Craig, William Lane. The Tensed Theory of Time: A Critical Examination.
Copan, Paul
Synthese Library: Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and
Philosophy of Science, vol. 293. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
2000. x + 287 pp. Cloth, $123.00 -- William Lane Craig is Research
Professor of Philosophy at Talbot School of Theology (La Mirada,
California). Quentin Smith considers him "one of the leading
philosophers of time," and his impressive, exhaustive three volume
series on God, time, relativity, and eternity clearly demonstrates this.
As the first two volumes are devoted to the problem of time--examining
whether a dynamic/tensed (A-theory) or static/tenseless (B-theory) view
of time is correct--I review them back-to-back.
Section 1 of The Tensed Theory deals with "The Ineliminability
of Tense" (chapters 1-5) while section 2 addresses "Arguments
Against an A-Theory of Time" (chapters 6-7, which cover
McTaggart's Paradox and the Myth of Passage, respectively). Chapter
1 explores the philosophy of language and its relation to time (tense,
indexicals, and so forth). According to the A-theorist, tense is real in
a metaphysical sense, not simply a feature of language (B-theory).
Ordinary language usage genuinely and strikingly exhibits tense, and the
B-theorist must somehow show that the tensed view of time (A-theory)
must be self-contradictory and therefore false (p. 21); in the absence
of such a proof, the best the B-theorist can do is show that tense is
superfluous. Yet a tensed view of time ought to be accepted as true
(that is, corresponding to the way the world is), as tensed sentences
cannot be reduced to tenseless propositions without loss of meaning.
Chapter 2 examines the Old B-Theory of Language (advocated by
Russell, Frege, Quine, Hans Reichenbach, J. J. Smart), which attempted
to de-tense language (a) by replacing tensed expressions with
appropriate dates and/or clock times (presumably without loss of
meaning) or (b) by analyzing tensed expressions in terms of token
reflexivity. The first strategy has widely been recognized as a failure;
tense and indexicality are irreducible and essential to explain certain
human thoughts and actions. Token reflexivity (translating tensed
sentences into tenseless ones without loss of meaning) does not deliver
what it promises; information is lost in translation, and tense again
proves inescapable to motivate human action. Thus tense is not
superfluous.
Chapter 3 discusses the New B-Theory of Language (most notably
promoted by D. H. Mellor), which admits to the necessity of tensed
language but denies any objectivity to tensed facts/events: they are
still tenseless, and A-theorists have wrongly reified them. However, the
New B-Theory is "logically defective" (p. 96) in that it, for
example, fails to give any coherent account of truth conditions and
confuses truth conditions with truth makers in tensed sentences.
Chapter 4 discusses theories of direct reference, examining the
B-theorist's tu quoque argument in particular--namely, if "the
A-theorist's arguments for the reality of tense are correct, then
there must be spatially `tensed' facts as well, which no one will
admit" (p. 97). However, this argument proves ineffectual as well,
as tense proves inescapable both in language as well as in reality. This
is borne out by our very experience of tense as properly and irreducibly
basic (chapter 5); while this idea of properly basic belief (ably
exposited by Alvin Plantinga) is prima facie rather than ultima facie,
it stands up to Mellorian counterexamples or potential defeaters (for
example, witnessing the alleged presentness of a supernova through a
telescope), which Craig deftly rebuts. That said, belief in tense and
temporal becoming as real is universal and enjoys the status of being an
intrinsic defeater to speculative B-theoretical arguments.
Chapter 6 brings us to the objection to the A-theory known as
McTaggart's Paradox, which seeks to show that an A-series of events
is self-contradictory or leads to a vicious infinite regress of
A-theoretic determinations. However, J. M. E. McTaggart's
underlying metaphysic (events as substances and the assumption that if
time is real, all events--including past and future ones--are equally
real) and his misconstrual of absolute becoming raise serious objections
to his view. Also in this chapter, Craig, a presentist (holding that
"the only temporal items which exist are those which are
present" [p. 208]), gives a very helpful discussion on presentness
and existence.
The final chapter ("The Myth of Temporal Passage")
examines a second objection, which turns out to be a misunderstanding of
"the flow of time," which certain B-theorists claim that
A-theorists hold. Among other arguments, presentists (A-theorists)
reject a substantivalist view of time, denying a literal flow of time
(p. 221); it is a mere metaphor for temporal becoming.
These two objections against the A-theory ultimately fail, and the
ineliminability of tense from language and our rich, properly basic
experience of tense offer prima facie warrant for an A-theory of time.
Further examination of the B-theory, however, is necessary and thus
taken up in the companion volume, The Tenseless Theory of Time.
In this book, though, Craig ably and rigorously argues for an
A-theory of time, and The Tensed Theory of Time offers a comprehensive
analysis and important advances on this particular theory of time.--Paul
Copan, Trinity International University and RZIM.