The tenseless theory of time: insights and limitations.
Dolev, Yuval
THE TENSELESS THEORY OF TIME has enjoyed a great revival in the
twentieth century. Prominent philosophers such as Russell, Ayer,
Goodman, Quine, and Smart and, more recently, Mellor and Parfit, have
turned their philosophical efforts and talents to its defense. It is
proper to refer to their work as a "revival," for under
different names (and, of course, with terms typical of other eras in the
history of philosophy), the view has been at the center of the
philosophical preoccupation with time for centuries. A version of the
view can be found in Augustine's Confessions, which presents the
essentials of the view in terms that are surprisingly familiar to a
student educated in contemporary philosophical thought and jargon.
In this century, supporters of the tenseless view have been keen on
quoting Einstein's famous assertion that "the distinction
between past, present, and future is only an illusion." (1) Of
course, each thinker has his own way of unpacking this statement, and
the differences can be considerable. Nevertheless, the term
"illusion" is invoked in connection with tense by practically
all the view's sympathizers. This assertion will be one of my
principle targets. Another closely related target will be the notion of
"tenseless relations." It is claimed by tenseless theorists
that, for example, the assertion that the American Revolution precedes
(or preceded) the French Revolution describes a tenseless relation, that
is, a temporal fact in which the notions "past,"
"present," and "future" do not figure in any way,
explicitly or implicitly. I shall argue that, like the idea that tense
is an illusion, the notion of a tenseless relation is an incoherent one.
A major challenge tenseless theorists have confronted was
undermining the massive evidence against their view constituted by
everyday language and thought. They have had to show that the fact that
we speak and think in tensed terms can be reconciled with the tenseless
view. For this purpose, many of them have resorted to the so-called
token-reflexive (2) account of tense. In this paper I shall discuss this
device as it is developed and presented by Mellor in his 1981 book Real
Time. I choose this book because of its thoroughness and clarity. In his
recent book, Real Time II (published in 1999), Mellor offers a modified
version of the tenseless view, an "indexical theory," that
does not rely on token-reflexive sentences. I shall explain in the
course of what follows how the objections I develop against the
token-reflexive account carry over to Mellor's current view.
To anticipate a likely misunderstanding, I wish to emphasize from
the outset that my objections to the tenseless view must not be taken as
implying support for the opposing tensed theory of time. The arguments
developed in this paper do not assume and do not entail any of the
tensed view's tenets. Since this remark is important for the
understanding of what follows, I would like briefly to explain it.
The tenseless theory of time is held by many of its adherents to
consists of two separate theses: a negative thesis, that there are no
deep ontological differences between the past, present, and future; and
a positive thesis that, as Parfit puts it, "tense is merely part of
mental reality," (3) or that tense is an illusion, or as Mellor
puts it, a myth. The first thesis is negative because it consists simply
of the negation of the rival tensed theory of time--the view that the
present is more real than, or ontologically privileged with respect to,
the past and the future (4)--and is given in terms taken from the rival
theory. The positive thesis consists of a picture of time that stands
independently of any other proposal. Tenseless theorists take the two
theses to be mutually implicated. For many of them, the only way to
establish the correctness of the tenseless view is to demonstrate the
correctness of the negative thesis, that is, the untenability of the
tensed view. Thus Mellor writes: "Tense is so striking an aspect of
reality that only the most compelling argument justifies denying it:
namely, that the tensed view of time is self-contradictory and so cannot
be true." (5)
For reasons that I can only hint at in this paper, I believe that
this supposed equivalence between the theses does not in fact obtain,
and that in particular, the negative thesis does not entail the positive
one. The assertion that there are no ontological differences between the
past, present, and future implies that the distinction between the past,
present, and future is merely an illusion only if we are forced into
choosing between the thesis that the present is ontologically privileged
and the thesis that "tense is merely part of mental reality."
(6) I think we should reject both positions as incoherent. Indeed, I
agree with tenseless theorists that the attempts to articulate a
metaphysical theory that ontologically or metaphysically privileges the
present are doomed to fail. We cannot make sense of the claim that the
present is metaphysically more real and, thus, we cannot accept the
tensed view, or so I claim. But neither can we make sense of the
tenseless positive assertion that the present is equally real as the
past and the future, when it is taken to mean that the distinction
between the past, present, and future is merely an illusion. Thus, I
think we ought to reject the imposition, accepted by both the tensed and
the tenseless camps, of the need to choose between them, an imposition
grounded in the shared supposition that philosophical clarity concerning
time must take the form of a reality claim. I therefore hold that it is
possible to accept the negative thesis of the tenseless theory without
thereby becoming committed to its positive thesis: we should reject the
idea that the present is ontologically privileged, but we cannot endorse
the thesis that tense belongs to mental reality.
This brief and general survey of the discussion in the metaphysics of time touches upon many claims, the argumentation for which would
exceed the scope of this paper. I shall limit myself in it to an
examination of the main points in Mellor's rendition of the
tenseless view. The next section concerns the role of tense in language
and discusses Mellor's reasons for holding that "tense is an
inescapable mode of perceiving, thinking and speaking about
reality." (7) In the third section Mellor's token-reflexive
account of tensed truths is presented, as well as his current, modified
view. These sections prepare the ground for the critical evaluation,
offered in the fourth section, of the notion of "tenseless
relations" on which Mellor's picture of time is founded.
Finally, in the fifth section, I outline my reasons for questioning the
intelligibility of the claim that tense is an illusion.
II
The Semantically Reductive Analysis of Tense. According to Dummett,
"McTaggart took it for granted that reality must be something of
which there exists in principle a complete description," (8) by
which he meant a description that is independent of the perspective of
the describer (he called it "observer independent"). Tensed
properties, which seem to be perspectival--the 1996 presidential
elections are past for us, but were future for the voters in
1995--cannot, therefore, be part of a complete, objective description of
events and things. In the same vein Parfit writes: "In a complete
description of reality, no [tensed statements] would be needed."
(9) For tenseless theorists, saying of tensed sentences that they are
perspectival is tantamount to asserting that, as Mellor puts it,
"there is in reality no difference between the past, present, and
future." (10) Very similarly, Parfit says that there are no deep
ontological differences between that past, present, and future. Mellor
seems to be speaking for both, or indeed, for all tenseless theorists,
when he asserts that "tense is not the way that in reality [things]
are," (11) and, what amounts to the same, that "tense is
really just a mode of thought." (12)
Driven by this notion of "a complete description," early
versions of the tenseless view were reductive, that is, they consisted
of attempts to eliminate tense, in principle at least, from language and
from thought, so as to furnish, again, in principle at least, such a
description. Various translation manuals of tensed sentences into
tenseless ones that were taken to mean the same were suggested for that
purpose. For example, in The Structure of Appearance, Goodman writes:
"The `past', `present', and `future' name no times.
Rather the `is past at', the `is present at' and the `is
future at' are tenseless two-place predicates that may respectively
be translated by the tenseless predicates `is earlier than', `is
at', and `is later than'." (13) On this suggestion,
"Kennedy's assassination is now past," means the same as
"Kennedy's assassination is earlier than the utterance of this
sentence (or the tokening of this thought)."
The term "translation manuals" is somewhat misleading,
for a translation usually imports a thought into a language which we
command. The above translation manuals, on the other hand, were conjured
up in order to translate something, namely tense, away--to export it out
of any language we might possess. Their function was not to help us
understand something we do not, but to make a metaphysical picture
palatable despite its apparent conflict with the language we already
understand and depend upon. Thus, the sophisticated intervention with
language that such manuals constitute was also somewhat violent, but it
was deemed necessary by early defenders of the tenseless view because of
the remarkable and pervasive presence of tense in our experiences,
language, and thought.
Indeed, the manifestations of tense with which such a theory must
deal are ubiquitous. All of our experiences are thought and spoken of by
us not as simply being in time, that is, as occurring on a certain date,
but as being past, present, or future. Moreover, not only are there
grammatical differences in the way we talk about past, present, or
future events and experiences, there are also phenomenological
disparities that correspond to the tensed locations of events and
experiences. Anticipating what it will be like to see Ingres's
"La Grande Odalisque" for the first time was an experience
qualitatively different from actually seeing it, and these two
experiences are phenomenologically different from remembering that first
time. Internal sensations, as Prior showed, make the case even more
impressively: "If I am glad that the pain will be over in five
minutes, this is not the same thing I shall be glad about in five
minutes' time when I say `Thank God it's over now!'"
(14)
To be sure, initially at least, experiential manifestations of
tense do not establish anything about its nature, for example, they do
not by themselves constitute proof of the reality or objectivity of
tense. But given their predominance, they do seem to place the burden of
proof on those who are after a tenseless description of the world. The
translation manuals mentioned above were supposed to meet this challenge
by dispensing with tense, at least insofar as language and thought are
concerned. However, despite the stock and effort invested in them,
further work soon proved their inadequacy as means for tenselessly
handling tense, thus confirming the worries of those skeptical of the
tenseless enterprise, that tense is too deeply and inextricably rooted
in language and thought for the idea of removing it from them to so much
as make sense. I shall now review Mellor's arguments which are
aimed at establishing decisively that translation manuals of tensed
sentences into tenseless ones that mean the same cannot be formulated.
Tensed sentences, in most cases, do not have, and cannot have, tenseless
equivalencies.
The first step toward realizing the impossibility of translating
tensed sentences into tenseless ones is noting that tokens of tensed
sentences do not have the same truth conditions as any tenseless
sentence that is a candidate to be their translation. Consider a token
of the tensed sentence "The lecture is beginning now." Let us
call this token T. It is true if and only if it is tokened--uttered,
read, thought--at the same time that the lecture is beginning. This
tenseless fact, the temporal relation between the two events, is (at
least according to tenseless theorists) the fact that gives T its
truth-value. If any tenseless sentence can serve as a translation of it,
that is, can have the same meaning it has, it is the sentence that
describes this tenseless truth condition, namely, the sentence "The
tokening of T, this very tokening of it, and the beginning of the
lecture occur at the same time." Let us call a token of this
sentence S (I shall contend shortly that this sentence is not really
tenseless, but for the moment let us assume that it is). Now, whereas S
is true (or false) regardless of when it is tokened, the truth of T
depends on when it is tokened. T's date, its location in time, is
part of the conditions in virtue of which it is true. But it is not part
of the conditions in virtue of which S is true. So the two sentences do
not have the same truth-conditions, and as Mellor says, "two
sentences can hardly mean the same if, as here, they are true in quite
different circumstances." (15)
It might be instructive to repeat this argument without appealing
to the debatable association of meanings with truth-conditions. If you
wonder when the lecture is about to begin, then T, but not S, can
provide you with the information you need. If you ask someone when the
lecture is beginning and the response is a token of S, you will still
not know when the lecture is beginning. Say the response is "The
lecture is beginning at the same time in which you are hearing this
sentence." You might still be unsure, for it might not be clear
which sentence the word "this" in the response refers to
(imagine the response is given to you by a foreigner who you suspect has
not yet mastered verb conjugation and might be using the present tense but means a sentence you heard in the past). (16) You will know when the
lecture begins if the response is "The lecture is beginning at the
same time in which I utter the sentence you are hearing now." But
this response, employing the word "now," is of course tensed.
Perhaps the tenseless response is simply: "The lecture is beginning
at 6:00 P.M." Again, this cannot serve as a substitute for T, for
it is useless unless you know that it is now 6:00 P.M., that is, unless
you employ a tensed sentence in conjunction with it.
The point is that "no sentence could possibly mean the same as
another if, as here, it cannot be used at all as the other one
standardly is." (17) John needs to take a medication at one
o'clock in the afternoon. If a reliable source--his wrist watch,
the radio, and so forth--provides him with a token of the tensed
sentence "It is now one o'clock in the afternoon," he
will be able to take his medication on time. Otherwise, he can only try
to guess the right moment. Obviously, if all he is provided with is a
token of a tenseless sentence of the kind we have considered as a
possible translation, he will not know when to take his
medication--tenseless sentences say that at one o'clock in the
afternoon it is one o'clock, but not whether it is one o'clock
now, which is what John needs to know. Since no tenseless sentence can
be used for the same end as "It is now one o'clock," no
tenseless sentence can translate it. In general tensed sentences have
daily uses that cannot be fulfilled by any tenseless sentences. Thus,
whichever way the relation between use and meaning is construed, in
light of such examples, we must conclude with Mellor that there cannot
be tenseless sentences that have the same meaning as certain tensed
sentences.
This also shows that tensed sentences are indispensable--to act
successfully we must have tensed beliefs. To take his medication on
time, John needs to know what time it is now, that is, have a tensed
belief of the form "It is now ..." Insofar as we act in the
world, the success of our actions depends in part on our possession of
tensed beliefs. I think these claims are pretty much straightforward and
indisputable. That is why attempts to formulate and defend the tenseless
view by demonstrating the dispensability, in principle at least, of
tensed sentences were doomed from the outset.
III
The Semantically Nonreductive Token-reflexive Account. The failure
of the reductionist program did not by any means signify, however, the
end of the tenseless endeavor. Having abandoned the project of
eliminating tense from language, a new generation of theorists found
promise in a version of the view which, rather than resisting it, allows
as part of its tenseless picture of time the fact that "tense is an
inescapable mode of perceiving, thinking and speaking about
reality." (18) Once this fact was recognized, the task for the
tenseless theorist was reconceived to consist, not of explaining tense
away, but of accounting for it in a manner that, while registering its
inescapability and indispensability, is congenial to the tenseless
picture. What needed to be abandoned, according to the new plan, was the
theory of meaning which claims that, and presumes to specify how, the
meaning of tensed sentences can be captured by tenseless statements. In
place of it, defenders of the tenseless view had to offer accounts of
the manner in which tensed statements, whose meanings cannot be given in
tenseless terms, receive their truth-values from tenseless conditions,
or explications, in tenseless terms, of how an understanding of tensed
terms comes about and what it consists of.
The great advantage of this approach is that, while it removes the
distinction between past, present, and future from objective reality, it
leaves tenses untouched precisely in the domains in which we are
accustomed to encounter them and in which we need them most--language
and thought. As Mellor puts it, "tense is not being banished
altogether, merely replaced where it belongs--in our heads." (19) I
shall now present briefly Mellor's version of the tenseless
token-reflexive account of truth, by means of which this taming of tense
is executed.
Two preliminary remarks need to be made. First, it is necessary to
adopt a terminological convention before we start. When one says that
the next presidential elections will take place just over three years
from now, one is locating these elections in time by means of a tensed
description. Tensed sentences come in many forms. In addition to the
notions "past," "present," and "future,"
adjectival words and phrases such as "now,"
"yesterday," "one week ago," "one year
hence," can be used to construct tensed sentences. When the
temporal locations of events and objects are given by means of such
words and terms, we shall refer to them as their tensed location. The
other manner of locating events in time is by means of dates. If I say
that the date of the presidential elections is November 2004, I am
locating them by their date. Following Mellor, I shall assume this
ordinary distinction between tenses and dates. (20)
Second, it needs to be emphasized that the assertion that tense is
an inescapable mode of thinking and speaking about reality, is about
language in relation to extralinguistic events and objects. It states
that when we think or speak about an event or an object, we necessarily
think or speak about it as tensedly located in time, that is, as past,
present, or future. When perceiving the setting of the sun, it is not my
perception that I judge to be present, rather, I perceive the sun
setting now. We may not pay attention to this fact about the event or
the object, but if we do, it seems to be there to be apprehended by us.
It is due to considerations such as these that Parfit remarks that when
there is a dispute about the role of tense in language, "the
disagreements [are] not about our language, but about the nature of
time." (21)
Now, "the first step in explaining away tensed facts is to
trade them in for tensed truths." (22) To facilitate the trade-in,
Mellor marks several features of truth. First, he asserts that truth is
a property of sentences. In the context of disputes concerning the
nature, not of time but of truth, this claim can open up a
Pandora's box of disagreements. Mellor, however, does not intend to
make with it a metaphysical claim about the nature of truth, and so we
shall grant him this harmless reference to truth as a property. Next,
Mellor points out that truth is a property of sentence-tokens and not of
sentence-types. Since the discussion that follows trades heavily on this
claim, let us clarify it. The claim is that in thinking and speaking, we
always make use of tokens of sentences, rather than of types. Again, in
using the notions "type" and "token" Mellor does not
have in mind any metaphysically charged distinctions but simply a very
ordinary distinction between, for example, your particular copy of the
bible, and what is sometimes referred to as the best-seller of all
times; or between the sentence "Socrates is mortal" and all
the particular events that consisted of someone's thinking,
reading, or uttering this sentence. In the present context, the claim
that truth is a property of sentence-tokens rather than of types can be
easily demonstrated with tensed sentences such as "Today is
Monday."
The useful observation Mellor makes about tokens--uttered tokens,
read tokens, thought tokens, and so forth--is that they all have
determinate dates: "Particular thoughts strike particular people at
particular times: the token judgments they make, therefore, like the
token sentences they speak and write, all have dates of greater or
lesser duration." (23) There is a slight complication in the use of
the terms "token" and "type" which should be noted.
A particular copy of a book may be counted as a token, in which case the
sentences printed in it should be counted as tokens as well. In another
context, however, the sentences printed in a book are not tokens;
rather, the event of someone reading them is. Thus, whether something
counts as a token or as a type may depend on the context. But the cases
that will concern us will not involve such complications. For our
purposes, we can treat having a determinate date as a defining feature
of tokens. The hour your watch is showing now (including the day of the
month, the month, the year) is the date of the thought you are having
now, and that suffices to distinguish it from the type we may associate
with that thought. All we need to remember is that particular thoughts
and utterances have a determinate date.
Finally, Mellor states that descriptive sentences that are true or
false have "facts that give them the objective truth or falsity we
know they have." (24) Mellor does not specify in any detail the
nature of the relationship between facts on the one hand and meaning and
truth on the other, nor does he assume any theory that explains it, for
example, some correspondence theory of truth or some form of
verificationism. Again, being economic with explanations on this matter
is part of Mellor's policy of avoiding, when possible,
philosophical muddles that are not related directly to the claims
concerning the nature of time that he is arguing for. We will,
nevertheless, have to examine somewhat closely the details of the
association Mellor makes between truths and facts, but at this level of
generality no particularly objectionable claim has yet been put forth.
Now, tenselessly accounting for the truth of tensed sentences
consists in finding "tenseless facts that give [tensed sentences]
the objective truth or falsity we know they have.... The facts I am
looking for must be undeniable facts, objective and tenseless, that will
make tensed judgments true when they are true, and false when they are
false." (25) Examples such as the following indicate exactly where
the sought after facts are to be found:
Suppose someone says or thinks sometime in May 1984 that the Queen is
fifty-eight, and suppose he absent-mindedly makes the same judgment again a
year later. That is, he produces two tokens of the sentence type `The Queen
is fifty-eight', each with an objective truth value. But not the same truth
value. The first token is true, because ... in May 1984 the Queen is
fifty-eight. The second token is false, because the inexorable change in
tense of the Queen's birth during the intervening year has by then made her
fifty-nine.... Token sentences, we have remarked, are things and events
with more or less definite dates. These dates (May `84 for the first token,
May `85 for the second), together with the date in April 1926 when the
Queen was born, are enough to make the first of these tokens true and the
other false. (26)
From examining such cases Mellor concludes that
The truth-value of tokens of any particular tensed type are--so far as time
is concerned--a definite function of how much later or earlier the tokens
are than the events they are about. (27)
If among the facts that give a token of a sentence its truth-value
there are facts about the token itself, for example, its date, the
account of what makes that token true is called a token-reflexive
account. Mellor's is such an account: rather than a nonrelational
property of being past or present or future, a tenseless relation of
precedence, in which the date of the token figures, is the objective
fact that gives tokens of tensed sentences their truth-values. Tokens of
future tense sentences are true if and only if the events they are about
have a date which is later than the date of those particular tokens;
tokens of present tense sentences are true if and only if they occur at
the same date as the event they are about; and tokens of past tense sentences are true if and only if they occur after the event they are
about.
Since according to this account only permanent, never changing
tenseless facts about dates figure in giving tensed sentences their
truth-value, it clearly paves the way for the elimination of tensed
facts: if tensed facts need to be invoked at all, it is only in order to
account for the truth of tensed sentences, but if other facts suffice
for this purpose, which is the case if the token-reflexive account is
correct, then no use can be found for tensed facts and there is no
reason for insisting on their reality.
As mentioned, Mellor has modified his position, and in his new
book, Real Time II, replaces the token-reflexive account with what he
calls the "indexical theory." The reason for the modification
is that, under certain circumstances, the token-reflexive account may
give wrong truth values:
Imagine a time t when no one has written or is thinking or saying anything,
i.e. when there are no tokens of any proposition; and consider the
now-propositions `There are tokens now' `There are no tokens now', which I
shall call `u' and `-u' respectively. At t, `u' is false and `-u' is true.
Yet, obviously, no token of `u' can be false at any time, and no token of
`-u' can be true. For whenever there are any tokens of any proposition, `u'
and its tokens are true and `-u' and its tokens are false. So when `u' is
false and `-u' is true, the token-reflexive tale of what makes these
now-propositions true or false will give the wrong answer. (28)
In order to circumvent this difficulty, the token-reflexive
account, according to which
any token of `P' is true if and only is it is as much earlier or later than
e as `P' says the present is than e (29)
is replaced by the following "indexical theory" (in Real
Time II Mellor adopts McTaggart's original terminology, and calls
tensed sentences "A-propositions"):
any A-proposition `P' about any event e is made true at any t by t's being
as much earlier or later than e as `P' says the present is than e. (30)
Evidently, the function fulfilled by the token-reflexive account,
namely, providing an analysis, in terms of tenseless relations, of what
makes tensed propositions true, is just as successfully fulfilled by the
indexical theory. The only difference is that tokens are replaced by
times: a tenseless relation holds between an event e and a time t,
rather than between an event e and a token of "P," as is the
case on the token-reflexive account.
To sum up, the nonreductive tenseless view consists of two claims
that, on the face of it, are at odds with each other, but that are
reconciled by means of the token-reflexive or indexical theories. The
first is that tense is inescapable and ineliminable from language,
thought, and experience--that is, that tense necessarily appears as part
of the reality which we experience, speak about, and think about. The
second is that, as Mellor puts it, "tense is really just a mode of
thought," (31) or as he says elsewhere, that "tense is not the
way that in reality [things] are," (32) or, to use Parfit's
formulation, tense "is merely a part of mental reality." (33)
Now, when the way we perceive reality is not the way that reality is, we
can say that we are subject to an illusion. When the illusion pervades
not only perception but also language and thought, that is, when the way
we think and speak of reality is also not the way that reality is, and
when this predicament is one which, in principle, cannot be escaped
from, then we are dealing with an illusion which is both global--it
effects all aspects of our cognition--and perpetual--it is operative in
all situations, all places, and at all times. We can bring together what
has been said hitherto about the tenseless view by saying that,
according to it, tense is such an illusion.
I shall now proceed to the critical part of the paper. First I
shall present my objections to the token-reflexive account, with which
the tenseless view is still widely associated, despite the existence of
alternatives, such as the indexical theory. I shall then explain why
this objection also applies to the indexical theory. Finally, I shall
discuss the claim, implied by these theories, that tense is a global and
perpetual illusion.
IV
The Incoherence of the Notion of "Tenseless Relations."
Let me start with a summary of the claims I shall develop in this
section. The token-reflexive account of the truth of tensed sentences is
given in terms of temporally tenseless relations and tenseless sentences
that describe them: what makes the sentence "The Queen is
fifty-eight" true (if it is true) is the tenseless fact that
fifty-eight years separate the Queen's birth and the date on which
it is tokened, a fact which is given by the tenseless sentence "The
Queen was born fifty-eight years before the tokening of this
sentence," or "Fifty-eight years separate the Queen's
birth and the tokening of this sentence." I shall argue that Mellor
justifies the distinction between tenseless and tensed relations by an
appeal to this very distinction, which renders his argument question
begging. More seriously, as will come out in the course of analyzing the
structure of Mellor's argument, the idea of "tenseless
relations" is unintelligible.
Let us recall that Mellor begins the argument for the elimination
of tensed facts by invoking the supposedly innocuous distinction between
facts and truths--the function of the token-reflexive account is to
facilitate the trade-in through which tensed facts are discarded while
tensed truths are retained. Now, there is a perfectly ordinary sense in
which events are distinct from the sentences with which we think and
speak about them. When the witness in court testifies "I was at
home when he was murdered," no difficulty arises in distinguishing
this true or false statement from what it is about, which is not part of
language at all. However, Mellor, under the guise of a natural
distinction between tensed truths and tensed facts, sneaks in the
heavily charged distinction between the mind, the dwelling place of the
subjective tense, and the world of real time. Let us pause for a moment
to consider the ordinary distinction between facts and truths. We can
distinguish between chemical facts and the truths of chemistry, between
the fact that [H.sub.2]O is water and the true sentence "Water is
composed of [H.sub.2]O molecules"; or between the fact that Kennedy
was assassinated in 1963 and the sentence "Kennedy was assassinated
in 1963." These are instances of the ordinary distinction between
facts and truths. One reason we call it ordinary is precisely because
the question of a trade-in does not come up in connection with these
examples. We cannot, and do not wish to enact a trade-in between these
facts or events and the true sentences that state them. If a trade-in is
the issue, it is plain that for it to accomplish its purpose, that is,
(paraphrasing Mellor) "replacing something where it belongs--in our
heads," the items traded must correspond to reality, on the one
hand, and to what goes on inside our heads on the other, and these
latter terms, used in this way, are no longer ordinary but are the
products of a philosophical position which is wedded to weighty
metaphysical assumptions. So the dichotomy is not the innocent
distinction it appears to be.
Now, Mellor needs to provide a justification for treating tense
separately, for metaphysically compartmentalizing tensed truths and
facts in a manner that sets tense apart from other ordinary instances of
the fact/truth distinction. He has to say why tensed facts can be
eliminated by the invocation of this distinction, while, for example,
chemical, historical, or tenseless facts are left unharmed. The
following passages contain the crucial components of Mellor's
reasons, and of his interpretation of the distinction between tenseless
and tensed sentences:
[contingent tensed sentences] may not have the same meanings as the
tenseless sentences that give their truth conditions, but those truth
conditions surely give their meaning ... anyone who knows that, for all
dates T, `It is now T' is true during and only during T knows what `It is
now ...' means. (34)
The word "give" works in this key passage in both
directions: sentences give truth conditions, and truth conditions give
the meanings of sentences. There is an asymmetry, however, between
tensed sentences and tenseless sentences in this regard. While both are
given their meaning by truth conditions, truth conditions are given only
by tenseless sentences. This distinction between tenseless sentences
that also give truth condition, and tensed sentences that only get them,
needs to be examined. So let us try to get clear on what
"giving" is all about. In the above quotation, to say of a
certain sentence that it gives truth conditions is to say simply that it
describes them, that is, that it can inform a listener as to what are
the facts, the states of affairs, in virtue of which a sentence is true
(or false) on a given occasion. It is a bit trickier to flesh out the
idea that truth conditions give meaning to sentences. The cited passage
makes it clear, however, that what Mellor has in mind is explicated, in
part at least, by the assertion that anyone who understands the
sentences that give these truth conditions, that is, that describe them,
can understand the sentence the meaning of which is given by them.
Mellor's example consists of the tensed token (S) "It is
now 1980" and a token of the tenseless sentence (TL) "S occurs
in 1980." TL gives truth conditions, the conditions under which S
is true: S is true during, and only during 1980, that is, if and only if
S occurs in 1980. What are the truth conditions of a token of TL? It too
is true if and only if S occurs in 1980 (TL is true if and only if TL).
Thus, TL gives its own truth conditions. Do S and TL have the same truth
conditions? Yes and no. Yes, in that TL describes the condition, the
state of affairs, the tenseless fact to which the truth value and
meaning of both are attached. No, because TL makes reference to the date
of S, but not to the date of TL itself. So although TL describes the
tenseless state of affairs to which the meanings of both sentences are
attached, this state of affairs stands in different relations to
each--it includes the date of one but not of the other. Giving the
shared truth condition involves saying something about one sentence and
nothing about the other. This relation is part of the truth condition of
both and since it is different in each case, in this respect S and TL do
not have the same truth conditions. This difference manifests itself in
that while S is true if and only if it occurs in 1980, a token of TL, if
true, is true regardless of when it occurs. That is why S and TL do not
have the same meaning.
Meaning is related to understanding, and the difference in meaning
induces a difference in what understanding consists of in each case.
Understanding consists, in part, in possessing the ability to use a
sentence correctly, and in particular, in being able to specify the
conditions under which it can be tokened truthfully, in being able to
give its truth conditions. These, on Mellor's view, are always
tenseless conditions. For tenseless sentences, these conditions just are
the conditions that give the sentence its meaning. As we noted, TL, for
example, gives its own truth conditions, and to understand it is to know
that if true, it is true regardless of when it is uttered. For tensed
sentences the situation is different. They do not give truth conditions.
Their truth conditions are rather given by token-reflexive tenseless
sentences. Since it is in these later sentences that the information
concerning when they can be uttered truthfully is contained,
understanding a tensed sentence S requires, on this picture, (at least
tacit) knowledge of the form "S has the truth condition TL."
Let us, then, imagine a speaker, Helen, who has the ability to make
her tacit knowledge explicit, and consider a sentence in Helen's
idiolect, say "It is raining now." Her understanding of this
sentence consists in part in knowing when it can be tokened truthfully.
How can she make this knowledge explicit? She cannot invoke
Tarski's "convention T" and give the requisite
specification by stating that it can be tokened truthfully if and only
if it is raining now, for this does not describe the sentence's
tenseless truth conditions. On Mellor's picture, a proper
specification of the conditions under which it can be truthfully uttered
would be: "`It is raining now' is true if and only if it is
tokened at a time in which it is raining." And Helen would have to
use this tenseless sentence if she wished to make her understanding of
"It is raining now" explicit. In Mellor's jargon, the
tenseless sentence gives the truth condition which gives the meaning of
"It is raining now." I think that, when fleshed out, this is
what the difference between giving truth conditions and having truth
conditions give meanings comes to: grasping the meaning of a sentence
presupposes the ability to think the tenseless thought (or at least to
have the tenseless tacit belief) that describes its truth conditions.
This fits in well with the picture Mellor is working with. For
Mellor, directly experiencing tenseless facts, for example, perceiving
the thunder succeeding the lightning, is an integral part of the
mechanism by which we come to understand tenseless sentences. We
directly perceive precedence, that is, tenseless facts, and through
these experiences we directly acquire an understanding of the sentences
that describe the facts experienced--what is experienced is what is
described. When a tenseless sentence says that things are thus and so,
the meaning and truth of what it says are fixed by things being thus and
so. There is no gap: the conditions that TL describes are the conditions
its truth and meaning are attached to. With tenses, however, the
situation is different. When a tensed sentence says that things are thus
and so, it is not by their being thus and so that its meaning and truth
are fixed, for it speaks of tensed facts when there are none. Here there
is a gap between what the sentence says, and the conditions that give it
meaning. We need to hook up with what gives it meaning before we can
understand what it says. Thus, the gap needs to be filled in, mediated,
by beliefs about the conditions that endow the tensed sentence with its
meaning, that is, by the beliefs which would be expressed, if made
explicit, by the tenseless sentences which give these conditions.
One of Wittgenstein's mechanical images can be helpful in
illustrating the point. Tenseless and tensed sentences can be likened to
gear wheels that share the same axis, rotating together. Only the
tenseless wheel, however, meshes with facts, with reality. The teeth of
the tensed wheel are not designed to do so--there is nothing in reality
they can latch on to. They get their motion (meaning and truth) by being
on the same axis with the tenseless wheel which is rotated through the
perfect, gapless fit that exists between it and reality. Because the
meanings of tenseless--but not of tensed--sentences attach directly to
the facts that endow sentences with meaning, tenseless facts cannot be
traded in for truths, while tensed facts can and ought to be. The upshot
of all this is that, while tensed sentences cannot be reduced, or
translated, into tenseless sentences (compare section 2 above), they are
nonetheless parasitic on beliefs expressed by tenseless sentences for
their meaning and truth, which, as we saw, entails that an understanding
of tensed sentences presupposes an ability to have tenseless
beliefs--beliefs which, were they made explicit, would be expressed by
tenseless sentences. It is this difference between tensed sentences and
tenseless ones that enables Mellor to treat the fact/truth distinction
as ordinary in the tenseless case, and as metaphysical in the tensed
case. Thus, getting rid of tensed facts while retaining tenseless facts
is facilitated for Mellor by a theory of understanding that
distinguishes in the above manner tenseless sentences from tensed
sentences.
Now, the first remark to make is that the trade-in of tensed facts
for tensed truths already assumes a distinction between tensed and
tenseless relations which discriminates against tensed relations and
thus begs the question: tensed facts are assumed to be inferior, not to
play any role in our understanding, and on the basis of this assumption
are then gotten rid of. The second, more important remark, is that the
above analysis of our understanding is, I believe, untenable. Indeed,
from within the tenseless picture it is natural enough--something has to
carry, as it were, the meaning from actual conditions which are
tenseless to a sentence that is tensed, a task that only the tenseless
thoughts (or tacit beliefs) can fulfill. However we understand notions
like "tacit knowledge" or "tacit belief," this much
is clear: if we do have the tacit knowledge that a tenseless state of
affairs (the one given by TL) is the truth condition for S, then it must
be the case that we could grasp, for example, the tenseless sentence TL,
"S is tokened in 1980," prior to and independently of our
understanding S, "It is now 1980." But this, I claim, cannot
be the case. In a nutshell, the reason is that, as Mellor remarks,
"however meaning may relate in general to truth conditions, it is
an indisputable canon of modern philosophy to relate it to usage."
(35) And if usage of a tenseless sentence requires having a grasp of a
tensed sentence, then it cannot be the case that we understand it or the
thought it expresses independently of the tensed sentence. Let me
elaborate.
Consider the sentence "Kennedy was assassinated in 1963."
To understand it or for such a sentence to transmit knowledge, one must
know what "1963" refers to. It is not enough to know that it
indicates a counting from a certain chosen point in time, that 1963
years separate between that point of origin and the assassination. This
tenseless fact is a useless fact to anyone who does not know when the
point of origin is with respect to the present. Attributing an
understanding of a certain symbol to someone--a word, a number, a
sentence--requires, at the very least, that that person be able to use
it for various ordinary, modest ends, and most ordinary uses of dates
are tied up with knowing the present date. Even if to the question
"When were you born?" John correctly answers "1960,"
he cannot be regarded as someone who understands that he was born in
1960 if he does not know how to answer the question: "How old are
you?" or if he thinks that 1960 is in the future. If I do not
understand that my appointment with the dentist that is scheduled for
March 3 is to take place next week, seven days from today, then I do not
really know the use of a calendar.
There are cases in which we happen not to know the present date, or
be mistaken about it, and fail to act successfully. Of course, if my
calendar indicates that my dentist appointment is scheduled for the
third, and I show up on the fourth by mistake, that does not mean that I
do not understand the use of a calendar or the sentence "Your
appointment with the dentist is on the third." But if I never know
the present date, then I can never use information about the dates of
events to act successfully, and there is no license to attribute to me
an understanding of sentences that fix the dates of events. It is true
that, as Mellor says, anyone who knows that "It is now T" is
true during, and only during T, knows what "It is now" means.
But only someone who already knows what "It is now" means, can
know that "It is now T" is true during and only during T. In
general, an understanding of a sentence of the form "S occurs in
[T.sub.1]" depends on understanding sentences of the form "It
is now [T.sub.2]."
Thus, it cannot be that being able to think tenseless thoughts
facilitates understanding tensed sentences, for it presupposes it. I
think the processes of acquiring tenseless concepts and tensed concepts
go along hand in hand, they are inseparable. Likewise, tenseless and
tensed concepts are not really separable, but are rather fused with each
other, with no sharp line or even a fuzzy border area dividing them.
Tensed concepts figure in every occasion that tenseless ones do, and
vice versa. Mastery of the uses and senses of so-called tenseless
sentences is both a prerequisite and a consequence of mastering the use
of tensed sentences, and vice versa. We are taught what "It is
now" means, for example, when we are told "The noise we are
hearing now is that of thunder." And we learn what "e occurs
at t" means when it is explained to us that we have a birthday once
a year, or when we are told "Dessert will be served after the
salad." But we need to have some grasp of temporal succession, that
is, of dates, to understand the first sentence. For example, we need to
know that the sentence we hear refers to the thunder that is
simultaneous with it, that they occur on the same date; and we need to
have some grasp of tense to understand that the sentence "Dessert
will be served after the salad" concerns the meal we are attending
now.
The problem with the token-reflexive account is that, contrary to
the supposition of those who rely on it, the sentences and relations
employed in handling tensed facts or relations are not themselves purely
tenseless. It is true that "It is now 1997" can be explained
by saying that the date of the utterance of this very sentence is 1997.
But that is only because the context makes it clear that the phrase
"this very sentence" refers to the sentence tokened now.
Simply employing auxiliary pointing devices--replacing "this"
with "this very," using italics, and so forth--still leaves
uncertain which sentence is being referred to by the phrase "this
very sentence." It is not inconceivable that to the question
"Which sentence exactly do you have in mind?" someone will
answer "The one he spoke during last year's meeting."
This is not likely, but then nor is it very likely that the phrase
"This very sentence," and not the word "today," will
be used in fixing today's date. The point is that to the extent
that token-reflexive formulations can explain tensed sentences, it is
because the context makes them tensed themselves. In the above example,
for instance, the "is" in "The date of this very sentence
is 1997" points to the present. If the context did not make that
clear, it would not be obvious what the phrase "This very
sentence" denotes. So, even though the token-reflexive account
seems to flesh out in tenseless terms what a tensed sentence says, its
ability to do so depends on the context providing the tensed information
conveyed by the tensed sentence. Thus, again, understanding a tenseless
explanation turns on already possessing tensed language.
In ordinary language this mix manifests itself in the presence of
tense in sentences describing tenseless relations: we say that the
American Revolution occurred before, or preceded the French Revolution,
or that Kennedy was assassinated in 1963, or that it is raining at the
time in which this very sentence is being uttered. Tense figures even in
seemingly tenseless chronologies of the form:
1712-J.-J. Rousseau is born in Geneva.
1742-Rousseau moves to Paris.
1750-Rousseau's "First Discourse" wins the contest
of the Academy of Dijon.
Though it is repressed here, tense does come into play in the use
of signs such as "1712."
We can conclude that Mellor's theory of meaning, which
portrays the meaning and our understanding of tensed sentences as
parasitic on tenseless ones, fails. It fails for reasons similar to
those Mellor developed against the reductive theories of meaning: since
tensed sentences have uses that tenseless sentences cannot fulfill,
tenseless sentences cannot be used to capture either the meanings of or
the conditions for understanding tensed sentences. More important, we
see that any attempt to isolate purely tenseless relations, described by
purely tenseless sentences, without recourse to and independently of any
tensed terms or notion, cannot succeed. The meanings of temporal
concepts, the process of acquiring temporal notions and of mastering
their use, just do not exhibit any discernible elements, any
dichotomies, to which the terms "tenseless" and
"tensed" can be made to correspond.
For the same reason, the indexical theory cannot constitute a
theory of meaning for the tenseless view of time. It too turns on the
idea of purely tenseless relations, differing from the token-reflexive
account only in its conception of the terms that enter into these
relations--events and times rather than events and tokens--but not in
its reliance on a distinction we cannot draw, between tenseless and
tensed relations.
V
A Fundamental Difficulty with the View that Tense Is a Global
Illusion. (36) If my analysis of the token-reflexive account and its
failures is correct, then this account cannot be considered as making
intelligible the assertion that tense is an illusion. In this section I
wish to lay out my reasons for holding that such grounds are necessary.
The problem with the idea that tense is an illusion, I shall now argue,
is not so much to believe it but to understand it.
According to tenseless theorists the objective world, the world of
real time, is tenseless, while the world as it figures in our minds is
tensed. Before we become convinced of the validity of their view, we
mistakenly think of the tenses as part of the real world, as aspects of
real time. What is affected by the study and internalization of the
arguments in support of the view is a geographical transfer of tense, a
crossing of the border between the two worlds, of the interface that
separates them: "Tense is being replaced where it belongs--in our
heads." (37) This move, I hold, is serf-defeating: it involves a
transgression of an interface, but can be made sense of only on the
supposition that the border marked by the interface is not
transgressable. Let me explain this.
As we saw, the inescapability of tense as a mode of perception,
thought, and so forth, amounts to this: if we think of events in tensed
terms, we cannot help recognizing that they have tensed temporal
locations, that they are past, present, or future. John is contemplating
the setting of the sun. He might not be paying attention when, in tensed
terms, it is happening. But if he is, then he cannot help thinking that
the sun is setting now, that is, that it is occurring in the present.
Now, according to the tenseless view, tenses are not real, and in
particular the setting of the sun is not a tensedly located event, it is
not past, or present, or future. So John is not, and cannot be, regarded
as perceiving a tensedly located event: how can one perceive tensedly
located events if there are no such things?
That is not to say that perception is infallible, it is only to
insist that one cannot be taken to perceive what is not there to be
perceived. I might think I am perceiving a pink elephant, but if there
is no pink elephant in my vicinity I am making a mistake, or
hallucinating, or something of the like. Looking up to the night sky,
John is thrilled by the sight of a shooting star. Unbeknownst to him,
however, the object that he sees burning through the atmosphere is not a
meteorite but an old Soviet satellite spiraling down to oblivion. Can he
still be regarded as someone who has perceived a meteorite? No. He
thought he saw one, and perhaps he still does, but he is wrong. In the
same manner, according to tenseless theorists, if John thinks of the
setting of the sun as a tensed event then he is wrong, for "tense
is not the way that in reality [things] are." (38) That is what the
geographical transfer of tense amounts to--it is the recognition that
events are not tensedly located, that they only appear to us to be so
located, that it is only in our heads that they are past, present, and
future.
Thus, our position in the world is such that we cannot help
perceiving events as tensedly located, though they are not--John thinks
that the sunset he is seeing is taking place now, that is, is a present
event, though it is not. That is the right description of John's
state. Or more precisely, of the prephilosophical John. For if John has
studied the tenseless view, and has been persuaded by the arguments,
then he surely no longer thinks of the events he perceives as present
events, for he now knows that they are not. Previously, he thought of
the sunset as occurring now. Now he no longer thinks it does; rather he
thinks that that is how matters appear to him.
But now a serious problem arises. Can we still maintain that tense
is a mode of John's perception? I think not. Tense was a mode of
his perception not in that he perceived tensedly located events; for
that to be the case, the events he perceived would have to be tensedly
located. Rather, it was conceived as a mode of his perception in that he
mistakenly thought of the events he perceived as having a tensed
location. If he no longer thinks of them as such, tense is no longer a
mode of his thinking in the one and only sense in which it was.
Memory calls for a similar account. Ruth recollects the day Kennedy
was assassinated--the horrifying pictures on TV, the shock. That event
is now long past, or at least that is how she thinks of it. But she is
wrong, she is not remembering a past event, for events are not past or
present or future, she just remembers the event as past. However, once
she recognizes that there are no tensed facts, that events do not have a
tensed temporal location, then she no longer thinks of the event as
past--she now knows it is not. "Though I inevitably remember things
as past," she thinks to herself, "I know that it is only in my
thoughts that that is how they appear to be, while in reality, which my
thoughts are about, they are not. If `pastness' belongs to
anything, it is to my memories, not to what I remember. So it is not
accurate to say that tense is inescapable, for when I remember that
horrid day, I no longer think of it as past."
Experience produces tensed beliefs, for example, "The train is
leaving in two minutes." These beliefs are indispensable for
successful action. Tenseless descriptions, such as "The train
leaves at 2:04 P.M.," are insufficient. If I do not know what time
it is now, this bit of tenseless information is useless, and I shall
miss the train. But if, having been convinced by the tenseless view, I
know that events are not tensedly located, I cannot have beliefs about
their tensed locations. I might unknowingly have wrong beliefs, but I
cannot have beliefs that I know are wrong, for example, I cannot believe
that "The train is leaving in two minutes" is about the tensed
location of an event. So we no longer have beliefs about the tensed
locations of events. That is exactly what studying the tenseless view is
designed to bring about. It is supposed to alter our understanding of
the nature of time, and the alteration consists in our ceasing to regard
events as tensedly located, that is, in the elimination of our beliefs
about their tensed location.
This, however, is not a position we can readily accept. A little
while back we paused to emphasize that tense is inescapable in the sense
that we cannot help conceiving events and objects as tensedly located.
Experiences and beliefs that are tensed in this sense are not a skin
that philosophical wiggling can help us shed and get out of; it is not
possible to peel tense away from language and thought. Quite the
contrary, the assertion that tense is an inescapable mode of perceiving
and thinking about events and objects describes a feature of our
cognition which philosophical inquiry presupposes. To use an analogy
reverted to by Mellor, no amount of theorizing can establish that we do
not perceive colors, for the fact that we do is part of the language and
conceptual stock that makes theorizing about colors possible at all. It
is the fact that we see colors that can get going in the first place a
discussion concerning the reality of colors. Similarly, we do think of
events as tensedly located--we remember events of the past, and perceive
those of the present, and anticipate future ones--and we cannot help
doing so, any more than we can help seeing the colors of objects.
For the tenseless view, that we inescapably perceive, think, and
speak about events as being past, present, and future, is not just a
matter of contingent fact; it is a logical condition for its very
stateability: it is only against this fact that the assertion that the
tenses are not real can make sense. But as we just saw, this assertion
implies that we can escape tense (John knows the sunset is not a present
event) and is thus self-refuting: it undercuts the condition for its
being meaningfully stateable. To put it in other words, the distinction
between mental tensed time and actual tenseless time turns out to
constitute an instrument by which we escape that which, ex hypothesi, is
inescapable; it undercuts the very hypothesis that makes it viable, a
consequence that puts into question its coherence.
Now, the tenseless theorist might object that the above argument
proceeds too quickly and misses a simple but important point. According
to him, before we study the tenseless view we do not distinguish between
believing that things actually have a tensed location and thinking that
that is only how things appear to us. We regard tensed beliefs as
beliefs about the tensed locations of things, and suppose that we
experience, think, and speak of events as tensedly located because they
really are. In light of the tenseless view we no longer see matters in
this way. The result of the analysis is the realization that things only
appear to be tensedly located. Having tensed beliefs is reinterpreted to
mean that it inescapably appears to us as though events and things have
a tensed location although they do not. But then, says the tenseless
theorist, the tenseless view, far from being in conflict with the
assertion that tense is an inescapable mode of thought and speech, is
still committed to it. Moreover, endorsing the view does not require
abandoning tensed beliefs, only realizing that these concern the
appearance of things, rather than the way things really are. So it might
be protested that the criticism made above, with its charge that the
tenseless view divests us of our tensed beliefs, is misguided. All that
tenseless theorists are claiming is that conceptual analysis teaches us
that tenses cannot be real. Admittedly, we perceive events as though
they are tensedly located, and "we must think and speak as if there
were [tensed facts]." (39) But this is nothing but the way the
inescapable global illusion that tense is manifests itself. Realizing
this, we see that philosophical analysis is not a means of actually
experiencing the tenseless reality that is beyond this illusion, only of
inferring that there is such a reality.
Similarly with other illusions, the rejoinder continues. On very
hot sunny days roads look wet at a distance. We cannot help seeing them
as though they were spotted with puddles. But there is no mystery here.
We know the road is dry, and can explain why it appears to be wet, by
describing the effect the heat emitted from the road's surface has
on the refraction index of the air right above the road, as a result of
which light rays coming from the sun curve, and it appears as though the
sun is reflected from a puddle. That is what an optical illusion
is--things appear differently from the way they really are, and they
continue to appear differently even after we learn the truth of the
matter. Of two lines of equal length, embedded in a certain geometrical
configuration (the Muller-Lyer diagram), one looks longer than the
other, and they continue to appear unequal in length even after it is
verified that they are not. This fact does not make us suspect that
perhaps they are unequal after all, rather, it compels us to explain why
they appear to be unequal. Similarly with tense, goes the rejoinder.
Events are not tensed, they do not have a tensed location, but they
appear to be tensed, and they continue to appear tensed even when we
discover, in this case through conceptual analysis, that they are not.
This claim, insists the tenseless theorist, is entirely innocuous.
Philosophizing does not open impossible channels of cognition, but it
can modify and correct our understanding of the mechanism and reality
underlying our cognition. That is its purpose.
Well, the reason this attempt to salvage the tenseless view falls
has to do with the following crucial difference between tense and
optical illusions: in the case of optical illusions we can specify, and
in fact attain, conditions under which our perception is veridical. It
is only by reference to the way a truly wet road looks under such
conditions that talk of a road appearing to be wet makes sense.
Similarly, it is only due to the fact that there are circumstances under
which we can in fact verify that the two lines in the Muller-Lyer
diagram are equal in length that we can so much as describe the diagram
as an optical illusion. To say meaningfully that the lines appear
unequal in length, we need to have the notion "equal in
length." Thus, only if there are circumstances that equip us with
this notion, circumstances under which we could correctly say of the
lines that they are equal in length, can we speak here of an illusion,
of a situation in which they appear unequal though they are not. More
generally, the word "illusion" designates a distinction
between the way something looks under one set of circumstances, and the
way it looks under different conditions, for example, between the way a
patch of asphalt appears at a distance on a hot day, and the way it
looks when observed from close by; or between the way two lines look
when they are embedded in a certain configuration with other lines, and
the way they look outside of this configuration. In fact, applications
of the notion "illusion" make tacit use of two veridical
perceptions. For example, we invoke both (a memory of) a perception of a
wet road and a perception of a dry road to describe both how the road
looks--it looks wet, and how it really is--it is dry.
The hypothesis that experience, thought, and language may be
systematically misleading is not new. However, it was always necessary
to invoke veridical cases in order to raise it. Descartes assumed we
knew what dreaming is when he articulated the possibility that what we
take to be our waking experiences are in fact dreams. Ayer had to
presuppose our acquaintance with bent sticks to so much as suggest that
a stick in water looks bent, that is, that the perception of a stick in
a glass of water is, as he put it, "delusive." (40) To repeat,
the word "illusion" describes a distinction between the way
things appear under different circumstances, and refers to those
situations in which things appear the way they would if different
circumstances were to obtain. The upshot of this is that the word
"illusion" evokes (tacitly) conditions other than those that
actually obtain.
But what could such conditions possibly be in the case of tense?
The problem is that with tense we have no clue, cannot have a clue, as
to what conditions other than those that obtain could be. In fact, the
very purpose of employing the word "illusion" in this case is
to assert that such circumstances, circumstances in which the illusion
were somehow neutralized, cannot so much as be conceived. Here we can
not draw the distinction between the way things appear under certain
circumstances and the way they really are, because we cannot describe
circumstances under which they would appear differently from the way
they do, or from the way they are. Again, it is entailed by the very
claim that tense is an illusion that we cannot under any circumstances
have access to veridical perceptions. If we could, tense would no longer
be an illusion! The same is the case with the way we think and speak
about events in the world, not only with the way we perceive them. This,
of course, is a serious problem, for it turns out that speaking of tense
as an illusion amounts to asserting that there is no nontensed realm of
experience, thought, or discourse which would furnish the acquisition of
the concepts required for describing tenses as illusions. If tense is an
illusion, then we cannot have access to that the contrast with which
warrants describing tense as an illusion. Clearly, this is an
application of the term "illusion" which we cannot make sense
of--it is incoherent. On the one hand, it tacitly suggests that
tenseless reality is something that under certain conditions we can gain
access to, but on the other, its function is to indicate that this
reality is always and forever veiled from us and out of reach. Thus,
using the word "illusion" in this context requires that we
remove ourselves from our heads and take our inevitably tensed minds for
a stroll in the tenseless fields of reality. And that even philosophers
cannot do.
To sum up, the use made of the word "illusion" in the
statement that tense is an illusion cannot be the ordinary use we make
of it in other contexts. One important feature of its ordinary use--the
conceivability of veridical perceptions--is absent. This observation
does not constitute a blanket argument against all versions of the
tenseless view. It merely aims to highlight that, contrary to the way it
is often introduced, the thesis that tense is an illusion is not
self-explanatory. A theory is necessary in order to make it
intelligible. The token-reflexive account of tensed sentences might have
functioned as such a theory were it not for its own structural flaws.
There are other arguments with which philosophers attempt to expound and
defend the tenseless view of time. The scope of this paper does not
permit a discussion of them. I can only remark that I have not found
them to be more promising than the arguments studied here and that thus,
the idea that tense is an illusion remains, in my view, incoherent.
As indicated in the introduction, I believe the tenseless view is
driven by an important insight, namely, that the present is not
ontologically privileged. More than anything else, what gets tenseless
theorists going is the need to react to the attempts of tensed theorists
to anchor the distinction between the present and the past and future in
some metaphysical theory which explains how the present is more real. I
believe that the reaction of the tenseless camp is a valid one, but only
so long as it remains a criticism of a doctrine that cannot be made
sense of. When this reaction evolves beyond the scope of a mere
criticism and turns into the doctrine that tense is an illusion, it
begins to suffer from incoherence as well. (41)
Correspondence to: Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Humanities,
Bar-Ilan University, 52900 Ramat-Gan, Israel.
(1) I am not sure that Einstein had something like the tenseless
view in mind when he said these words. I think that what he intended was
that the impression that being past, present, or future are absolute
properties, rather than properties that are relative to a frame of
reference, is an illusion. This, will become evident, is very different
from what tenseless theorists mean by the claim that tense is an
illusion.
(2) A term first introduced by Hans Reichenbach in his Elements of
Symbolic Logic (New York: Free Press, 1966).
(3) Derek Parfit, "Rationality and the Metaphysics of
Time," unpublished paper, 7.
(4) It should be mentioned that some tensed theorists hold that the
past, as well as the present, is real. All of them agree, however, that
the future is not.
(5) David H. Mellor, Real Time (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1981), 4-5.
(6) Parfit, "Rationality and the Metaphysics of Time," 7.
(7) Mellor, Real Time, 6.
(8) Michael Dummett, "A Defense of McTaggart's Proof of
the Unreality of Time," in Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978), 356.
(9) Parfit, "Rationality and the Metaphysics of Time," 3.
(10) Mellor, Real Time, 58. To this Mellor adds: "i.e., there
are no tensed facts." Parfit finds the denial of tensed facts both
unnecessary and indefensible. According to him there are such facts, and
the sentences that state them "can be straightforwardly true of
false." But tensed statements are subjective, in the sense that
they are perspectival: "they describe reality from a particular
subject's point of view"; Parfit, "Rationality and the
Metaphysics of Time," 7.
(11) Mellor, Real Time, 24.
(12) Mellor, Real Time, 140.
(13) Nelson Goodman, The Structure of Appearance (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1951), 295.
(14) This formulation of the example is from Dummett, The Reality
of the Past, Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1978), 373.
(15) Mellor, Real Time, 74.
(16) Using "this very sentence" rather than "this
sentence" would not make much of a difference, for there might
still be some uncertainty as to what the new phrase, "this very
sentence," refers to. The context might be such that it is clear
that it refers to the sentence being uttered now, but in that case the
response is in effect tensed. I shall return to this point later.
(17) Mellor, Real Time, 75.
(18) Mellor, Real Time, 6.
(19) Mellor, Real Time, 92.
(20) The second chapter of Mellor's book Real Time provides a
detailed and helpful elucidation of this distinction.
(21) Parfit, "Rationality and the Metaphysics of Time,"
1.
(22) Mellor, Real Time, 34.
(23) Mellor, Real Time, 39.
(24) Mellor, Real Time, 40.
(25) Mellor, Real Time, 40, 34.
(26) Mellor, Real Time, 40.
(27) Mellor, Real Time, 41.
(28) Mellor, Real Time II (London and New York: Routledge, 1998),
32.
(29) Mellor, Real Time II, 31.
(30) Mellor, Real Time II, 34.
(31) Mellor, Real Time, 140.
(32) Mellor, Real Time, 24.
(33) Parfit, "Rationality and the Metaphysics of Time,"
7.
(34) Mellor, Real Time, 75 (italics in the original).
(35) Mellor, Real Time, 75.
(36) Some tenseless theorists take tense to be perspectival (like
the "hereness" of a place) and claim that we are subject to an
illusion if we fail to recognize its perspectival nature. I address this
interpretation of the assertion that tense is an illusion in a paper
entitled "Space and Time--Some (dis)Analogies," Iyyun 49
(January 2000): 61-72.
(37) Mellor, Real Time, 92.
(38) Mellor, Real Time, 24.
(39) Mellor, Real Time, 78.
(40) This fact is, of course, the basis of Austin's adamant
criticism (in his Sense and Sensibilia [Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1962]) of Ayer's attempt to draw from such cases the conclusion
that all we ever perceive are sense data.
(41) I am greatly indebted to Hilary Putnam, Derek Parfit, Charles
Parsons, Yemima Ben-Menahem, and Ruth Weintraub for helpful comments on
earlier versions of this paper. I would also like to thank the Sydney
Edelstein Center for the History and Philosophy of Science at the Hebrew
University in Jerusalem for a fellowship that made writing this paper
possible.