Etudes sur les philosophies Hellenistiques: Epicurisme, stoicisme, Scepticisme.
Allen, James
BRUNSCHWIG, Jacques. Etudes sur les philosophies Hellenistiques:
Epicurisme, stoicisme, Scepticisme. Evry-Cedex: Presses Universitaire de
France, 1995. 364 pp. Cloth, FF 248.00--Jacques Brunschwig's
collection of papers, Etudes sur les philosophies Hellenistiques:
Epicurisme, stoicisme, Scepticisme follows close on the heels of his
similar, though not identical, Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1994). It performs the same valuable
service for Francophone readers that was performed for Anglophone
readers by the English volume: it makes available for the first time in
French articles that originally appeared in English along with a
selection of pieces first published in French. The only serious
complaint I can imagine against either volume concerns the decision to
exclude certain pieces from each. Yet one should not be greedy; this is
a splendid collection which gives ample cause for gratitude as it is.
Like its English counterpart, this collection contains twelve
pieces. It may perhaps be worth singling out for special mention three
pieces that made signal contributions to the issues they take up when
they first appeared in English and are therefore likely to be especially
welcome here. "Definir la demonstration" is a, or rather the,
pathbreaking study of the accounts of proof transmitted by the
Pyrrhonian skeptic, Sextus Empiricus. By dint of painstaking
archeological work, Brunschwig is able to separate the different strata
of this very confusing but potentially very illuminating discussion, in
this way bringing to light a complex and philosophically exciting set of
developments within Stoic thinking about this subject.
"L'argument des berceaux chez les Epicuriens et chez les
Stoiciens" is a comparative study of the uses to which the Stoics
and Epicureans put the so-called cradle argument: the appeal to the
behavior of infants in order to arrive at an understanding of human
nature before it is hopelessly perverted by the corrupting influence of
society. Brunschwig throws light not only on the ethical issues at
stake, but on how the adherents of a philosophical position understand
the considerations they offer in support of first principles which they
regard as in some way too obvious to be established by argument in the
usual way. "Le probleme de l'heritage conceptual dans le
scepticisme: Sextus Empiricus et la notion de [GREEK TEXT NOT
REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] investigates, with special attention to the
criterion, the too seldom recognized questions raised by Sextus'
use of a conceptual framework to classify and describe the competing
dogmatic positions he subjects to skeptical examination. How, Brunschwig
asks, can a skeptic, officially detached from dogmatic theory, employ a
framework which is far from free from theoretical commitments and is the
product of the contingencies of its own curious history?
One of the reviewer's privileges is to pursue a little further
a question raised in the work under review. "La formule [GREEK TEXT
NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] chez Sextus Empiricus" defends a broadly
deflationary interpretation of the phrase "insofar as it is a
matter of logos" that has been assigned a more philosophically
pregnant part in some recent interpretations of Pyrrhonism. This kind of
view takes the phrase, at least sometimes, to
characterize--globally--the way in which the skeptic raises questions
and suspends judgment about the matters that come under his
consideration. He does so, on this view, insofar as it is a matter of
reason or philosophical reflection or something along these lines. This
way of putting into question and suspending judgment can then be
contrasted with a way in which the skeptic does not put into question or
suspend judgment about a matter, that is, it is somehow compatible with
the skeptic's claim that he goes along with or follows the
phenomena. Brunschwig, on the other hand, takes the phrase, as a rule,
to have a local significance, relative to a particular context and the
logos at issue in it.
Brunschwig's case presents a stiff challenge, but all the same
I think that there is something to be said for a view of the kind he
opposes. His discussion is focused on the first occurrence of the phrase
at PH 1.20, where Sextus is concerned to answer the charge that the
skeptic abolishes the phenomena. "We inquire," Sextus says,
"not about the phenomena, but about what is said about them ... for
example, honey seems to us to be sweet, which we grant ... but we
continue to inquire as to whether it is sweet so far as the logos is
concerned." Brunschwig offers us a choice between anaphoric and
nonanaphoric interpretations of logos. At first glance, it might seem
that the kind of view I am defending is best served by a nonanaphoric
interpretation of logos as something like philosophical theory, which
has not been referred to in the immediate context. Yet it does not have
to be abandoned if we adopt an anaphoric interpretation that takes logos
to refer to "what is said about the phenomena," as Brunschwig
persuasively argues that we should. For "what is said about the
phenomena" could refer to the whole range of arguments and
counter-arguments about whether appearances afford us an accurate grasp
of the way things are.
I believe that this interpretive possibility does not emerge
clearly because Brunschwig insists on too close a connection between
grammatical and philosophical interpretations in the two anaphoric
interpretations he offers--an adverbial reading in which "so far as
it is a matter of logos" belongs to "we inquire," and an
object-orientated reading in which it is attached to the object under
investigation, namely, that honey is sweet. For he supposes that on the
first, adverbial reading the logos is the argument whose strength
furnishes the skeptic with his reason for doubting that honey is sweet,
while on the second, objectal reading it refers to the nonskeptic's
ground for supposing the opposite whose weakness is the basis of the
skeptic's doubt. Yet it seems to be a mistake to suppose that a
choice of this kind is at issue, because the skeptic's suspension
of judgment is not the result of his being moved by the arguments on one
side of a question and unimpressed by those on the other, but rather the
result of his being as impressed (or unimpressed) by one argument as by
the other. If the skeptic argues a little more insistently on one side
of an issue than the other--the side we are accustomed to call the
skeptical side--it is only because the other side has been well enough
handled by others (see M 7.443).
I suggest that we need an interpretation of logos here broad enough
to embrace both sides of the argument, for example, both Aristotelian
and Stoic arguments that, in the right conditions, perceptual
appearances afford us a grasp of reality and, say, Cyrenaic and
Democritean arguments which, in very different ways, call this into
question. Sextus goes on in the same chapter to say that even if he does
bring logoi against the phenomena, it is only to exhibit the rashness of
the dogmatists by showing how deceptive the logos can be. Logos clearly
must mean something like reason here. However I should like to suggest
that Sextus is not introducing a new logos, but proceeding to consider a
further question about the logos already under discussion, namely
whether the effects of reason applied to the appearances can be confined
as he has just suggested they can.
Scholarly disagreement should not obscure the fact that this paper
and its companions here represent contemporary writing about classical
philosophy at its very best. All will repay close and careful attention
and will be a source of pleasure and illumination to anyone interested
in Hellenistic philosophy.
James Allen, University of Pittsburgh.