Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues.
Lewis, V. Bradley
MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings
Need the Virtues. Chicago: Open Court, 1999. xiii + 172 pp. Cloth,
$26.95--Dependent Rational Animals consists of a revision of the three
Paul Carus Lectures delivered by MacIntyre at the 1997 Pacific Division
meeting of the APA. The book is rather different from MacIntyre's
work since After Virtue in that it proceeds systematically rather than
historically to develop a Thomistic-Aristotelian view of ethics that
takes its departure from (1) the continuities in human and nonhuman
animal nature and (2) the role of dependence in human lire. These issues
lead to a consideration of the distinctive virtues required of us if we
are to become independent practical reasoners able to acknowledge our
dependence on others in arriving at that state of independence as well
as continuing dependence on others with whom we participate in the
relationships of giving and receiving through which we pursue the goods
that constitute human flourishing. The argument proceeds in roughly
three stages.
First MacIntyre argues for a more direct continuity between human
nature and the nature of nonhuman animals through a discussion of
whether or not nonhuman animals can be said to act for reasons. While
many have argued against this notion on the grounds that there can be no
action for reasons without language, MacIntyre uses the example of
certain species (most importantly of dolphins) to show how animals do
exercise a nonlinguistic mode of distinguishing between true and false
that the later and distinctively human ability to reflect on and
evaluate prelinguistic and nonlinguistic distinction-making builds upon
(pp. 36-7). Moreover, the nonlinguistic distinction-making of nonhuman
animals is analogous to the prelinguistic stage in the development of
human beings from infants to mature practical reasoners and it is
precisely this continuity between the nonhuman and the human that
renders intelligible human development (p. 56).
It is the transition human beings undergo from infant to
independent practical reasoner that occupies the second stage in
MacIntyre's account. The transition is characterized by three
dimensions that all require the possession of language: the movement
from simply having reasons/desires to evaluating them as good or bad and
consequently changing them and our actions; learning to cooperate with
others in the pursuit of common goods; and the ability to imagine future
possibilities. The main work of the transition to independent practical
reasoner is the acquisition of those qualities of intellect and
character that support practical reason and enable us to pursue the
goods that constitute human flourishing: the intellectual and moral
virtues. Yet the virtues continue to be important in the sustaining of
relationships of giving and receiving that are crucial to the good of
mature human beings. So the dependency that characterizes infants and
children gives way to an independent ability to reason practically, but
we remain in many respects dependent on others with whom we cooperate in
various contexts and the relationships through which that cooperation is
carried out are also sustained by the virtues.
The third stage of MacIntyre's argument concerns those
relationships through which we continue to pursue the goods that
constitute human flourishing. Here MacIntyre considers the relationship
of rules and virtues in a brief but illuminating account of the natural
law as "precepts promulgated by God through reason without
conformity to which human beings cannot achieve their common good"
(p. 111). He also offers a critique of the ability of rational choice
theory to explain the relationships necessary for the common good,
emphasizing the importance of the larger context of market
relationships, relationships that involve affective and sympathetic ties
that are themselves grounded in and "governed by norms of
uncalculated and unpredicted giving and receiving" (p. 117)
vindicated by his account of human development. This leads to a
discussion of what MacIntyre calls the virtues of "acknowledged
dependence," the most important example of which is the virtue
called misericordia (pity, mercy) by Aquinas and which MacIntyre
explains by contrasting it with Aristotle's account of magnanimity.
There is also a discussion of the kind of political contexts that can
embody the relationships of giving and receiving that allow pursuit of
individual and common goods. Here MacIntyre argues that neither the
family, which is too small and necessarily influenced by larger forces,
nor the modern state, which is too big can do the job. The family is a
necessary but not a sufficient context that requires local communities
and institutions intermediate between it and the state if the full range
of human goods are to be pursued.
Throughout the book MacIntyre pays special attention to the themes
of vulnerability, dependence, and animality in human life while
revealing important aspects of the rational faculties that differentiate
human beings from nonhuman animals. Along the way there are illuminating
discussions of parenthood, age, disease, and disability and the book
concludes with an account of philosophic inquiry that again pits
MacIntyre's Thomistic Aristotelian perspective against that of the
philosopher who he still takes to be it's most compelling rival:
Nietzsche. While this book is largely without the strong rhetoric that
has made some of MacIntyre's earlier work so provocative, its
conclusions are every bit as radical, especially as they concern our
economic and political institutions. Dependent Rational Animals is a
brief and lucid exposition of the current thinking of one of the most
important philosophical voices of the second half of the twentieth
century. It should not be missed.--V. Bradley Lewis, The Catholic
University of America.