The Structure of Liberty: Justice and the Rule of Law.
Mossoff, Adam
BARNETT, Randy. The Structure of Liberty: Justice and the Rule of
Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998. xi + 347 pp. Cloth, $29.95--The most
famous contemporary work advancing the principles of classical
liberalism and libertarianism is Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State,
and Utopia, published in 1974. Twenty-five years later on the opposite
bank of the Charles River, Boston University law professor Randy E.
Barnett now hopes to pick up the libertarian mantle with his first
published book, The Structure of Liberty. Advancing what he simply calls
"liberalism" (a term that I will use throughout the review to
refer to Barnett's synthesis of classical liberalism and
libertarianism), he offers fresh arguments for theories that many might
have considered to have already received their preeminent expression in
Nozick's earlier work.
The reason for the surprising relevance of The Structure of Liberty
is twofold. First, drawing upon his knowledge and experiences as a law
professor, and before that as a prosecutor in Chicago, Barnett quickly
leaves the realm of theory to study the application of the principles he
is proposing. In fact, the Introduction to the book--a theoretical
exposition of natural law and natural rights--concludes with his
expression of frustration with contemporary political and legal
philosophers because "they usually focus exclusively on such
philosophical issues and never get around to showing how such an
approach actually works" (p. 24). The rest of the book is thus
dedicated to explaining how liberalism serves as a solution to pervasive
problems affecting everyone in organized society.
Second, Barnett does not focus the themes of his work around
answering objections raised against liberalism. To the contrary, the
majority of the book contains original exegeses on the purpose,
function, and implications of the principles of liberalism. Barnett
writes: "The thesis of this book [is] how certain rights and
procedures that define the liberal conception of justice and the rule of
law address the serious and pervasive problems of knowledge, interest,
and power" (p. 314). Thus, throughout the core of the book, Barnett
discusses these three pervasive problems and how the myriad principles,
rules, and institutions of liberalism provide indispensable solutions.
Nonetheless, philosophers in particular will probably find the
concluding section of the book the most interesting and germane. It is
here that Barnett addresses common themes of contemporary political
philosophy, such as the neutrality thesis, Rawls's
"impoverished view" (p. 315) of rights, distributive justice,
and the nature of public-policy analysis. The central theme of this
final section can be summed up as: the limits of criticism.
This theme is best exemplified in Barnett's analysis of the
neutrality thesis. He poignantly questions the premise behind the
neutrality critique itself; asking if the charge of hypocrisy and lack
of neutrality really establishes any truth about the ordering of society
at all. Simply because one has allegedly proven the non-neutral status
of liberal political associations, then that does not by itself
establish the legitimacy of adopting an explicitly non-neutral political
system. "If we have learned nothing else from the millions of
killings we have witnessed in the twentieth century," writes
Barnett, "we have learned that the problems of power are only
magnified when force is used to assure compliance with a vision of `the
good'" (p. 307). The pervasive problems of knowledge, power,
and interest that give rise to the liberal conception of justice and the
rule of law do not disappear if liberalism is allegedly non-neutral in
any meaningful way.
It is difficult to convey the comprehensiveness of The Structure of
Liberty, and raise the questions that still need to be asked. Given the
scope of Barnett's project, he comes to many conclusions that
should be questioned. This is particularly the case in the latter
portions of the book in which he reaches some radical libertarian
conclusions, such as critiquing the "vicious cycle of public
property, public police, and public prisons" (p. 221). Regardless
of one's final conclusions regarding the merit of Barnett's
liberalism, this book is certainly a must-read for anyone concerned with
studying, or refuting, these ideas.--Adam Mossoff, University of Chicago
Law School.
(*) Books received are acknowledged in this section by a brief
resume, report, or criticism. Such acknowledgement does not preclude a
more detailed examination in a subsequent Critical Study. From time to
time, technical books dealing with such fields as mathematics, physics,
anthropology, and the social sciences will be reviewed in this section,
if it is thought that they night be of special interest to philosophers.