Taking the universal viewpoint: a descriptive approach.
Wood, Robert E.
Today, in an epoch of the proclamation of radical
incommunicability between ethnic groups, between the sexes, and between
individuals sunk in the privacy of their own gratifications, supported
by a theoretical rejection of principles or universals of any sort, I
want to explore the possibility of "taking the universal
viewpoint" and thus finding a way out of a situation of radical
cultural disintegration without succumbing to one or the other mode of
intellectual imperialism, theological or otherwise. I will attempt to do
so by attending to what, I would claim, is the most obvious and showing
what is implicit in recognizing that. In focusing our attention, let us
attempt to set aside for the time being everything we might think we
know from other sources, science included: bracket temporarily all
theories, all dogmas, all preferences, all commitments other than that
of paying attention to what presents itself to careful attention here
and now. Nothing should intrude except the evidence present to us,
since, I would claim, that evidence is presupposed in appealing to these
other factors, including arguments for the "theory-ladenness"
of evidence.(1)
Besides this more general framework of concern, however, we should
keep in mind the direct presence of the written page both I and my
readers have in each of our sensory fields, though differently located
spatially and temporally. Further, since it is most likely that each of
us is reading a different reproduction of the same text -- I on the
computer screen, the readers on paper -- we should keep in mind the
differentiation between the sentences which are the same and their
spatio-temporal sensory instantiations which are different in each case.
Further still, since I might also read the paper to an audience, keep in
mind the differentiation between the sameness of the sentence in the
difference of sensory medium, visual and audile. We will return to that
later.
I
Let us begin within those two frames -- that of the general
cultural situation today and that of the status of the vehicle of
delivery of this essay -- and attend to the simple, trivial, and
seemingly uncontroversial recognition that something is. Of any entity
we consider, the most obvious and yet the least articulated thing we can
say about it is that "It is." "It is" can be said of
an indeterminate number of instances of whatever sort, including the
visible marks on this page or the sounds of my voice as I utter "It
is" to myself or to my interlocutors. "It is" is an
eidos, a universal, a one-over-many, capable of being applied to an
indeterminate number of instances. Further, "It is" exhibits
my recognition that whatever "it" might be, it stands outside
of not-being-at-all. Yet simultaneously we recognize that it is an
object of awareness, so that there is an essential distinction between
awareness and its objects. "Being" can be said of whatever
"it" we might consider, including oneself as considering it.
"Being" is an eidos or universal, object of reflective
awareness; but it is also more than an eidos, including as it does all
instances of being, eidetic and individual, and everything about them.
We quickly see then that there are at least six eide which show
themselves as sharing in being and as involved in the most universal and
indeterminate consideration which forms the framework for any
consideration: the eide of being, of instance, of object of awareness,
of awareness itself and, at another reflective level, of eidos itself
and of individual. They articulate what is implicit in our beginning
with the simple "It is"; they articulate being.
An eidos, in addition to its distinction from and relation to its
instances, involves a distinction between its universal mode and its
content. As eide all eide are the same in their universal mode but
differ in content. The instances of eide are either other eide -- as we
have shown thus far -- or ultimate individuals, functioning
spatio-temporal unities. As an eidos, each is identical in content in
all its individual instances but different in its universal mode. Each
eidos contains other eide within itself, namely those which define it;
some eide -- several of the ones we are watching unfold here -- contain
all other eide within themselves.
Being is a one which contains within itself many, a same which
includes difference, an "is" which contains an "is
not." Being is an encompassing one, and each eidos is a one over
and among many within that oneness. Each of the six eide are
self-identical, other than the others and both same and different with
respect to their ultimate individual instances, though an participate in
being. Being other, each is not any of the others. Further, the notions
of sameness and difference are each both the same as themselves and
different from each other, so that sameness shares in difference and
difference in sameness. Our inventory of implicit forms thus also
includes, in addition to the eide of being, of instance, of object of
awareness, of awareness itself and, at another reflective level, of
eidos itself and of individual, the eide of nonbeing, of unity and
multiplicity, and of sameness and difference, so that we have now eleven
eide.
Now as changing from implicit to explicit, the notion of being
undergoes development before the awareness of each of us who are
following it. This entails another kind of "not being": not
the simple otherness of the various eide we have shown thus far to be
implicit in the notion of being, nor the internal otherness in relation
to each other of the traits of each eidos, but the not-being of
antecedent and consequent states. Furthermore, what is involved here is
not simple succession but development, articulation moving toward
completion, from relatively empty to relatively fun vis-a-vis awareness
-- hence a teleological change. We might recall that the notion of
being, which contains these eide within itself, also sets itself off
from absolute nonbeing, so that, even prior to the development we are
following, to be at all is to be other than absolute not-being. So we
have a number of senses of nonbeing operative: absolute nonbeing, the
nonbeing of otherness between and within each entity and the nonbeing
involved in temporal antecedence and consequence (not-yet-being and
no-longer-being).
As the first individual instance of "It is," I will take
my own awareness of it. The reader is invited thereby to focus upon the
same considerations with respect to his or her "I" as reader.
I, as conscious entity here and now, am an ultimate individual instance
of awareness which, like any "it," is an instance of being.
Indeed, I am also an instance of the eidos "I" and an instance
of instance. Awareness is an eidetic instance; I am an ultimate
individual instance of the eide being, awareness, instance, individual,
and I, which entail one and many, sameness and difference, and
development which, in turn, entails antecedence and consequence.
The notion of instance, itself an eidos, is in its content either
an ultimate spatio-temporal individual or a universal. The eidos
"individual" here signifies space-time occupancy, located
within a determinate segment of space-time, the same in content but
different in mode of existence from its eide, and both same and
different with regard to its own past and future. Space-time occupancy
entails being one of an indefinite plurality of like instances of eide.
Abstraction from that plurality yields the eidos, though abstraction is
itself possible because space-time as a whole is anticipated in the
field of awareness able to attend to the eide, for an eidos is what is
recognizable as repeatable any time and any place the proper conditions
for its instantiation are met.
Occupants of space and time are both spread out in three
dimensions and separate from, though in some ways also continuous with,
other such objects. Each of the three dimensions in relation to the
others yields two opposite directions: for humans they are above and
below, in front and in back, to the right and to the left. For other
bodies on the earth which do not have the frontal orientation humans
have, above and below are present by reason of resting upon the earth,
and the opposing sides in the other two directions are without special
orientational names. Each dimension is given as spread indeterminately
about a given body. As occupying these dimensions, each individual is
composed of a multiplicity which contains a mode of otherness that
allows that multiplicity both to come together and to come apart.
Instantiating the eidetic as a spatio-temporal individual sets each
individual within an essentially mutable matrix. Space-time occupants
are thus in some way or another always other than they have been and
other than they will be -- actually in two senses: in an absolute sense
as not having been and as aimed toward no longer being the individuals
they are, and in a relative sense as no longer being, while they are,
what they were and as not yet being what they will be. Within the latter
context, they are nonetheless both in some respect identical and in
other respects nonidentical with themselves throughout that span. Within
the former context, there are, antecedent and consequent to their
origination and end, the elements which will enter or have entered into
their composition. The eidos "time," linked to the essential
transience of spatially extended individuals, exhibits the character of
past, present, and future -- of the no longer, the now, and the not yet,
with the past and the future spread indeterminately
"backwards" and "forwards" for our awareness -- and
this before any theory of time such as those offered by Aristotle,
Newton, or Heidegger.
All of this sets the invariant frame for the field of awareness
and, I would claim, applies indubitably to all we might consider,
including differences of worldview, differences of interpretation, and
even the self-contradictory nominalist or deconstructionist efforts to
displace the invariant and thus universal. All of this involves further
articulations of content as we advance into it. We are able to carry on
this articulation by an on-going reflection upon what we have already
seen, both on the side of the object of awareness and on the side of
awareness itself, so that the content has not been added from without
but unfolded from within and is implicit in any affirmation we might
make.
To recapitulate a bit: the notion of being is, minimally, the
notion of being outside of pure nonbeing. However, there is also a
relative sense of nonbeing in the otherness of each of the eide thus far
considered in their relations to each other and to their instances, and
in the otherness, both internal and external as well as both spatial and
temporal, involved in operative individuals. The relation between the
eidos and the individual instance involves an identity of content within
a difference of modality, individual in the one case and universal in
the other. As all-encompassing, the notion of being includes both
awareness and its objects. It includes as well all eide and every
spatio-temporal individual, and it includes them in such a way as to
include everything that may be discovered about all and each. It thus
sets a fundamental goal of awareness as a capacity to move toward the
horizon of all-encompassing awareness. We are following that direction
in articulating what is implicit in our initial focus upon "It
is." The notion of being poses a demand that an advance into any
entity or eidetic region circumscribing types of entities be located
within the never-fully-disclosed complete whole of all beings. Such an
advance involves showing how the notions of sameness and difference are
realized in different instances, eidetic and individual. It also raises
the question of the how of the relation of awareness to the whole -- a
consideration of the utmost importance for human life. Again, the one
encompassing notion of being shows itself to be intrinsically many
without fracturing its own unity.
II
Now to say all of that is to appeal to a community, to a
"we" bound together by the English language. It is to rest
upon a tradition available to literate members of that tradition, but
also to any human beings, for any human being can come to learn to speak
and read that language, to write and to translate what is said into
their own native language(s). There are several ways we can go from
there. One is to attend to the fact that "It is" is written,
fixed in black patterns appearing on a white background; it can also be
spoken, embedded in the sound patterns that succeed one another as they
disappear; in addition, it can be embossed on a flat surface in Braille.
In any case, it is the same "It is" appearing in the
differences of spatial fixity and temporal disappearance. In this
paragraph I have repeated the same expression "It is" three
different times in writing, instantiating it in three different spatial
locations by the temporary successive activity of typing. I recognize
that the same sentence can be instantiated an indeterminate number of
times and places in either media, visual or audile or, in the case of
Braille, tactual. Indeed, any visual or audile or tactual pattern is
indefinitely repeatable, like dimes from a mint or recordings from a
studio. Yet that involves, as its flip-side, an insight into myself: in
such recognition I as a reflective observer -- though at the same time
an organism and a sensory observer immersed in the Now -- have escaped
the Now of the immediate presence of sights and sounds and tactual
sensations by anticipating the whole of space and time as the field for
the possible instantiation of the eide involved in the situation that
come to be represented by the sensible patterns arising by convention in
a given ethnic community.
Of course, the meaning of "It is" can be realized also
in sentences coming out of different linguistic traditions: Greek estin,
Latin id est, French il y a, German es ist, and so forth. So the meaning
transcends not only spatio-temporal instantiation, but also linguistic
enculturation, though its apprehension requires both enculturated and
spatio-temporally immanent sensory instantiation. Again, as recognizing
that, I escape in a certain fashion not only embodiment, but also the
enculturation that makes possible my linguistic articulation of the
meaning.
As an instance of awareness, I address you through the medium of
writing. In a sense, in addressing you I in principle also address the
eidetic "you," any "you" able to read English, and,
by reason of the translatability of language, actually any human being.
Furthermore, I have written meaningful English sentences which, I would
claim, you and I can also judge to be true, that is, which function to
display what is available to any sufficiently reflective and attentive
awareness. We thus have a set of distinctions and relations between the
written or embossed or spoken spatio-temporal instances, the
enculturated sentence, the transculturally meaningful proposition
capable of being translated into a different cultural form, and the
judgment or truth-claim for which I take responsibility.
However, all this is also and essentially object of thought,
something manifest to awareness. Object as the manifest is contrasted
with the nonmanifest, which would either be simply outside of the object
in question or hidden within it. Consider as well the implicitly
functioning eide we have been attempting to make explicit here and the
hidden as such. The former is set within the field of awareness but
prefocal; the latter is not within the field of awareness. However, even
here we have to consider that in the notion of being everything is
included, though not like the implicit we have been unfolding thus far.
To reach toward the wholeness of each thing within the Whole, we have to
uncover the hidden from outside the level of complicating eide
constituting the framework of relation between awareness and its
objects.
Consider again the page upon which this writing appears as an
instance of a spatio-temporal individual. It stands within the field of
sensory awareness: a visible, tactual -- and also a possible olfactory,
auditory, and even gustatory object. Intrinsic to the character of each
of the senses is their fixation upon aspects of spatio-temporal
individuals. The individuals appearing as coordinated objects of the
various senses are each one spatio-temporal thing appearing through the
manyness of these aspects, each having its own set of eidetic features.
For example, as visual object it is colored, separated from my viewing
by apparently empty space, spread out in space and separate from other
things so spread out, appearing within a horizon and affording a set of
perspectives. Both horizon and perspectives are relative to the position
of the embodied viewer. As I move about the body or cause it to move
about by manipulation, the perspectives within each sensory field cohere with the perspectives within all of them. Though all of this occurs
within the privacy of my body-based perception, nonetheless what we have
said of it holds for all human perceivers, and indeed for all bodily
based perceivers with the same sensory equipment. Yet for the page to
appear as one through the manifold appearances it affords to the
different senses operating from different spatial positions in time, I
as viewer must myself in some sense be one through the time of the
various showings of the page in and throughout the various sensations. I
myself must be the locus of retaining and synthesizing experiences
through time, both at the sensory and at the eidetic levels.
The differing sensations are factually correlated with the
possession of specific types of organs which are arrangements of what
once were independent compounds via the process of nutrition and growth.
The process of growth is a coming to stand within predetermined limits
of self-sustaining processes of a functioning whole which+ constitutes
the adult state of the organism capable of feeding itself, of defending
itself, of reproducing and, in the higher mammals, of caring for its
offspring. Organic development is a gestalting process in relation to
the elements which yields a functioning whole. Parallel to, and as an
instance of, the unfolding of the initial notion of being, increasingly
complex ramifications of an initially relatively simple but
comprehensive entity is the condition for the possibility of organs for
perception coming to be. Perception is a gestalting process in relation
to the sensory elements entering into a configured appearance. Such a
process furnishes a desirous synesthetic-kinesthetic field as manifest
material for the next level of eidetic apprehension, interpretation from
the explicitly given to the implied, and choice based upon such
apprehension and interpretation.
The thinker has thus first of all to be an eater; but to be such
involves being oriented towards specific types of presentations, namely,
those that satisfy the needs of the organism. Thus an animal has to be
able to recognize features which involve the distinction between the
edible and the inedible, the beneficial and the harmful, under penalty
of organic dissolution. The theorist who disallows the eidetic continues
to exist by reason of being able to recognize instances of the eidetic.
An animal is also a reproducer, oriented via sexual desire to activities
which terminate in the production of offspring and to the desire to care
for them in their state of biological dependency. Only certain types of
acts oriented toward specific types of bodily loci in the type of entity
of the opposite sex lead to definite types of cells combining to bring
about initially a relatively independent and later independent, unified,
physiologically developing processive whole.
To activate such capacities, a sensorially desirous organism needs
not only to register sensations but to interpret the observed motions of
a member of the opposite sex as expressive of the inwardness of its own
desires. It needs, as an integrally functioning whole, to see and read
an integrally functioning whole. Especially in the case of encountering
other humans, the gaze of the conscious other expresses its inwardness,
which, unlike the sensory surface involved in expression, escapes the
transparency of the observing-desiring other. That surface can be read
because of past observation of its correlation with certain types of
behavior as well as by reflecting upon one's own state of mind in
similar circumstances.
A sensory power, whether cognitive (for example, sight) or
appetitive (for example, hunger or sexual desire), is a concretely
universal orientation toward the whole field of its objects, but it is
activated, only by particular instances. The recognition of power
entails activation by the universal orientations or types realized in
individual instances which are recognized by sensory activation. This
orientation we call "intellection" is of a kind oriented
towards kinds or eide. Intellection renders manifest the universality
implicit in possibilities of action and passivity to action.
Any entity within the field of experience can act and be acted
upon; each entity is of a determinate kind which circumscribes the range
of ways it can be acted upon and the ways in which it can act. This
instantiation of type and delineation of correspondent possibilities
linked to recognition of the repeatability and coordination of visual or
audile patterns are the objective bases for language and for that
developed and developing language we call science. In any case,
possibility involves a set of universal orientations, active and
passive, toward what is causally correlated with the type of entity
instantiated. A possibility is a concrete universal. Nonconscious
possibilities are actualized by individual things. The same is true for
possibilities for awareness at the sensory level. However, what we call
intellect is a concrete universal of a peculiar type: it is oriented,
via the notion of being, toward the whole of the experienceable and the
inferable and hence toward the whole of space and time. It is actualized
precisely by the recognition of the concrete universality implicit in
possibilities of entities and of their activities and passivities.
Intellect is an absolutely universal orientation actualized by the
concrete universal orientations ingredient in things.
This provides a privileged position for the intellectually endowed
organic entity. Oriented toward the whole, it stands beyond the here and
now of elemental, physiological, and sensing entities -- indeed, beyond
its own elemental, physiological, and sensing base. Pried thus loose
from the here-and-now, it is required to choose from among the
possibilities provided initially by the sense powers correlated with the
upsurge of physiological desire and subserving the growth, sustenance,
and reproduction of the organism. Its choices presuppose ways of
describing and interpreting as well as, following therefrom, ways of
acting. Its relation to its offspring and to those of its own kind
spatially proximate to it brings about the transfer of its patterns of
description, interpretation, and choice to others, contemporary and to
come. The dominant vehicle of such transfer is language, itself the
primordial transferred. The sedimented result of such transferred
patterns constitutes a culture. As oriented to the whole, however, each
individual human is pried loose from the Now of both physiology and
culture and condemned to choose. As such, the individual human has an
intrinsic value and dignity, an inviolability which sets the limit to
permissible encroachment by others. In its interior, its assent must be
free and uncoerced, an insight it has taken millennia to recognize and
to build into institutional structure.
Let us return to the beginning: "It is." It is written;
it can be spoken. In each case, we have a sensory presence addressed to
a reader or hearer. Even though immediately the reader or hearer may be
confined to the speaker or writer, in principle it is addressed to any
reader or hearer because it appeals to the universal human capacity for
eidetic recognition. The spoken words pass away as they are generated;
the written words remain through the flow of time. Yet each are taken
from an eidetic inventory, recognized or made and recorded by an
antecedent linguistic community. To get to the position of the sort of
reflection we are engaged in, one must first have grown from a
fertilized ovum to a perceiving, desiring, functioning adult, as well as
have been raised in a linguistic community, stamped by the way the
sedimented understandings and decisions of others have been factually
brought to bear upon each of our concrete formations. Yet the
recognition of all this involves an essential transcendence of the
limitations involved in the structures recognized and thus the
translatability of language.
This involves the general structure of what I call the I-Me.
"Me" is in the objective case: it is all that about myself to
which I can attend as an object. "I" is the center of a
person, before which everything else is object. The "I" is
correlate to the notion of being: referred to the whole, to everything
about everything, I am pried loose from any particular thing and can
reflect upon it and upon various given features of myself as
"Me." There are three levels to this Me": first is
genetic, the initial endowment given me by my parents; second is the
cultural shaping I have received, initially mediated through my parents,
but more broadly through all the influences that have impacted and
continue to impact upon me from my cultural environment; third is the
sedimented results of the choices I have made on the basis of those
other two factors. Here and now, the "Me" I have is the
concrete resultant of those three factors which provides a limited set
of real possibilities for choice. The "Me" exhibits a series
of zones more remote or more proximate to the "I." The
genetically produced, as biological ground, is furthest. Cultural
stamping lies closer and the history of past choices closer still.
Closest of all is the spontaneous identification with certain lines of
attraction centering in what a long tradition has called "the
heart." What is in my heart defines what is closest to me, what
attracts me without even having to reflect upon it. However, as pried
loose from everything determinate by reason of being by nature
indeterminately oriented toward the whole, I am perpetually condemned to
choose, to assess even my own heart and to shape the given
"Me" as the concrete artist's material into a meaningful
whole.
However, one must also have in one's heart the motivation to
carry on the inquiry we are undertaking and the lived distance, provided
by discipline and sedimented into habitual dispositions to act, from the
immediacy of appetite and thoughtless proclivity evoked by culture and
sustained by a history of personal choices. The immediate occasion for
the current inquiry is a concern about the skepticism introduced by
nominalism and deconstructionism regarding our ability to apprehend eide
-- that is, to rise above the privacy of our own sensations and feelings
and the limitations of our ethnicity in order to be the locus of the
apprehension of universal principles of order implicit in sensation and
in organic existence -- indeed, in the very character of spatio-temporal
existence itself.
The emergence of sensations correlated with organic need occurs
within certain thresholds within which those relational aspects of
things emerge out of the darkness of their total being to confront us as
needy and thus desirous sensors. Yet we are referred beyond the sensory
circle to what for sensation itself is a dark encompassing, but which,
for an awareness oriented toward being, is the source of all
understanding. We are referred to the full being of what appears through
the limited, subject-dependent, and hence culturally mediated way in
which that appearance happens. Hence the need for developing techniques
of inferring what lies beyond the immediately sensed, for interpreting
what is given.
The notion of being occupies one pole of the bipolar structure of
human nature whose other pole is organically based sensation. The notion
of being is the notion of the encompassing totality. Yet initially it is
an empty notion. We do not begin by knowing the whole; we rather exist
as the question of being. The notion of being as the notion of the whole
poses the fundamental task of bringing the organically based field of
sensory appearance in relation to the full being of things and of
ourselves, first by eidetic inventory whereby we locate the individually
given sensum within the whole of space-time, then by interpretation
which attempts to read the regularities on the sensory surface as
expressive of ultimate depth, and finally by choices among the options
for action made available by such understanding in order to form
one's heart. The way the notion of being is given involves a whole
set of eidetic structures that constitutes the enduring framework within
which the differences of understanding, choosing, and interacting occur.
One who begins to understand that has begun to practice a mode of
reflection that catches up with the founding structure of human
existence.
The relation to the whole of what is calls for the whole of what
we are as divinatory of what essentially lies hidden, but which
nonetheless essentially concerns us as oriented toward the full being of
what is ourselves included. That full relation is a relation of what a
long tradition has called "the heart." Its divination is not a
matter of our cognitive and practical conquests but a matter of learning
appreciative "letting be" through which beings make their
claim upon us, and we are gathered into our fullness as the other to
which otherness can appear as such. What we have uncovered provides the
enduring framework, not only for further conquests, but also for acting
out of the claim of otherness, our own as well as that of others. That,
however, is another story.
III
The description I have given, I would claim, uncovers the major
features of the invariant framework of all our experience. It puts us in
a position to understand how the major questions in the history of
thought came to be and allows us some measure of the adequacy of the
proffered answers in terms of how they do justice to those aspects of
experience we have uncovered. However, our inventory does not provide
answers to questions as to the origin of that field and indeed of the
universe within which it operates. It settles nothing regarding the
coming into being of species, the relation between matter and form, life
and matter, consciousness and life, intellect and awareness. It does not
even broach the question of the ontological status of the eidos. It says
nothing directly about possible immortality or the existence and
properties of God. It does not settle burning questions concerning what
we are to do, which options to select among the myriad possible, or the
ground of the authority that might determine those selections. It says
nothing of possible revelation, of religious pluralism and authority. It
has no direct relation to all the technical problems of how to achieve
the various goals given by nature, conditioned by culture, or selected
by individuals. However, it does make us aware of the common field from
which all of the above spring and in which they have to operate. And its
dispassionate pursuit puts us in the position of some distance from the
passions invested in living out these other quests. It teaches us to be
less partisan and more understanding as regards the various competing
claims involved. It creates a clearing in our mutual worlds, open to all
humankind. It imposes upon us a dialogical imperative to give witness to
our own, to attempt to understand and weigh the various construals of
what lies hidden beneath, beyond, and encompassing the field of
awareness as that to which we are all, as humans, essentially directed,
and to let ourselves be measured by what emerges from that quest.
Correspondence to: Department of Philosophy, University of Dallas, 1845
East Northgate Drive, Irving, TX 75062-4799. (1) Outside this note, this
essay will employ no footnotes. Following Husserl, it claims to attend
"to the things themselves." However, the historically informed
reader will find similar insights in Plato's Theatetus and Sophist,
in Aristotle's On the Soul and Metaphysics, in Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit and Science of Logic as well as in
Husserl's Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, vols.
I and II, and Bernard Lonergan's Insight: A Study of Human
Understanding (New York: Harper and Row, 1978) -- works which have
taught us how to attend to "the things themselves." This
should also help verify Heidegger's claim that phenomenology is a
return to Plato and Aristotle (Prolegomena to a History of the Concept
of Time [Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991], 136). For a
different but related approach to the themes developed in this essay,
see my A Path into Metaphysics: Phenomenological, Hermeneutical and
Dialogical Studies (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990).
For a positioning of these considerations within a cosmological context,
see my "Being and Manifestness: Philosophy, Science, and Poetry in
an Evolutionary Worldview," International Philosophical Quarterly
35, no. 4 (1995): 438-47.