissensehafstlehre illegally trespasses the limits by the critique of reason, (2) that Fichte is the one who brought Kant's transcendental philosophy to its completion by finding out and by remediating Kant's systematic loophole, and finally (3) that Fichte's correction to Kant does not go far enough and has to wait for its completion through Hegel. There is something true in these mainstream interpretations, and something that needs to be corrected, says Hanewald. In order to reconstruct in the most exact way where Fichte stands with regard to Kant, the first thing to do is to put into brackets what Fichte himself says about the primacy of practical philosophy, for instance in the detailed stances on Kant from the Erste und Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, which do not represent anymore the stand of the first Wissenschaftslehre and rather mirror that of the Wissenschafstlehre nova methodo, as one can see, for example, as regards the role played by the pure ego as the principle of philosophy. This means that one should rather proceed by directly comparing Kant's and Fichte's argument and look for agreements and disagreements, which is what Hanewald effectively does. For example, while for Kant the unity of manifold representation must precede the identical serf-reference of identity, for Fichte the contrary is the case, namely, that identical self-reference is the presupposition of all synthesis. Besides, Fichte explores other forms of serf-referential ego, from which he deduces among others the relation of subjects and accidents. In this case Kant cannot obviously be counted among Fichte's sources, because for Kant the category of substance is tied up with what is permanent in the flux of the accidents, which is something that finds expression in the schema of the permanence of time. Among the merits of Hanewald's book is that it shows that the role played by the intellectual intuition in the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo marks a significant development from the first Wissenschaftslehre and at the same time a significant distance from Kant's theoretical philosophy.--Riccardo Pozzo, The University of Verona.

联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有