Howard-Snyder, Daniel, and Paul K. Moser. Divine Hiddenness: New Essays.
Bradley, James
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. ix + 242 pp. Cloth,
$60.00; paper, $22.00--This is an interesting, sophisticated collection
of philosophical essays on the hiddenness of God, in the specific sense
that God (if such there be) has not made his existence sufficiently
clear. The question addressed is whether or not such hiddenness is
compatible with the existence of a creator God. The incompatibility
thesis is argued by J. L. Schellenberg in his well-known work, Divine
Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993). He
claims there that if there were a perfectly loving creator God, such a
God would ensure that there are no inculpable nonbelievers. As there
are, no such God exists. In the present collection, Schellenberg
contributes "What the Hiddenness of God Reveals: A Collaborative
Discussion," which is a complex, subtle reconsideration of the
issues in dialogue form that introduces a notion of the
"religions" (p. 61) that is wider and looser than that
connected with theism. By contrast, all the other contributors defend
some form of the compatibility thesis against Schellenberg. The basic
outlines of the debate are laid out in the excellent Introduction by the
editors, and the ensuing essays consider a number of fundamental issues.
First, there are the epistemic questions connected with divine
hiddenness. In "Seeking but not Believing: Confessions of a
Practicing Agnostic," Paul Draper defends an agnosticism that
appears to be religious in the large sense of Schellenberg and argues
that there is an equal balance of epistemic probabilities on the side of
theism and atheism. Jonathan L. Kvanvig's "Divine Hiddenness:
What is the Problem?" maintains that the hiddenness of God adds
nothing to the epistemic difficulties presented by the larger problem of
evil. On the other side, Peter Van Inwagen's "What is the
Problem of the Hiddenness of God?" holds that divine hiddenness
presents quite distinct problems that have to be considered in their own
right. Either way, William J. Wainwright and Michael J. Murray argue
that the epistemic difficulties of divine hiddenness can be met by
considerations arising out of the nature of freedom. In his "Deus
Absconditus," Murray defends the compatibility thesis by way of a
carefully considered soul-making theodicy. Wainwright's essay on
"Jonathan Edwards and the Hiddenness of God" mobilizes
Edwards's account of the evidences of God and significantly revises
Edwards's harsh view of nonbelievers on the basis of the value of
human freedom.
Second, there is the question as to whether or not divine
hiddenness should primarily be treated as an epistemic issue. Laura L.
Garcia's "St. John of the Cross and the Necessity of Divine
Hiddenness' argues that human relations to God are not primarily
cognitive but experiential. Paul K. Moser takes a similar view, and in a
powerful essay on "Cognitive Idolatry and Divine Hiding" he
defends a "cognitively robust theism" (p. 125) in which human
relations to God are understood to be primarily a matter of moral
transformation. In a subtly different vein, M. Jamie Ferreira's
"A Kierkegaardian View of Divine Hiddenness" employs Aquinas
and Kierkegaard to argue both that the absolute difference of God
implies divine hiddenness and that, as John Henry Newman held, there are
no probabilistic and cumulative degrees of genuine faith in such a God.
Nicholas Wolterstorff's striking account of "The Silence of
the God Who Speaks" presses that point: he rejects all theodicies
and free will defenses as inadequate to the tragedy of evil and holds
faith alone to be the proper response to God's silence.
Third, it is noteworthy that all the contributors, except Jacob
Joshua Ross in his "The Hiddenness of God: A Puzzle or a Real
Problem?", conduct their discussions on the basis of a generally
recognizable yet unspecified traditional account of the creator God as
omnipotent, loving, personal, and so on. Ross alone among the
contributors raises the question as to whether or not the issue of
divine hiddenness, among others, requires a revised conception of the
creator God. Here he puts his finger on the weakness of much philosophy
of religion, particularly as conducted in the analytical tradition:
because the history of theology as much as that of philosophy is largely
ignored, traditional notions are taken as ahistorical givens. The result
is that there is little readiness actually to do philosophical theology
and to undertake a fundamental metaphysical re-examination of concepts
as ancient and complex as those of omnipotence, love, personality, and
their relation. Perhaps the real achievement and significance of this
fine collection is that the divisions and debates among its contributors
point down that road--which is, after all, the road taken by
philosophers like C. S. Peirce (whose concept of "vagueness"
should not be overlooked in the present context), as well as theologians
like Wolfhart Pannenberg and James P. Mackey.--James Bradley, Memorial
University of Newfoundland.