Individuals, universals, and capacity.
Wood, Robert E.
SENSING PRESENTS TO US INDIVIDUALS. But, though directing us
practically, the way it presents them misleads us systematically about
the nature of the individuals with which we have our practical dealings
and poses serious questions about the status of the universals we use to
describe them. We are all quite aware of the consequences in the
practical order of unsettling the question of universals. The notion of
capacity can overcome the problems involved.
What is it to be an individual thing? If we attend to the immediate
evidence provided by seeing and touching, there are five characteristics
involved. To be an individual is to be (1) actual, (2) immediately
present, (3) spatially circumscribed, (4) in external causal relations
with other such actual, spatially circumscribed individuals, and (5)
utterly other than the universals used to describe it. Descriptive
universals are mental constructions conventionally tagged by naming.
Seeing and touching, as individual acts of individual organisms produced
by causal connections with other individuals, present us with such
individuals. Furthermore, looking at the conditions for seeing gives us
a physical-physiological causal account of light propagation and
electrical stimulation culminating inside the head of the seer wherein
the individual privacy of visual awareness occurs. All the evidence
displays the general features of individuals as actual, immediately
present, spatially circumscribed, in causal interaction with other such
individuals, and utterly other than the problematic universals used to
describe them. Thus a common empiricist-nominalist account. (1)
What I intend to do is to reflect upon the capacities in things,
most centrally the capacities for seeing and for being seen which
together provide the overriding evidence as to the nature of
individuals. In so doing, I will present another and, I would claim,
fuller account of individuals, which takes into consideration the
conditions for the possibility of the account given above and generated
out of the evidence provided by seeing. The whole field of sensory
givenness is comprised of features both actual and individual, with not
a crack of capacity or universality showing. As Sartre put it, the realm
of the immediately given is full, like an egg. (2) It is upon the
individuality and actuality of the sensorily given that empiricist nominalism bases itself.
I will proceed in two stages. First I will attend to the conditions
for the possibility of seeing, which presents us with our typical
evidential starting point. In so doing, I will attempt to secure the
general notion advanced in Plato's Sophist that the definition of
being is the capacity of acting and being acted upon. (3) In the second
part I will attend to the capacities involved in giving an account,
specifically the capacity for seeing and for intellection. In the first
part I proceed downward, so to speak, to a most general notion; in the
second part I proceed upward to the specific capacity for "general
notions."
I
Begin with the seeing capacity. Though an individual feature of an
individual organism, it is not simply individual in the way a seen
object presents itself. It is a universal orientation correlative to the
kind of objects which it requires. It is oriented a priori toward all
those individuals that could actualize it, wherever and whenever they
might appear. So if there is the capacity for seeing, there are not
simply individuals, but, of necessity, the kinds of individuals in the
environment that correspond to it, namely colored objects. (4)
Visibility is spelled out in color, necessarily coexistent with
extension and correlated with both light and distance from the seer as
co-given eidetic features verified every time we open our eyes and look.
Thus we have universality, not simply in some abstract construction of
the intellect, but in both the universality of the orientation of the
capacity for seeing and in the existence of specific kinds of objects,
instances of universals--in this case color and its eidetic
accompaniments--in the environment. This explains Aristotle's
notion that through sense the human soul is, in a way, all things
sensible. (5) The way is that of an a priori orientation of openness
toward the kinds of objects proper to each sense. The abstract
universality of the kind is correlative to the concrete universality of
the capacity. So in the notion of the concrete universality of an
individual capacity, the distinction and opposition between the
individual and universal is aufgehoben, canceled as absolute opposition
and yet preserved and synthesized in fact. (6)
What Berkeley would call "the abstract idea" of color is
not manufactured by the mind; (7) it is given within the fundamental
character of visual capacity even qua individual; it is the a priori
horizon of the power. (8) However, it is not given in sensation but only
through it by way of reflection. It is verified every time we open our
eyes and see. Though we begin with individual seen objects, through
reflection upon experience over time our thinking catches up with the
horizon within which they all operate: the single concrete universal
capacity for seeing correlates to color as the overarching genus aimed
at by the capacity.
There is thus, in the case of the seer-seen relation, a duality on
both sides of the subject-object relation. On the side of the object,
there is the seen individual as instance of the genus color. On the side
of the subject, in the act of seeing there is individual activation of
the generic orientation of the capacity. In between the two poles on the
side of the object we learn to discriminate species and develop
theories, such as that of the primary colors red, blue, and yellow, of
which the other colors are combinations. What this indicates is that in
order to function as seen objects, things have to come in determinate kinds--not yet functional wholes, but what we might call epistemic correlates. Sensory objects, what Aristotle calls "proper
sensibles," (9) are further differentiated into kinds corresponding
to different capacities of observation.
Now, in addition to its own concrete universality and in contrast
to its actual objects, the notion of capacity involves its own
nonactuality; it is a possibility of actualization. It is the features
of nonactuality and universality that cannot be apprehended by seeing or
by any other sensory act for sensory acts always involve manifest
individual actuality. (10) Before it is an actual act of seeing, seeing
is actually a capacity, a determinate feature of my own being at the
level of what Aristotle called first act, determining the kind of
process that a given individual organism is and providing its
fundamental dynamic capacities. The capacity of seeing is oriented
toward second act, toward being actualized by the actual presence of
individual visual objects. (11) When it is actualized it displays
separate, spatially circumscribed, always actual, causally interactive,
individual visual objects. Such an image is not adequate to the seeing
capacity, nor indeed to the full reality of the things seen which have
their own capacities, among them the capacity of being seen. This
involves their subsumption under the generic notion correlative to the
capacity. That we might see them, things have each their own capacity of
being seen, which entails their orientation to being seen not just by
this or that factual seer but by any seer, by the kind of being we call
a seer, in all those situations where they might be seen, that is, once
again, any time and any place the conditions for being seen are met. The
passive capacity for being seen is as universal as is the active
capacity for seeing.
Let us take a further step. As the evidence of seeing shows, seeing
itself cannot take place without the appropriate instrumental complex of
eyeballs, optic nerve, and cortical locus in coherent functional
relation not only with each other but also with the illumined
environment and the objects manifest through the capacity. Without the
instruments there is no activation of the capacities. Just as, if there
is no saw made out of hard material, there is no sawing, no matter what
skill the carpenter might possess, so, if there are no eyeballs attached
to the optic nerve and grounded in the back of the cortex, there is no
seeing. (12) The point upon which I want to focus here is that such
instruments (eyeballs, ears, hands) have to be grown and sustained by
regularly repeatable and repeated unconscious noncognitive processes,
activating peculiar capacities in the complex functional totality we
call an organism or system of organs. One of the aims of the need for
food is to grow the organs that would allow us, in a natural feedback
loop, to see the food which sustains us.
The organism is a system, a complex interrelation of factors such
that the absence of one factor could destroy the whole. Once one
understands the systematicity involved in organic existence, one sees
that the observations we make of it are not "loose and
separate," as Hume would have it, and that certain generalizations
we make about this organic necessity do not admit of falsification. (13)
Cut off a head of an animal or crush its heart, and the whole organism
necessarily ceases to function. (14) One could not speak of
falsifiability here: there is systematic, universal necessity that
grounds whatever verification we make through seeing. This would ground
a Popperian view of science, as the sum total of those disciplines
subject to falsifiability, in the structural features of experience
which are not so subject because they are always verified in wakeful
experience. (15)
A self-developing and self-sustaining organic system requires
peculiar capacities correlative to other kinds of things in the
environment, namely the capacities for energy extraction and processing.
Once again, qua capacities, they are concrete universals requiring
specific kinds of things in the environment, namely the kinds that can
nourish the given organism. Carnivores require other animals, herbivores
plant life, and plants inanimate features of the environment, specific
kinds of things such as sunlight, earth, and water. But certain kinds of
animals, certain kinds of plants, and certain kinds of elements are
inimical to certain kinds of organisms. That is, each organism requires
for its sustenance not just other individuals but the kinds of
individuals correspondent to its capacities, just as it is inimical to
those kinds that would thwart its development. The sense capacities
present kinds of aspects of things; the nutritive capacity requires
kinds of things displayed through the sensing capacities.
Amidst all the contemporary talk about the rejection of so-called
Platonism which believes in essences, one has to eat, and, indeed, to
eat the kinds of things that are nourishing. (Of course, as one does not
see color but specific individual instances of color, one does not eat
the kinds but only the individuals that instance the kinds.) The
evidence for that is irrefutable evidence--irrefutable under penalty of
there being no one around to refute or prove or indicate unless that
evidence is recognized and lived by. The thinker has thus first of all
to be an eater; but to be such involves being oriented, via specific
kinds of capacities, toward specific kinds of presentations, namely
those that satisfy the needs of the organism. An animal has to be able
to recognize features which involve the distinction between the edible
and the inedible, the beneficial and the harmful, under penalty of
organic dissolution. The theorist who disallows the eidetic continues to
exist by reason of being able to recognize instances of the eidetic. One
might say, as a variation on a Feuerbachian theme: Primum edere, deinde
philosophari. First eat, then think about it--or, unless you eat first,
you won't be around to think about it. But only specific kinds of
things in the environment can contribute to that.
A further feature of organisms, besides their self-developing,
self-sustaining capacities, is their capacity for reproduction. A seeing
organism cannot be unless it has been generated by another such organism
of the same kind as itself and unless it, under normal conditions, has
the same capacity for reproduction in itself. Qua capacity, once again,
it requires a specific kind of individual object in the environment,
namely a mate of its own species, with which it must perform a specific
kind of operation in a specific kind of location (a pretty lame
description of sex). The kind is determined, at the level of the
species, by the same cluster of capacities in each mate and, at the
level of the individual organism, by peculiar gender capacities
correlative to the opposite sex.
Organisms then necessarily come in kinds, and for them to flourish
as a species, they require specific kinds of things in the environment:
not only nourishing kinds but mating kinds of their own species. To be
for an organism is to have been produced by an organism of the same kind
and to be able to reproduce another of its kind. As Hegel, and before
him Aristotle, noted, reproductive capacity is the claim of the concrete
universality of the species upon the individual organism. (16) Organisms
thus necessarily come in kinds, for that is the only way they can come
into being. So not only are there necessarily kinds of individuals
correspondent with our faculties, but, to be able to see and act in
relation to such things, we ourselves, as organisms, must be generated
by one of our own kind and thus belong to a species. Visual observation
requires species, both the species of the visual observer and the
correlative sustaining species in the environment.
What I have been attempting to do up to this point is to supplement
the account that seeing gives of the properties of individuals, namely,
that they are actual, immediately present, spatially circumscribed, in
causal interaction with other such individuals, and set in contrast to
the universals used to describe them. The central insight is this:
capacity involves nonactual universality and correspondent kinds in the
environment. The seeing capacity that provides the initial evidence
requires its own organs and the organ-system that sustains it. Each
capacity of that system has its correspondent kinds of individuals in
the environment. These kinds, in turn, require other kinds in their
environments to sustain them, all the way down to the specific kinds of
nonliving elements required for specific kinds of plant life. The kinds
are presented in individuals as functional wholes. Each must be of the
kind that can act and be acted upon in such a way as to sustain the food
chain in the kinds that lead up to the seeing organism. As a function
within such perceiving organisms, seeing ultimately requires the
reproductive capacity in its parents that brought its organic base into
being, so that living things in general must come in kinds. So
universality is not merely a construction of the mind; it is ingredient
in the capacities of things and in the corespondent kinds of things in
the environment. It is ingredient in the nature of organic being as
reproductive. It is involved in the conditions for the possibility of
seeing, which provides us with our initial evidence as to the nature of
individuals. Seeing requires not only seeable objects but integration
within a supportive organic system and into an interrelated systematic
hierarchy of nourishing kinds as its overarching environment.
The world we inhabit and observe is a world of the encompassing
interrelation of things with specific capacities of acting and being
acted upon. Each capacity as a universal orientation anticipates space
and time as the whole within which it can operate, for its capacities
can be activated at any time and any place the conditions for its
operation are met. Observed actuality and the actuality of observation
both arise out of the specific capacities, the universal orientations of
the passively observed and actively observing individuals.
Peculiar clusters of capacities form differing kinds of
individuals: for example, the kinds that are gathered systematically in
the Periodic Table of Elements or the kinds listed in the taxonomic
schemes of organic types. None of them comes loose and separates, but
rather they are integrated into the systematic interrelation of
inorganic and organic types that constitutes the cosmos within which we
exist. Any entity is the locus of concrete universal capacities that
determine what kind that entity is. So we can go beyond conscious
activity, sensory or intellectual, to consider any real entity under the
same rubric, following the Stranger's suggestion in Plato's
Sophist that the definition of being is the capacity of acting and being
acted upon. Any entity--not just one having cognitive capacities--is not
simply spatially circumscribed but involves, through its active and
passive capacities, a priori relations to the cosmic whole within which
it exists. Hence we see the place for Plato's eidetic realm, the
so-called separate realm of the Forms, not in some separate heaven of
abstract universals but in what Martin Buber has called "the earth
of our bodily meetings." (17)
This moves in the direction of Leibniz who claimed that the least
thing has to have inscribed within itself its compossibility with the
entire actual universe within which it exists. (18) But I do not go
quite as far as Leibniz because my observations concern only the
possible causal interactions. Such interactions are precluded by
Leibniz's notion of the windowless character of the monads.
Further, his monads would include all relations, such as the changing
spatial relations between a given entity and the entire universe, and
would precontain its whole actual future, not simply the possibilities
of causal interaction in which I am interested here.
Now we move to our second part: an examination of the peculiar
capacities involved in providing evidence and giving an account.
II
If sense data positivism overlooks the notion of capacity and thus
systematically misleads us regarding the nature of individuality in
general, it also systematically misleads us regarding the nature of the
specific kinds of capacities involved in observation. Now I want to
examine the capacity of seeing and to attend to another feature of
individuals derived from seeing: their apparent spatially circumscribed
character. (19) Let us look again at the account of seeing given by
looking. Light sources reflect off of visible objects, pass through the
pupils of the eyes and through the lenses that invert on the retina the
images carried by light, stimulating electrical movement in the rods and
cones of the retina and thus activating the optic nerve which carries
the electric impulses to the visual center in the back of the brain
where seeing of a noninverted image is said to occur. Seeing then is
viewed as an intraorganic event. (20) What else could it be, since seen
objects are quite evidently spatially circumscribed, and when one
observes someone looking, spatial circumscription characterizes that
looker? However, one could not give that account unless each of the
items involved were seen precisely outside the organism of the observer.
But that means that seeing organisms are not serf-contained in the
manner that seeing sees them. Seeing transcends the self-enclosed
character of the seen organism. The visually descriptive account
explains the necessary conditions for seeing, but it does not yet touch
the nature of seeing itself. Seeing is the necessarily presupposed
framework within which the seeable appears and which cannot itself
appear within that framework because it exceeds it. Seeing transcends
the spatial circumscription, the apparent self-containment of the
visually appearing organism. Seeing therefore, though grounded here
inside my organism, involves a certain sui generis mode of being there,
outside my organism. Sense data positivism follows the descriptive
plenitude of the seen object and misses the essential expressivity of
the look that indicates a kind of absence from that plenitude in the
direction of the manifest object. So when we see something that is
seeing, we see an actual, immediately present set of moving color
patterns belonging to a spatially circumscribed organism. But that
organism's seeing is a kind of absence from the plenitude of
immediate sensory presence, an absence in the direction of the seen
object. When a cat watches a rat, the awareness of the cat is, in a real
sense, not simply in the cat; it is with the rat. (21) Here opens up the
realm of the interior dimensions of awareness as ways of being with what
is exterior. (22)
Further, seeing not only involves the functional correlation of its
specific organ system and the supportive nutritional processes, it also
requires a functional coherence at the level of sensing itself, a
coherence in the field of awareness between its present and past
experiences and between the deliverances, past and present, of other
sensory capacities in relation to the seen object. The awareness of the
animal must be able to recognize the differing presentations of each of
the sensory capacities and is thus other than such capacities. In order
to recognize, it must transcend the present object given through one of
the senses by retaining in the present the past of other experiences
from the operative sense and also from other senses. (23) Sensory
coherence thus manifests not simply sensory objects but coherently
functioning things, some of which are able to see.
The things presented are of the kinds that could serve the
appetites for nourishment and mating by the seeing organism. Driven by
need, seeing is instrumental to the display of just those kinds of
things. Hence manifestation occurs in terms of action. Action is
dictated by those needs which lead me to seek or to avoid specific types
of things appearing in the field of the senses. Seeing is correlated not
only with other externally oriented sensations but with appetite, for
seeing serves need. (24) In this function it is necessarily correlated
with tactility, for the end of seeing for the organic being is to take
in food and to come in contact with mate and offspring. (25)
Furthermore, since seeing occurs in the animal in function of
organic need rising to awareness as desire, what we see in the seeing
organism expresses not only an absence from the plenitude of sensory
presence in the direction of the presently seen object of the
animal's awareness; what we see also expresses an absence in the
direction of the future of the satisfaction of the animal's desire.
The look of the other is not simply sensorily there, fully present; but
the full presence expresses the inner orientation of the animal. The
future component involved in desire means that in observing the look of
an animal, what we observe is a kind of absence from the full plenitude
of sensory presence, intending both the immediate presence of things in
the environment outside the observing organism and the future
fulfillment of its desires. (26) It exists beyond the punctual now in
the living now of what Husserl called retentions and protensions. (27)
Functioning as an optometrist, one systematically looks away from
the patient's looking as a kind of absence expressed in the overall
behavioral comportment and centered in the look. The optometrist zeros
in on the eyeball mechanism, all of whose features can be made visibly
present to him. But, of course, the aim of optometry is to allow the
seer to look away in the direction of the seen and in function of its
goals. And as a matter of fact, optometrists shift their own seeing
attention back and forth from the eyeball mechanism to the expressivity
of the total facial gestalt when they speak to their patients before,
during, and after the examination. They themselves are guided in their
examination by how the patient responds when asked how the E-chart
appears as different lenses are interposed between the eyeballs of the
patient and the chart. Themselves seeing, optometrists are concerned
with aiding the act of seeing in their patients; but what is focal for
them is the observable plenitude of the eyeball mechanism. The
optometrist presents in miniature what observational science tends to
follow in toto. Such science thereby tends to fall into what I have
called the empiriomorphic fallacy, considering all things in the form
presented by a sensorily observable object. (28)
Let us come back again to the situation of seeing. I look, and what
I see is a smooth, placid desk, separated from my eyes by empty space.
But looking in function of the kind of thinking that produces
instrumentation presents a different picture. The empty space is full of
dust particles, sound waves, air molecules, photons, TV and radio
waves--indeed, with irradiations across the whole electromagnetic
spectrum. The smooth surface of the podium is only smooth relative to
the rather crude sensors in my fingers, and the placidity conceals the
fact that it is composed of elementary particles as pulsating centers of
energy irradiating their light spectra. Seeing as an organic function
carves out a space of appearance relative to the needs of the organism.
Not seeing everything is the condition for seeing at all. And the seen
presents itself in a way in which it is not. Seeing creates a kind of
illusion, a third thing nonexistent apart from organism and object, a
new emergent in the world of physical processes and capacities. I take
this to be what Aristotle means when he says that "the sensible in
act is the sense in act." (29) Aristotle further made what many
realists would take as a startling claim, namely that the senses are
mostly mistaken. (30) One could easily verify that through vision which
necessarily presents us with perspectival distortions. The
quasi-illusion is correlative to the spatial point of view that
establishes the perspective. The sun looks like a rather small disk;
railroad tracks look like they join in the distance; a cube appears
larger in the face it presents to us than in its other faces, and the
top and bottom edges of its sides do not appear parallel to each other.
Furthermore, the horizon within which perspectival color presentations
occur is simply not there without a seer. Like a psychic hoopskirt, it
moves when the seeing organism moves. Color, perspective, and horizon do
not exist apart from perceivers; but that does not make them merely
subjective. The horizon, the perspective, and the color are neither
wholly objective as naive realism would have it nor wholly subjective as
modern accounts from Galileo to Kant would have it. Color, perspective,
and horizon appear in a sui generis subject-object relation, a relation
of manifestation between the organism and environmental objects,
precisely an appearance of the reality of environmental objects but not
a presentation of the full reality of those things. Indeed, because of
the organic dependency of the appearance, we could say that things
appear in a way they are not apart from the appearance. In the
Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition, the use of the language of phantasmata
(from phainomai, "I appear") and of species (from specio,
"I behold") for aspects of perceptual process underscores the
peculiarity of the relation of appearance. (31)
However, the appearance, though relative to the organic conditions
of perception, nonetheless does not present us with merely apparent
food, mate, and enemies. (32) Because it occurs in function of organic
need, the appearance allows us to identify the kinds of things that can
support or thwart the immanent ends of my organic being. Nietzsche said
that the senses lie but that the lie is necessary for life. (33) So the
world of immediate sensory presentation is an organ-dependent
construction, stably relating us to things in the environment. A realism
confined to such an appearance is what I would call, following Owen
Barfield, a "dashboard realism" which conceals as much as it
reveals and misleads speculatively as much as it leads pragmatically.
(34) Hegel calls it "the hard rind" of the everyday world
through which speculative thought must break in order to arrive at the
encompassing truth. (35) That phenomenal surface teaches us input and
output correlations without any practical need for knowing what lies
under the hood and behind the dashboard of sensory observation. But to
know that involves a move which situates the functional circle of
appearance within the wider circle of full being.
As seeing is taken up in scientific investigation, what appears
does so in function of another capacity, namely the capacity to uncover
capacity that we have come to call intellect. What makes the
intellectual capacity different from the sensory capacity is its
inprinciple transcendence, not simply of the supposed self-enclosure of
the sensing organism such as occurs in seeing, but a transcendence of
the realm of sensory appearance itself even while dealing with the
sensory. Intellect is initially discriminated from sensation in that
sensing always presents individuals whereas what we have come to call
intellect grasps the universals. (36) The grasp of capacity, of
universality, and of intellect emerge together. However, this initial
discrimination is only preliminary.
The apprehension of the universal is founded upon a more primordial
orientation displayed in the judgment that something is the case. The
first thing that occurs to an intellectual being is the notion of being:
we understand that something presented in sensation is; it stands
outside of nothing and shares this feature in common with anything we
can encounter or infer. (37) What we call intellect is the capacity for
apprehending the notion of being. Involving absolutely everything that
is, it also involves everything about everything. Outside being there is
nothing at all. It is this orientation toward the fullness of each being
that allows us to recognize the merely surface character of sensory
deliverances. In a way different from that of sensory capacity, through
its intellectual capacity the human soul is all things by anticipating
within its horizon of awareness absolutely everything. (38) Though
sensation is, in a way, all things sensible, the way is unconscious and
is limited by nature to being relative to organic need. It is further
limited to what is actual. Sensation is all things sensible at the level
of the capacity, not of the act; at the level of the act it is only of
the actual and not of capacities. But in the case of intellect the whole
of being is implicitly, horizontally, prereflectively manifest in such a
way that humans can grasp capacities as such and thus also their
correlated universal objects. (39) Thus, included within being is not
only each and every individual in its fullness but also the universality
ingredient in the correlativity of capacities and kinds that are there
in, among, and as individuals. The whole of being involves the
interrelation of individual and universal, and intellectual capacity is
the locus of the display of that interrelation progressively unfolded as
reflection advances. (40)
Orientation toward the whole of being contains within itself
orientation toward the whole of space and time. Space and time are
given, not as abstract concepts, but as encompassing, though empty,
wholes that are progressively filled in by experience and inquiry. (41)
This I would claim is the basis for the ability to grasp the universal
orientations in things and the kinds that they entail, for the
orientations are toward all those features of the kinds of individuals
that could activate the capacities, wherever in space and whenever in
time they might be found. It is intellectual capacity that allows us to
grasp the indeterminate repeatability of the acts and objects of the
capacities.
The recognition of space and time as encompassing wholes also makes
possible deliberate attempts not only to recall but to reconstruct the
past which we never experienced through its traces in the present. It
makes possible a deliberate anticipation of the future and thus the
projection of goals that we might deliberately pursue. In this case we
would introduce goals not given immediately with the appetites naturally
correlative with the sensory deliverances. One of those goals might be
the apprehension of the nonsensorily given features of individuals given
in sensation.
The task for theoretical thought set up by our bipolar structure of
immersion in sensory immediacy and reference to the cosmic whole spills
over into the task for practical thought. Orientation toward being as
the fullness pries us loose mentally from what is immediately given,
even and especially the immediate givenness of our own motivational
sources. This creates a gap in the causal universe which seeing presents
as seamless. (42) Serf-determining freedom stands over against the
causal networks within which it is embedded as the materials for its own
operation. (43) Freedom is the ability to specify which of the concrete
possibilities will be activated among those formed by the conjunction of
concrete capacities in the interrelation between the individual person
and its environment.
The distance and freedom of intellect allows us to make our
motivational sources explicit and to assess them in terms of a growing
awareness of the fuller context of the presuppositions and consequences
of all our actions. The theoretical task of uncovering the fuller
context of our existence is itself one of the practices; in fact it is
perhaps the distinctive practice in which we engage as humans. It
uncovers the universal orientations toward kinds involved in the
existence of the least entity in the cosmos. Its theoria is the
serf-presence of the cosmic whole, the place where the whole comes to
self-awareness. (44)
This orientation toward full being through partial appearance sets
the task for the history of inquiry, working in one direction, with more
and more sensorily given data uncovered by following frameworks of
explanation that are methodologically self-corrective as they play in
relation to the expansion of our hold upon the data. (45) That is the
direction of empirical science. Grounded in the permanent verifiability
of the eidetic constants of the organic life-world, empirical science
advances into the continually deferred full presence of the things that
appear within that life-world. But this has to be seen, in another
direction, always in relation to the self-presence of the knower, so
that a view of the cosmos is required which includes that self-presence.
Such self-presence is not an alien intruder into a world of material
particulars, but is the locus of the manifestation of the universals,
concrete and abstract, ingredient in encountered and encountering
individuals.
Theories present different possible interweavings of the
interpretive systems of sameness and difference by which we attempt to
situate the permanently given organic life-world within the larger,
sought-for totality whose presence, deferred, continually lures us on.
The system of differences and deferral of final presence is the dual
focus of Derridian differance. But deferral and difference are
nonetheless anchored in the permanent presence of universal orientations
and their correlative kinds. (46) Platonic essences still emerge for
reflective awareness within the earth of our bodily meetings. And the
horizon of being as lure for intellectual beings permanently grounds
that awareness. (47)
Return again to seeing. I am reading, as is the reader, from the
script in front of me. The page is an individual, flexible, smooth,
thin, white rectangle with neat rows of small, black forms of varying
but repetitive unit-shapes. But I take it up in function of an
antecedent communally constituted space of meaning conventionally tied
to these visible shapes. It is, in fact, the same communally constituted
space of meaning which you and I, reader and writer, share in common,
namely, the space of the English language. (48) Our conventional
language tags the eidetic constants given in each of our sensory fields
required for the flourishing of our organisms as it also tags the
distinctions supervenient upon that field discovered and/or invented by
those who preceded us. In taking up language we are already outside the
supposed privacy of our own individual consciousnesses. We each form our
own opinions in terms of occupying a position within that space. In
reading a paper before an audience, through the generation of sound by
my vocal chords one attempts to transfer the identical meanings tagged
by the visual patterns on this page to field of awareness of each of the
members of the audience. But the audience's coming to occupy the
positions the speaker is advancing within this communally constituted
space transcends the audile and visual patterns that convey the meanings
intended. Among other things, the vastly different audile and visual
patterns present identically the same meanings. The individuals that we
are as intelligent knowers far transcend what is immediately given in
the sensory field. Far from being serf-enclosed, we are only in our
interrelation with other humans in the nonsensorily accessible space of
meaning mediated by sensation. By the nature of our intellectual
capacity that space extends to the whole of what is. (49)
We might gesture here in the direction of Aquinas, who unpacked the
implications of the orientation of the mind toward encompassing being.
By reason of the unlimited character of the notion of being we come to
realize that the factual limitation of beings in experience requires a
cause that is not finite and whose infinity permanently sustains all
finitude. The upshot of this is that to be an individual is to be
perpetually rooted in the infinite encompassing power of unlimited
being. (50) But this has a double implication. As Josef Pieper puts it:
for Aquinas things are intelligible because they are created by
God's thought, but for that same reason they are unfathomable. (51)
Here we clearly join with Heidegger's reflections on the mystery of
Being. (52) Aquinas was thus no dashboard realist. He was fully aware
that "we do not know the essence of a single thing, not even
something as simple as a fly," (53) and "we know about God
that we do not know about God." (54)
But here we are a very long way from the actual, immediately
present, spatially circumscribed, universal-excluding, individual
character provided by seeing. Beginning always within the confining
horizon of sensory givenness, with the dashboard of our organically
functional world, and being always referred to the absolute encompassing
plenitude of being, we seek the fullness that is permanently deferred.
Such deferral involves not simply the absence of God from the sensory
plenitude; it also involves the absence of any encounterable other,
rooted in the creative activity of Ipsum Esse Subsistens. But the always
verifiable presence of the regularly given, sensorily present other
lulls us into ignoring that deferral. We fall into the empiriomorphic
fallacy or remain at the level of dashboard realism.
Dashboard realism and its empiricist opponents tend to make us
comfortable with the life-world and to forget the mystery upon which it
is rafted. The correspondence of our own native orientation toward the
fullness of being within the horizon of which we observe and judge what
presents itself within our sensory fields--the correspondence of that
with the existence of an infinite plenitude of being beyond all finite
presentations points us to an encompassing presence which is
simultaneously an infinite absence. It is the presence that makes
possible a fusion of that infinite reference with the sensory immediate
in the experience of theophany; it is the absence that inflames the
deepest desire of the creature who lives out of the anticipation of the
fullness of meaning. (55)
Looking back by way of conclusion: What does sensation tell us
about individuals? That they are actual, immediately present, spatially
circumscribed, in external causal relations with other such actual
individuals, and utterly other than the universals used to describe
them. Sensation so presents things in function of our organic needs. But
though sensing leads us pragmatically as organically needy beings, it
systematically misleads us speculatively. What it does not directly tell
us is that the things it presents are the loci of the concrete
universality of their capacities, correlated with the kinds of
capacities in kinds of things which can act and be acted upon by such
capacities. Universality is not a mere fabrication of the mind but is
found in the very individuality of our capacities, cognitive and
noncognitive, in their concrete universality, and in their necessary
correlates: kinds of things in the environment. Further, sensation does
not tell us of the peculiar capacity for transcendence of the observed
organism by sensing itself, which is able to manifest what is outside
the observing organism precisely as it is outside. It does not tell us
of its own organically relative constitutional power and hence of its
own in-principle limited mode of manifestation. Further, sensation does
not tell us of the peculiar intellectual capacity for the recognition of
those immanent universal structures, the necessary interrelation of
kinds and capacities. It does not tell us of the communally constituted
space of meaning indicated by those visual and audile constructions
emanating from intellectual capacity. And it does not tell us of the
permanent ontological anchorage of observer and observed in the
plenitude of being to which intellectual capacity is fundamentally
directed.
Nonetheless, sensing provides us with the permanent phenomenal
anchorage that sets in motion our reflective capacity. When we look in
function of that capacity, that is, when we look intelligently at the
sensorily appearing other, we see functioning wholes activating their
various capacities. We come to read their natures in the capacities
expressed in their behavior. When we look intelligently at the look of
an animal, we see the expression of its intent upon the things present
in their environment, anticipating the future fulfillment of biological
need. In looking at the signs on this page, one reads the traces of what
I hope has been intelligent activity. And in looking at an audience, the
speaker sees the expressive look of intelligence--some perhaps slightly
absent by the end of a long address, some perhaps critically reserved,
some more or less approving, but all more or less within the space of
meaning within which the speaker is operating. One reads further the
look of intelligent observation and detached appreciation and critique
coming to the present from the distance of orientation toward the
fullness of being. One reads the expression of an final absence from the
plenitude of sensory presence, away in the direction of the fullness of
being itself. Indeed, one might even come through seeing actually to
experience the least entity appearing within the field of vision as
theophany, as the manifestation of God. But all that is not only
because, like any animal with eyeballs, one can see, but because, like
any functional human being, one can interpret intelligently and
sensitively what seeing presents in the nonseeable space of meaning we
humans occupy together. (56)
(1) I am, of course, thinking of Locke, Berkeley, and especially
Hume, as well as, more recently, the members of the Vienna Circle and
their derivatives in thinkers like A. J. Ayer. See Locke's Essay
Concerning Human Understanding, bk. 3, ch. 3, [section] 11;
Berkeley's A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge,
Introduction, especially [subsection] 12-15; Hume's A Treatise of
Human Nature, bk. 1, pt. 1, sec. 6; Viktor Kraft's The Vienna
Circle, trans. A. Pap (New York: Philosophical Library, 1953); and
Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic (New York: Dover, 1946).
(2) Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. H. Barnes (New York:
Harper, 1965), lxvi.
(3) Sophist 247e.
(4) Hegel saw this clearly. See Hegel's Philosophy of Mind,
trans. W. Wallace and A. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971),
[section] 401, p. 77.
(5) See On the Soul (hereafter, "OS") 3.8.431b22:
"The soul is, in a way, all things." He goes on to say that it
is all things intelligible by way of intellect and all things sensible
by way of sense. The part on intellect we will treat below. For my own
general approach to Aristotle which lies behind much of this paper, see
chapter 8 of my A Path into Metaphysics: Phenomenological,
Hermeneutical, and Dialogical Studies (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1990), 155-76.
(6) The notion of Aufhebung is, of course, the central insight of
Hegel (see The Encyclopaedia Logic, [section] 96). In fact, the
separation between individual and universal exhibits in an especially
clear manner the way in which we typically employ the principle of
identity. Looking to the things themselves overcomes the one-sidedness
presented in sensed actuality. For Hegel, identity-in-difference is the
principle of Vernunft that overcomes the abstractness of the products of
Verstand (see The Encyclopaedia Logic, [section] 115).
(7) Berkeley, The Principles of Human Knowledge, Introduction,
[section] 8.
(8) On the notion of faculty as formal a priori see Karl Rahner,
Spirit in the World, trans. W. Dych (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968),
97.
(9) OS 2.6.418a7.
(10) OS 2.5.417624. Hett's Loeb translation omits the crucial
energeian in the line: "ton kath' hekaston he energeian
aistheysis." He translates, "actual sensation is of
particulars." It should read "of the particular and
actual." See Aristotle, On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath,
trans. W. Hett (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), 99. Did an
empiricist focus lead him to overlook this important observation?
(11) OS 2.1.
(12) OS 1.3.407b21.
(13) Again, this is directed against Hume's notion that all
our experiences are loose and unconnected. See his Enquiry Concerning
Human Understanding, ed. E. Steinberg (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1977),
7.2, p. 49. We could not have experience unless we as observers and as
organisms were "tight and connected" in very definite,
systematic ways.
(14) That is why Hume overcomes his skepticism when he gets out of
the way of a carriage which he knows could crush his skull.
(15) Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York:
Basic Books, 1959), 40-2.
(16) Hegel, Hegel's Philosophy of Nature, trans. M. Petty
(London: George Allen and Unwin, 1970), [subsection] 367-9, 3:172-6; OS
2.4.415b. Compare Symposium 207d, where Eros is described as the desire
of the mortal for the immortal.
(17) "Interrogation of Martin Buber," conducted by
Maurice Friedman in Philosophical Interrogations, ed. Beatrice and
Sydney Rome (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1964), 57.
(18) Monadology, [subsection] 56-7, p. 248; Principles of Nature
and Grace, [section] 12, p. 418. Both of these are in the collection by
R. Latta, Leibniz: The Monadology and Other Philosophical Writings
(London: Oxford University Press, 1951). The term
"compossible" comes from the Lettre a Bourquet cited in Latta,
64 n. 2. For a general approach to Leibniz see chapter 12 of my Path
into Metaphysics.
(19) For a systematic approach to the field of awareness as
permanent prolegomena to any larger philosophic project, see chapter 2
of Path into Metaphysics.
(20) This is a commonplace in the tradition that goes back to
Galileo and Descartes.
(21) See Michael Polanyi on the three logical levels involved in
understanding animal behavior in The Study of Man (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1959), 76.
(22) I have tried to follow the notion of interior dimensions so as
to suggest a seven-dimensional view of humanness in chapter 2 of Path
into Metaphysics by using the model provided by Edwin Abbott in his
novella Flatland (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1963).
(23) This was noted for the first time in Theaetetus 184d and
picked up in Arisotle's notion of the aisthesis koinone in OS
3.1.425a15.
(24) OS 2.2.413b24.
(25) Theaetetus 184e and following; OS 3.1.425a15. This, I would
claim, is why Aristotle in OS, ascending from organism to sensation to
intellection, concludes the book with the treatment of locomotion and
touch. See OS 3.9-13.
(26) Here we are basically following the direction indicated by
Aquinas (Summa theologiae I, q. 75) that in coming to know something
intellectually, we move from act to power to essence.
(27) Edmund Husserl, Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness,
trans. J. Churchill (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1964),
50-97.
(28) Path into Metaphysics, 36.
(29) OS 3.2.425b27. Aristotle claims that white and black have no
real existence apart from vision but they do have potential existence.
See also Metaphysics 4.5.1010b33.
(30) OS 3.3.427b4. Of course, regarding their proper objects, the
senses are not mistaken; that is, seeing directly presents color and not
sound (see OS 3.3.427b12). And there is functional correction through
changing perspectives and through correlation with touch.
(31) See OS 2.7.419a4 and 3.7.431b3 on language for sensation
connected with phainomai; see Aquinas, for example, Summa contra
gentiles II, c. 76, par. 10 on phantasms and species.
(32) This seems to me to refute at least one way of reading Kantian
phenomenalism. Because a thinker must first be an eater, though the way
in which the edible presents itself must satisfy the conditions of the
senser in order to appear, what appears is not merely phenomenal food
but real food--hence a kind of "refutation of idealism." See
"Refutation of Idealism," A226/B275 and "The Ground of
the Distinction of all Objects in general into Phenomena and
Noumena," B296/A236, in Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason,
trans. N. K. Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965).
(33) "On Truth and Lie in an Extramoral Sense," in The
Portable Nietzsche, ed. and trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Viking, 1954),
43-7.
(34) Saving the Appearances: An Essay in Idolatry (New York:
Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1957), 28-35. Barfield's expression is
actually "dashboard knowledge."
(35) Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T. Knox (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1975), 1:203-8.
(36) OS 3.5.417b22.
(37) "Id quod primum cadit in intellectu est ens." See
Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle, 4.2. Note that the use of
the dative precludes the coming into the intellect of the notion which
would be indicated by the accusative. Being is the first thing that
occurs within an intellect; it does not come into the intellect from
outside. It the a priori horizon of intellectual capacity. On the
features of the notion of being see Bernard Lonergan, Insight: An Essay
on Human Understanding (New York: Harper and Row, 1958), 348-74.
(38) This could be correlated with Aristotle's claim in
Nicomachean Ethics 4 that nous as intellectual intuition not only grasps
the first principles of being and noncontradiction but also the ultimate
particular (to eschaton). This would seem to entail that an intellectual
act could apprehend itself in its individuality. As Aquinas said, it is
not individuality but matter than hinders intelligibility so that an
intellectual being can grasp its own intellectual act. See my
"Aquinas and Heidegger. Personal Esse, Truth, and
Imagination," in Postmodernism and Christian Philosophy, ed. R.
Ciapolo (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of American Press, 1977),
227.
(39) I take this to be involved in Aquinas's claim that an
intellectual knower implicitly knows God. See Summa theologiae I, q. 2,
a. 1, ad 1.
(40) I have tried to work out the eidetic features that are
implicit in the recognition that something is the case in "Taking
the Universal Point of View: A Descriptive Approach," The Review of
Metaphysics 50, no. 4 (June 1997): 769-81.
(41) This is a basic insight of Immanual Kant, Critique of Pure
Reason, A23/B37-A36/B53.
(42) Though claiming that every experience is loose and separate,
Hume also claims that allegedly free human choice cannot escape the
necessity involved in the regularity found throughout experience (see
Enquiry 8.1, pp. 53-64) nor can divine choice intervene in the course of
natural necessity through miracles (see Enquiry 10.1, p. 76).
(43) Hegel makes much of this: it is the pivotal observation in his
Phenomenology of Spirit, [section] 337; it is basic to his Philosophy of
Spirit, [subsection] 469-82 and especially to his politics in Philosophy
of Right, [subsection] 4-29. Sartre is only repeating Hegel in his
distinction between the freedom of the pour soi and the determinism of
the en soi (see Being and Nothingness, lxii-lxvii and 73-9).
(44) I have tried to present the lines of an evolutionary cosmology
by following out the implications of the self-presence involved in the
notion of being in my "Being and Manifestness: Philosophy, Science,
and Poetry in an Evolutionary Worldview," International
Philosophical Quarterly 35, no. 4 (December 1995): 437-47. The analysis
extends the notion of capacity back into the anticipations of intellect
at the least level and requires a radical transformation of the
all-too-common notion of matter.
(45) It is here that Hume is correct: empirical science is ongoing,
expansive, and methodologically serf-corrective.
(46) See Jacques Derrida, "Differance," in Margins of
Philosophy, trans. A. Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982),
3-27.
(47) The core of these insights is in Plato's Sophist which
presents various networks of sameness and difference carving the
life-world in order to capture the sophist. The dialogue goes on to
indicate that such carving is guided by the overarching gene: being,
sameness and difference, motion and rest (see Sophist 254d). I have
tried to pick up on that in my "Self-Reflexivity in Plato's
Theaetetus: On the Lifeworld of a Platonic Dialogue," The Review of
Metaphysics 52, no. 4 (June 1999): 807-33. Derrida himself defends the
priority of the notion of being in his critique of Benveniste's
attempt to reduce ontology to Greek grammar in "The Supplement of
Copula: Philosophy Before Linguistics," in Margins of Philosophy,
176-205.
(48) This is one of the ways in which Socrates in the Theaetetus
shows the insufficiency of the identification of knowing with sensing.
See Theaetetus 163b.
(49) This is central to Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit:
Language gives expression to "the We that is I and the I that is
We." See Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1977), [section] 177, p. 110.
(50) Aquinas's famous "five ways" are, of course, in
Summa theologiae I, q. 3, a. 4; see also Summa contra gentiles II, c.
52.
(51) Josef Pieper, The Silence of St. Thomas, trans. J. Murray and
D. O'Connor (New York: Pantheon, 1957), 53-67.
(52) "On the Essence of Truth," in Martin Heidegger:
Basic Writings, ed. D. Krell (New York: Harper and Row, 1977), 133, and
"Memorial Address," in Discourse on Thinking, trans. J.
Anderson and E. Freund (New York: Harper and Row, 1966), 55.
(53) Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima, 1.1.15; Disputed
Questions on Spiritual Creatures, q. 11, ad 3; On Truth, q. 4, a. 1, ad
8.
(54) On the Power of God, q. 7, a. 5, ad 4.
(55) These insights are behind the studies I have recently
published, Placing Aesthetics: Reflections on the Philosophic Tradition
(Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1999). See especially the
concluding chapter.
(56) In its original form this paper was delivered as the annual
Aquinas Lecture at the Institute of Thomistic Studies in the University
of St. Thomas, Houston.
ROBERT E. WOOD
University of Dallas
Correspondence to: Department of Philosophy, University of Dallas,
Irving, TX 75062.