Christians Among the Virtues: Theological Conversations with Ancient and Modern Ethics.
Lewis, V. Bradley
Hauerwas, Stanley and Pinches, Charles. Christians among the Virtues:
Theological Conversations with Ancient and Modern Ethics. Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1997. xvii + 230 pp. Cloth, $29.95--This
volume engages the contemporary revival of interest in the virtues among
philosophers and theologians and aims to articulate a distinctively
Christian contribution to this conversation through (1) a selective
discussion of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics; (2) critical
discussions of three leading proponents of virtue ethics: Alasdair
MacIntyre, Martha Nussbaum, and John Casey; and (3) a practical display
of the distinctively Christian contribution to the recovery of virtue
theory in discussions of the virtues of hope, courage, obedience, and
patience. The purpose of the authors is both cautionary and suggestive.
They wish to caution that any Christian appropriation of virtue ethics
must entail a transformation of our understanding of the virtues, and to
suggest the shape of virtues so transformed.
The discussion of Aristotle serves to remind us of the classical
form of virtue ethics and concentrates on Aristotle's conception of
happiness as essentially temporal for human beings and explicable with
reference to the metaphor of the happy life as a journey rather than as
a point of arrival. Similarly, the authors see the virtues not as ends
in themselves, but as dispositions which help us on the journey and thus
as the "form" of the happy life. Finally, they treat the theme
of friendship in Aristotle, emphasizing the extent to which philia and
the virtues are inseparable from one another. They also suggest what
Christians should see as some limitations of Aristotle's account,
namely, the extent to which philia likens the friends to one another and
thus threatens to eliminate the "otherness" of the friend.
Similarly, they raise doubts about Aristotle's statements that
friends will attempt to insulate one another from their own suffering.
Both of these doubts question the goal of self-sufficiency toward which
Aristotle's view of the virtues points and a conception of the
virtues themselves as a kind of armor intended to insulate us from the
vicissitudes of human life.
The second part of the book is composed of three critical
encounters. The first suggests instabilities within MacIntyre's
work inasmuch as in building on Aristotle's conception of the
virtues, it builds on what John Milbank, in his own criticism of
MacIntyre, calls a "politics of violence and exclusivity" (p.
62) at odds with a Christian conception of the virtues. Hauerwas and
Pinches also criticize Martha Nussbaum for reading liberal assumptions
about the separation of public from private life into her discussion of
the relationship of friendship and politics in Aristotle, suggesting
instead that a Christian ecclesial context provides a more adequate
account of friendship. Their general argument is that Christianity
provides a more satisfactory understanding of the "fragility"
of the human condition which is at the center of Nussbaum's
discussion. Finally, the authors criticize John Casey's attempt to
find in classical pagan virtue a more satisfactory notion of personhood than that available in those rule-based accounts which he sees as the
common legacy of both Christianity and the Enlightenment. Casey makes
friendship understood in the context of the classical polls the center
of his argument, but he never articulates a viable model of community
which could serve as such a context for us. So his account loses the
very particularity which he seeks as an alternative to modern
abstraction. Hauerwas and Pinches again put forth the church as such a
context.
The last part of the book is the most impressive and the most
difficult to summarize. There the authors move toward a more
constructive Christian account of the virtues which they explicate in
discussions of hope as the growing receptivity that Christians show to
grace, and of courage as a virtue centered not in warfare, but in the
demands of martyrdom. There are also enlightening discussions of the
senses in which obedience can and cannot be seen as a virtue, and of
patience as essentially linked to the Christian view of divine
providence.
These last four chapters are rich and deserve wide readership. The
earlier part of the book is less satisfying, largely because of the
haste with which many of its points are made. This is particularly the
case in the treatment of Aristotle, who is interpreted as something of a
spokesman for the ethos of the classical city and its demands for a
virtue grounded in military prowess. A more careful engagement with
Aristotle, or Plato, would show the extent to which both were deeply
critical of this ethos. Their own constructive accounts pointed toward
the virtues necessary for the life of inquiry, and thus toward
discontinuities between conventional civic virtue and human excellence
as such. With respect to Aristotle, this raises the vexed questions
surrounding the interpretation of Ethics X, questions which receive only
brief acknowledgment from Hauerwas and Pinches. Many of these issues are
suggested in earlier parts of the Ethics as well, albeit delicately and
with an eye to Aristotle's likely audience which did value warrior
virtue and the honor which was its chief reward. These problems with
their discussion of Aristotle seem not unrelated to the extent to which
the authors are insufficiently critical of Casey's monolithic
picture of "pagan virtue" and too ready to accept
Milbank's criticisms of MacIntyre, criticisms based on a similar
picture of classical philosophy, as well as on a postmodernism which
raises a host of other difficulties. This is a very interesting volume,
part of the appeal of which lies in its civil and serious engagement
with scholars whose perspectives differ sharply with that of the
authors.