Abbey, Ruth. Charles Taylor.
Simpson, Peter
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001. vi + 250 pp. Cloth,
$55.00; paper $16.95--To write a book summarizing and explaining the
thought of a wide-ranging and complex philosopher is a hard task, and
even more so when the philosopher in question is still writing. Still,
it is usually a worthy and often a necessary task. That is certainly so
in this case. Charles Taylor is one of the few contemporary philosophers
both to be at the forefront of a major philosophical movement (that of
communitarianism) and to have comfortably and ably straddled the great
divide between analytic and continental philosophy. He is also a
philosopher who has had, and continues to have, a significant impact in
the difficult and very different world of active politics, namely in his
native Quebec.
Ruth Abbey brings to this worthy and necessary task both wide
knowledge and eager enthusiasm. She is a sympathetic, though not
uncritical, exponent of her subject. She carefully and informatively
takes us through the several moments that she singles out of
Taylor's thought. She admits that there is something a bit
artificial about this. Taylor's thought is more of a continuum than
a whole of clearly articulated parts. To divide the continuum into
discrete moments discretely examined runs the risk of distorting that
thought. There is, however, no alternative. Perhaps indeed the fault is
in the thinker that his thought is not easily articulated, and perhaps
it is a service to the thinker for another to do the articulating for
him. If so, then Taylor could hardly ask for a more sympathetic
articulator than Abbey.
She divides her book into five main chapters: (1) "Explaining
Morality"; (2) "Interpreting Selfhood'; (3)
"Theorizing Politics"; (4) "Understanding
Knowledge"; (5) "Conclusion: Sources of Secularity." She
adds that the absence of a chapter on Taylor on language is in part an
indication of the general problem: Taylor's views on language are
discussed in every chapter because of the difficulty of separating them
out from his views on other matters. It would have perhaps been
interesting trying the same approach with the other themes that Abbey
does pick out, but then it would have been hard to find a principle of
organization other than that of chronology (which has its own problems).
Abbey's approach is probably as good as one can expect with a
subject like Taylor.
But let us turn now to the content of the book. Here our interest
is in seeing how well Abbey has introduced her readers into her
subject's thought and enabled them to see the good and the bad. One
should note, therefore, at the outset that Abbey has been expressly
serf-denying in avoiding criticism except in the notes and in occasional
concluding remarks at the end of chapters. This seems the right approach
to take given her overall aim, but it also has the additional advantage
of allowing the reader freely to form his own judgments as he goes
along. Speaking for myself, then, as such a reader, I found my ideas
about Taylor (as about others in his rough communitarian line of
thinking, as MacIntyre) more or less confirmed. Taylor is good in
criticism of others' views and in his more concrete or immediately
practical thinking (as on politics and secularity), but unconvincing in
his grand historical overviews of human thought. I personally think that
such overviews are impossible to achieve and anyway not necessary for
understanding. Certainly the particular views of particular others can
be helpful in our own search for truth, but that is all we need concern
ourselves with. Whether there is also some sort of story to tell about
past thought, or several stories, is matter for diversion perhaps but
not a key to understanding the questions at issue.
I also found myself confirmed in my views that historicist and
fallibilist approaches to knowledge, such as we also find in MacIntyre,
and which Taylor picks up in part from Gadamer, are incoherent. What is
interesting about such ideas is not whether they are true--they are
not--but why so many otherwise clever thinkers are attracted to them.
The best answer I have so far come up with--and Abbey's discussion
of Taylor has only confirmed me in this--is that it is the natural place
to go in reaction to the false objectivism or ahistoricism of much
analytic philosophy. Human thought necessarily begins in time and
proceeds through time and is inevitably colored thereby. Yet it need not
stay bound by time or it need not end in time: it can transcend time and
reach the eternal. The best analogy I know of this is Plato's cave.
We all necessarily start in some cave or other--the cave of our
particular time and place and culture--but there is a path from every
cave to the universal and eternal truth outside (and above all to the
truth about caves). We cannot, unlike some strains in analytic
philosophy, ignore the historicity of our present context (and above all
the historicity of analytic philosophy). However, we should not think,
unlike strains in continental philosophy, that we can never transcend
historicity to eternal truth.
Without making this anywhere her theme, Abbey, in her careful and
faithful presentation of the many parts and phases of Taylor's
thought, helps us to see it as the chief lesson we can learn from
Taylor. For that reason, as for the several others already briefly
noted, we have much reason to be grateful to her for this book.--Peter
Simpson, City University of New York.