Just Interpretations: Law Between Ethics and Politics.
Mossoff, Adam
ROSENFELD, Michael. Just Interpretations: Law Between Ethics and
Politics. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998. xii + 296 pp.
Cloth, $45.00--Anyone familiar with twentieth century legal philosophy
will easily concede Michael Rosenfeld's opening claim that
"the practice of legal interpretation has been mired in a deep and
persistent crisis" (p. 13). The source of this crisis is the
critical dissolution of the practice of law into mere politics, that is,
the unfettered, Hobbesian quest for power within society. In response,
legal philosophers have advanced various conceptions of law that are
conceptually or normatively distinct from either amoral politics or
controversial ethical norms. Rosenfeld's Just Interpretations
provides the reader with a broad-ranging survey of the source and nature
of the crisis at hand, and what he considers to be the best solution
available to the pluralistic, democratic polity of our post-modern
age--the substantive, normative principle of "comprehensive
pluralism."
In fact, one of the principal values of Just Interpretations is
Rosenfeld's extensive, critical analysis of the recent, diverse
work on the issue of legal interpretation. He adeptly presents the
critical challenge of deconstructionism, and the apparent disintegration
of legal interpretation into mere (political) interpretation. Although
the critical challenge to law reaches farther back than
deconstructionism--to the Legal Realists in the twenties and
thirties--his cogent exegesis of the nature and implications of the
deconstructionist project is quite illuminating.
Rosenfeld then discusses, and ultimately rejects, the various
theoretical attempts to differentiate law from ethics and politics. He
explicates both Stanley Fish's and Ernest Weinrib's "new
legal formalism," Niklas Luhmann's conception of legal
autopoiesis, and Jurgen Habermas's discourse-theoretical approach
to proceduralism. Finally, he elucidates Richard Posner's Law and
Economics and Richard Rorty's "neopragmatism," two
theories based on legal pragmatism. There are also brief references to
the work of John Pawls and Ronald Dworkin, and, adding some historical
perspective to the contemporary debate, he discusses some of the ideas
of Oliver W. Holmes, John S. Mill, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Thomas Hobbes,
and even Adam Smith. All in all, Rosenfeld has produced a well-rounded
survey of the controversy over legal interpretation within contemporary
jurisprudence.
However, Rosenfeld does not simply review the field of legal
philosophy. He directly engages each conception of law, and actively
enters into the discourse with his own analyses. He argues that
formalism, for instance, only masks substantive and controversial
ethical norms smuggled into these theories. Also, he argues that the
theses of Luhmann and Habermas ultimately fall prey to the threat of
either becoming "morally arbitrary" or requiring the
introduction of extralegal (ethical) norms. Thus, although Rosenfeld
finds certain concepts and methodologies within the aforementioned
conceptions of law useful in his own project, he concludes that any
attempt to bracket off law from the norms and values of politics and
ethics is an impossible task.
In illustrating this crucial critical theme, Rosenfeld discusses
interesting, up-to-date political and legal controversies. The questions
surrounding the adjudication of "hate speech" laws are used to
expose within legal pragmatism underlying normative choices concerning
the nature of practical consequences. The debate over abortion--with its
unique metaphysical, normative, and political quandaries--is another
counter-example which arises often in Rosenfeld's critical
analyses. He also returns to abortion in his positive exposition of
comprehensive pluralism, acknowledging that "comprehensive
pluralism cannot resolve the conflict over abortion, but it can reduce
the tensions that surround it" (p. 274). It is refreshing to read a
philosopher directly confronting a difficult case in expounding his own
thesis.
Unfortunately, it is impossible within a brief review to do justice
to Rosenfeld's conception of comprehensive pluralism as a
counterfactual ideal for just legal interpretation. Nonetheless, the
project represented by his slogan "pluralism as norm is best for
pluralism in fact" (p. 200) is quite unique and provocative. The
fact that he believes that law must take into account the political and
ethical norms of our pluralist polity is appealing to one's
postmodern intuitions. Overall, Rosenfeld's book, particularly with
respect to his critical survey of the discourse to date, is an
interesting contribution to the raging debate over legal interpretation.
--Adam Mossoff, University of Chicago Law School.