The development of physical influx in early eighteenth-century Germany: Gottsched, Knutzen, and Crusius.
Watkins, Eric
Standard histories of modern philosophy(1) tend to view causality in the following way: After Descartes distinguishes between the mind and
the body as two radically different kinds of substance, it becomes
problematic as to how such substances could act on each other. Thus,
Malebranche develops Occasionalism, which solves the problem by denying
that any finite substance has any causal efficacy whatsoever, and
Leibniz, dissatisfied with what he sees to be the perpetual miracles
involved in the Occasionalist solution, develops Pre-established
Harmony, according to which a substance can act, but only on itself.
Hume, by inheriting an empiricist account of meaning, is then seen to
criticize the very notion of causality insofar as it requires a
necessary connection between cause and effect. Such histories typically
end with Kant, who attempts to show the incoherence of Hume's
critique in his Second Analogy of Experience. There are numerous
difficulties with this picture. One is that Kant's contributions to
the issue of causality are not exhausted by his reply to Hume in the
Second Analogy, since Kant reacts to Leibniz in the Third Analogy as
well as in other passages.(2) Another, related difficulty is;that on
this picture Leibniz's Pre-established Harmony seems to have no
effect on the rest of modern philosophy. This is simply wrong, and what
makes it wrong is a philosophically interesting story, namely the
development in early eighteenth-century Germany of a view Leibniz
opposes to Pre-established Harmony and occasionalism and dubs
"influxus physicus" or "Physical Influx."(3)
Before the story can be told, however, some stage-setting is
necessary. First, it is important to be clear about the most basic
doctrines of Pre-established Harmony, Occasionalism, and Physical
Influx.(4) Physical Influx asserts intersubstantial causation amongst
finite substances.(5) For instance, when I appear to kick a ball, I
really am the cause of the ball's motion. Pre-established Harmony
denies intersubstantial causation, but affirms intrasubstantial
causation. According to Pre-established Harmony, then, I am not the
cause of the ball's motion, but rather the ball is simply causing
itself to move (through the unfolding of its complete concept, in
Leibniz's version). Occasionalism, like Pre-established Harmony,
denies intersubstantial causation, but, unlike Pre-established Harmony,
it denies intrasubstantial causation as well. Occasionalism typically
asserts that God alone, that is, an infinite substance, is the cause of
all changes, and thus of the ball's motion. Though there are other
ways of defining these causal theories, this way has the advantage that
the causal theories form an exhaustive disjunction.(6)
Second, since I shall be focusing primarily on Pre-established
Harmony and Physical Influx, it is worth considering Leibniz's
reasons for rejecting Physical Influx and supporting Pre-established
Harmony. Leibniz presents two main objections to Physical Influx. First,
he repeatedly objects that physical influx is inconceivable because it
is incomprehensible how one substance could act on another substance,
that is, that an accident from one substance could be transferred or
migrate to another substance.(7) Second, he argues that Physical Influx
implies a violation of the laws of nature, more specifically, the law of
conservation of motion. The idea is that if the mind were to act on the
body so as to cause motion, then there would be more motion in the world
after the mind's action on the body than beforehand, which is a
clear violation of the law of the conservation of motion.(8) Leibniz
develops a number of arguments for Pre-established Harmony. For example,
in A New System of Nature he claims that Pre-established Harmony is at
least possible, since God clearly has the power to endow a substance
with an internal force that brings about all its later states. Moreover,
it is also the most probable hypothesis because (1) Occasionalism
requires perpetual miracles and Physical Influx encounters the
aforementioned difficulties and (2) Pre-established Harmony has numerous
advantages (for example, it displays our freedom, and the immortality of
the soul and it allegedly provides a new proof for the existence of
God).(9) I take it that his main positive argument, however, is that a
substance (which is defined as something independent of other finite
beings and self-sufficient, that is, something that has, to use
Leibniz's own term, a complete concept) has no need for the causal
activity of other substances.(10) Any causation from without would
necessarily be overdetermination (something for which Leibniz has no
sympathy). Leibniz may also think that a real relation between
substances (as a causal relation would be) is impossible due to the
essential reducibility of relations to monadic properties.(11) Thus,
Leibniz presents important arguments in favor of Pre-established
Harmony.
Third, the intellectual-political situation in Germany in the first
part of the eighteenth century requires brief characterization.
Intellectually, there are two main camps: on the one hand, the Pietists,
led by August Hermann Francke, Philipp Jakob Spener, and Joachim Lange,
and, on the other, the Aufklarer, that is, proponents of the
Enlightenment, whose intellectual leader is Christian Wolff.
Accordingly, when Wolff publishes his major treatise on metaphysics in
1719-20 (significantly, in German), entitled Vernunfftige Gedancken von
Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen uberhaupt,
(a work now commonly referred to as simply the German Metaphysics), the
Pietists finally have in their hands the material they need in order to
launch a full-scale attack on Wolff. Despite the fact that Wolff is very
cautious in his acceptance of Pre-established Harmony (ultimately he
affirms it in its unrestricted form only for the mind-body relationship,
not for body-body relationships), this odd and perhaps even
dangerous-sounding doctrine is sufficient for Lange and several of his
followers(12) to begin their assault because it seems to them to result
in determinism, fatalism, and Spinozism. To make a long story short,
Wolff wins the battle philosophically, in part because Lange and his
followers are not particularly philosophically acute. However, at least
in the short run, the Pietists win the battle politically. For during a
series of exchanges between Wolff and his Pietist opponents, the
Pietists resort to political means to ensure victory, namely, so the
story goes, by intimating to King Frederick William I that, according to
Pre-established Harmony, a soldier who deserted from the army could not
be held responsible for his action because it was already determined
beforehand that he had to do it. Frederick William I is naturally not at
all disposed to tolerate such a dangerous doctrine and thus on November
8, 1723 gives Wolff 24 hours to leave Prussia or be executed.
(Wolff's German Metaphysics is also prohibited from being taught at
Prussian universities.) Wolff naturally favors expulsion and leaves for
Marburg, where he had previously been offered a chair.(13) (I should
note that the Pietists' victory is relatively short-lived, since
already in 1740 Wolff returns to Halle upon Frederick II's repeated
invitation. In fact, Frederick II even attempts to bring Wolff to Berlin
to be codirector of the Prussian Academy of Sciences along with
Maupertuis, but Wolff, now suspicious of royal whims as well as of the
anti-Wolffian bent of the Academy, politely declines. Also, one can
imagine how banishment might make one popular amongst intellectuals of
the day. Thus, in part due to the political situation and in part due to
his greater philosophical ability, Wolff quickly gains a large
following, including figures such as Thummig, Bilfinger, Reusch,
Baumeister, Baumgarten, Meier, and Hollmann,(14) to name but a few.) At
any rate, the effect of these intellectual-political events is that both
Wolffians and Pietists, that is, both camps, give serious philosophical
consideration to what is at least prima facie the source of the debate,
namely Pre-established Harmony, Occasionalism, and Physical Influx.(15)
Although this stage-setting raises a number of important
issues,(16) I shall focus on just one: the development of a version of
Physical Influx that is responsive to Leibniz's criticisms and that
even has plausible arguments in its favor. What we shall find is that a
relatively sophisticated version of Physical Influx emerges from 1732 to
1745 in the writings of Johann Christoph Gottsched, Martin Knutzen, and
August Friedrich Crusius. Further, it is interesting to note that two of
the three figures who are instrumental in developing Physical Influx,
namely Gottsched and Knutzen, are Wolffians, not Pietists.(17)
I
Gottsched's Version of Physical Influx. Gottsched is perhaps
best known at present for his literary efforts, since he is often
considered to be the first major literary figure of the German
Enlightenment. Yet Gottsched is offered and accepts a chair in
metaphysics on the basis of his dissertations in philosophy, entitled
Vindiciarum systematis influxus physici (1727-29)(18) and his Erste
Grunde der gesammten Weltweisheit (1733-34), which is a shortened
rendition of Wolff's philosophical system that contributed
significantly to Wolff's popularization. However, in both of these
works Gottsched parts ways with Wolff on the issue of Pre-established
Harmony.
The Vindiciarum systematic influxus physic) divides into two parts.
The first part contains primarily an historical account of the three
causal theories. The second part, however, contains an extended defense
of Physical Influx against the objections primarily of the
Cartesians.(19) In particular, Gottsched considers the following
objections. First, a Cartesian might object to Physical Influx on the
grounds that one cannot clearly and distinctly perceive how the soul and
body could act on each other, since their natures are radically
distinct.(20) Gottsched responds to this objection by noting that we
have insufficient accounts of what it means for the soul to think and
the body to be extended. Even if it is clear that thought and extension
are the essences of the soul and the body, it does not follow that all
of the soul's and body's properties can be derived from their
essences. Therefore, the objection that physical influx cannot be
derived from the natures of the soul and the body loses its force.
Gottsched's response can also be used to provide a preliminary
reply to Leibniz's objection concerning the inconceivability of
Physical Influx; since we do not have an adequate account of the soul
and the body, the lack of a complete description of physical influx is
not objectionable, but rather to be expected.
Gottsched then considers the objection that Physical Influx
violates the law of the conservation of motion. Gottsched first notes
that the law of motion that Descartes and the Cartesians think Physical
Influx violates, namely, the law of conservation of motion, has been
shown (by Leibniz) to be false.(21) What is conserved is not motion,
but, as Leibniz argues, living or motive forces, which are measured by
the mass of the body times the square of its velocity. Thus the
incompatibility of Physical Influx with a false law is no evidence
against Physical Influx. Gottsched then considers whether Physical
Influx violates this "corrected" law of nature. In justifying
his negative answer, he uses an example of a taut bow. The tension in
the string when it is drawn back by an arrow held in one position so
that it is at rest contains, Gottsched claims, the same amount of motive
forces as does the motion of the arrow when it is released, despite the
fact that the amount of motion in the world is clearly not the same in
the two cases. Thus, Gottsched can argue by analogy that according to
Physical Influx the soul can add motion to the universe or the motion of
a body can cause an idea in the soul (possibly diminishing the amount of
motion in the universe) without violating the `corrected' law of
conservation. The important requirement is that the motive forces of the
body and the soul remain constant regardless of whether or not they are
impeded by external actions, that is, whether they result in
"new" motions. Given that it is not obvious that Physical
Influx violates this requirement, this objection to Physical Influx
loses its force. In this way Gottsched develops an interesting reply to
one of the two main objections raised against Physical Influx. Moreover,
Gottsched manages to do so on the basis of Leibnizian principles, since
crucial to this response is his acceptance of Leibniz's principle
of the conservation of motive forces rather than motion.
Still, in his dissertation, Gottsched's defense of Physical
Influx is nothing more than a defense; his main goal is merely to defend
Physical Influx from some of the objections that were or might be raised
against it. He does not develop any positive reasons for accepting
Physical Influx rather than Pre-established Harmony. Gottsched does,
however, develop his version of Physical Influx further in his Erste
Grunde der gesammten Weltweisheit. In Wolff's philosophical system,
which Gottsched's Weltweisheit follows in many respects,
Pre-established Harmony arises primarily in two contexts, namely in the
Cosmology, which discusses the concept of world, and in the Psychology,
which discusses the mind-body relationship. In the Weltweisheit
Gottsched maintains what is perhaps best described as an officially
neutral position with respect to the general cosmological issue.
However, in his discussion of mind-body interaction in the section on
Psychology he suggests what may best be described as an unofficial
acceptance of Physical Influx.(22) First, Gottsched describes Physical
Influx, Pre-established Harmony, and Occasionalism, giving a brief
history of each position's advocates and their motivations. He then
notes that "none of the three is completely explained or
demonstrated; each one of them still has its difficulties: Thus, each
person can maintain whichever one is most pleasing. However, for me it
has always seemed that: one does not have reason to reject the oldest
and most common opinion of natural influence until one has completely
refuted it and demonstrated its impossibility. At this point this has
been done by no one,"(23) Thus in the Weltweishett Gottsched
commits himself in an unofficial way to Physical Influx for mind-body
interaction.
His defense of Physical Influx in this domain is limited primarily
to responding to some of the objections raised against it (although, as
we shall see shortly, he also presents incomplete arguments for Physical
Influx). First, in response to Leibniz's and Wolff's objection
that physical influx is incomprehensible, Gottsched now explicitly notes
that although physical influx may appear incomprehensible to one with
obscure and incomplete notions of the body and the soul, it is possible
that more distinct and complete notions of body and soul could (in the
future) render physical influx intelligible.(24) However, Gottsched also
notes ([sections]1067) that "tire word influence [EinfluB] is taken
in a metaphorical or `verblumtem' sense."(25) Accordingly,
Gottsched further undercuts Leibniz's and Wolff's first main
objection to Physical Influx by noting that `influence' (influere)
is not to be taken literally as a flowing (of, for example, a liquid),
but rather in terms of the capacity or power of a substance to act
directly on another substance. Thus, despite his more modest claim that
physical influx may be made more comprehensible in the future, Gottsched
has already taken an important step toward a more sophisticated and
coherent version of Physical Influx.
Second, Gottsched responds to the objection that Physical Influx
would destroy the soul's simplicity. On Gottsched's account
the soul possesses both the power to represent and the power to move
bodies. The objection to this account must be that two such powers would
be incompatible with the soul's simplicity. However, Gottsched
notes at [sections]1080 that the soul can both will and understand
without thereby destroying the soul's simplicity. Even the most
orthodox Wolffians claim to derive (apparently without inconsistency)
the powers of the understanding and the will from the single
representing force of the soul (qua simple substance). Thus, Gottsched
argues, Physical Influx does not cause difficulty for the soul's
simplicity.(26)
In the second part of [sections]1080, Gottsched proceeds to offer a
tentative argument for Physical Influx between the soul and the body. He
notes: "the soul has an effort (Bemahung) to bring forth new
sensations ([sections]1051). It cannot have this if its body does not
have a position and place in the world of the kind that materialists
presume can be awakened in the brain through the sensible parts
(GliedmaBen). Thus, it strives at the same time according to this
changed position or place of the body."(27) Despite its obscure
form, Gottsched's argument in this passage is that only physical
influx between the soul and the body can render intelligible the
soul's desire to bring forth new sensations. For, it is assumed,
sensations require a body with a particular place and position in the
world. This argument is of course question-begging, since it simply
assumes without argument that sensations require the action of a body on
the soul, an assumption a proponent of Pre-established Harmony need not
make. None the less, Gottsched can still be seen as at least asking the
proponents of Pre-established Harmony to explain how a person is to
undergo sensations without the causal efficacy of a body.
Since most of Gottsched's discussion in this chapter of the
Weltweisheit centers on the interaction between the soul and the body,
his unofficial acceptance of Physical Influx might seem to be limited to
the soul-body relationship. However, in [sections]1081 Gottsched commits
himself in a limited and equally unofficial way to Physical Influx with
respect to the general cosmological issue as well. That is, Gottsched
seems to admit that substances can act on each other, regardless of
their particular natures. He argues that we need not say that the soul
taken by itself possesses the entire power of moving a body. For
"there are so many powers already in the fluid parts of the body:
that these powers require only stimulation and determination if they are
to act. Though we cannot explain how it is that the soul brings some
nerve fluid (Nervensaft) into motion; so too with respect to bodies we
cannot completely comprehend how one ball hitting another can set the
other in motion. For since monads or elements are present in all points
at which they are in contact: these [monads or elements] must be able to
act on each other and continue the motion, even if we do not know
how."(28) In other words, Gottsched seems to be arguing that
physical influx between the soul and the body implies physical influx
among bodies.(29) For the soul is not sufficient to move all of the
body's fluid parts, but rather these fluid parts must be able to
move each other. Moreover, he wants to suggest that just as we do not
completely understand physical influx between the soul and the body, we
do not completely understand physical influx between bodies, so no
objection can be raised against Physical Influx on that count. Thus, for
Gottsched, Physical Influx at the cosmological level has the same
(unofficial) status as it does for the soul and the body.
Finally, Gottsched adds a brief argument in the final section of
this chapter ([sections]1082) against Pre-established Harmony. He asks
rhetorically: "But could the soul have all its sensations even
without it [the body]: For what use would the body be? An idealist would
then have a much better opinion; because by rejecting bodies he would
have transcended innumerable difficulties."(30) Gottsched's
criticism is that if a soul could have all of its sensations without a
body, then the body would be superfluous and idealism would represent
the most attractive position.(31) Nonetheless, these two arguments are
quite brief and directly after this last argument Gottsched adds:
"Yet I present all this only as mere speculation and do not decide
which opinion, with a more mature knowledge of the soul and the body,
will gain the upper hand with time."(32) However, in later editions
of this work, immediately after making this conciliatory remark,
Gottsched refers the reader to his dissertation on the topic, making it
clear that he has a definite opinion! Thus it seems appropriate to
interpret Gottsched's statements (especially about the cosmological
issue) as unofficial or personal remarks about his own opinion rather
than a philosophical claim that can stand on the basis of the arguments
he presents.
Gottsched's contribution to the debate about Pre-established
Harmony and Physical Influx is thus quite substantial, even if not
definitive. For although he does not take an official stand on the
issue, he is unequivocal about the possibility of Physical Influx, since
he responds to a number of important objections raised against that
theory. Also, he provides reasons, even if not compelling ones, for
accepting his unofficial version of Physical Influx. Perhaps his most
important achievement, however, is to suggest that physical influx
should be taken, not in a literal but rather in a metaphorical sense,
according to which physical influx is not an inconceivable migration of
accidents, as Leibniz and Wolff charge, but rather the capacity or power
a substance has to act directly upon another substance.
II
Knutzen's Version of Physical Influx. The second major
advocate of Physical Influx--who forms the crucial turning point in the
debate--is Martin Knutzen. Knutzen is now best known (and this is faint
praise, since he is not at all well-known) as one of Kant's
teachers in Konigsberg. However, in the first half of the eighteenth
century he is well-respected in academic circles for his writings in
philosophy, theology, natural science, and mathematics; some of his
writings are De immaterialitate animi (1741), Philosophischer Beweis von
der Wahrheit der Christlichen Religion (1740), Vernunftige Gedanken von
den Cometen (1744), and Theoremata nova de parabolic infinitis eodem
parametro et circa eundem axin descriptis (1737).(33) However, his real
claim to fame is his dissertation, which he publishes in 1735 as an
independent monograph, entitled Systema Causarum efficientium, of which
a second edition is issued in 1745. What should be emphasized, however,
before we consider the details of this treatise, is that in the course
of its three parts, 62 sections, and 210 pages, Knutzen is explicitly
and forcefully arguing for Physical Influx as an "official"
position rather than merely hinting at privately held beliefs or timidly claiming that Physical Influx is perhaps still possible, since no other
theory has been definitively proven.
Further, what makes Knutzen's argument so influential is that
it is based on Leibnizian principles. Despite the fact that there is
considerable difficulty in determining which of Leibniz's works
Knutzen would know, Knutzen himself refers to Leibniz's letters to
Wagner, "A Brief Demonstration of a Notable Error of Descartes and
Others concerning a Natural Law," A New System of Nature, and the
Theodicy; and additionally the Monadology and On Nature Itself had been
published before 1735,(34) so that it is safe to conclude that Knutzen
has access to many (if not all) of Leibniz's fundamental
philosophical doctrines. Moreover, Knutzen often supplements his
references to Leibniz with references to Wolff, who, despite his
departure from Leibniz on certain points,(35) is clearly still a
Leibnizian. Thus we have sufficient prima facie evidence to take
seriously Knutzen's claim to be basing his argument on Leibnizian
principles, with one major exception, namely, Leibniz's complete
concept theory of substance.(36) There is simply little trace of that
doctrine to be found in Knutzen's account of Leibniz, and insofar
as Leibniz bases Pre-established Harmony on this doctrine, Knutzen
misses part of Leibniz's motivation on this point. However, it is
also possible that Knutzen is aware of this doctrine, but simply finds
it unreasonably strong and thus worthy of being rejected tout court. At
any rate, Knutzen does not misunderstand the main points of
Leibniz's position even if he is unaware of or rejects some of the
more unusual details of Leibniz's conception of substance. With
this in mind, let us now turn to Knutzen's treatise.
The first part gives a general introduction to the topic,
explaining the empirical correlation that holds between the states of
the mind and the states of the body, stating precise definitions of the
three causal theories, and arguing that direct experience cannot decide
the issue between them. It is worth noting that Knutzen's argument
that direct experience does not decide the issue is not novel. During
the debate between Wolff and various Pietists, Wolff repeatedly argues
that all three causal theories are consistent with what we directly
experience. Thus all parties to the dispute agree that the issue must be
decided by argument, not observation.
The Argument from vis motrix. In the second part Knutzen presents
four distinct arguments for Physical Influx. In order to lay the
necessary foundation, he first carefully articulates definitions of the
following: human beings ([sections]17), spirit or monad ([sections]18),
bodies or composites ([sections]19), action ([sections]21), force
([sections]22), space, place, and position ([sections]23), internal and
total motion, and motive, primitive, and derivative forces
([sections]243. Accordingly, Knutzen interprets Leibniz's position
to be roughly that of the New System of Nature,(37) namely, that there
are simple elements or substances that compose bodies(38) and that are
in a place, though they do not fill a space.(39) He then proposes his
first, and what amounts to his most important argument for Physical
Influx in [sections]28:
[sections]. XXVIII. A force [of something] to move itself
involves in
reality a force of moving another as well.
A force of moving that brings it about that any being changes its
own
proper place without the force of moving other things that surround
it
cannot be conceived, but rather it is necessary that after positing
one the
other is given at the same time. For a force of moving that brings
it about
that a being changes its own place does not exist except as a
conatus for
changing its own place ([sections]. 24.) that is, for occupying a
place
distinct from the one that it now occupies, yet one that is still
continuous
to it ([sections]. cit.). But other coexistent things that surround
the
movable thing on all sides hold a place distinct from the place of
the
movable thing, since two distinct beings cannot be in one place at
the same
time ([sections]. 23.): therefore, a being endowed with the force
of moving
itself strives to push things to another place, if they resist. But
if in
truth they are also supposed to yield spontaneously, nevertheless,
that which is already participating in progressive motion exerts
itself in
the way which is required to complete the motion
beyond itself or to push things to another place. Because
resistance is
to such a degree the occasional cause of motion, it does not add
anything to the intrinsic force: Therefore, a being that moves
itself enjoys
the effort of changing the place of coexistents or the force of
moving
other things ([sections]. 24.). Therefore, the force of moving
itself
without the force of moving other things cannot be conceived, but
after the
one has been posited, the other is posited at the same time.(40)
This is an interesting argument. The basic idea is that if, as
Leibniz and Wolff assume, a being possesses the force to change its
place,(41) and the change of place of one being implies the change of
place of another being,(42) then the force to change its own place
implies, now contra Leibniz and Wolff, the force to change the place of
another being. More abstractly formulated: Intrasubstantial causation
implies intersubstantial causation. This argument can be formulated in
two different versions. The first version would claim that insofar as
one being moves itself it in fact causes the motion of the other. The
second version, which I shall discuss shortly, would claim that the mere
capacity of a being to move itself implies that it could move the other,
which is enough to contradict Pre-established Harmony as Leibniz defends
it.
What might Leibniz find objectionable in the first version of this
argument? What is unquestionably right in the argument is that the fact
that one being changes its place implies that another being must change
its place too (if it occupies the place into which the first being is to
move). Leibniz will presumably argue, however, that it is illegitimate to infer from this fact that the motion of the second being must be
caused by the first being, since according to Pre-established Harmony
each being will be causally responsible for its own changes. Thus, the
fact that the first being has the force to move itself implies only that
either the first or the second being has the force to move the second
being. In other words, all that the motion of the first being implies is
that there be some cause of the motion of the second being. On what
grounds does Knutzen infer that the cause must be located in the first
being?(43)
Knutzen has, I believe, resources to answer this question. Even if
one grants Leibniz that the second being has the force to move itself,
Knutzen can argue that what activates the force in the second being must
be precisely the force of the first being. In other words, even if
Knutzen admits causal activity in the second being, he need not accept
that this causal activity is sufficient for the second being's
motion. After all, if the first being had not moved itself into the
place of the second being, the second being would not have moved itself
either. Thus it seems entirely appropriate to say that the first being
has the force to move the second being even if it does so only in virtue
of acting on the latter's force.(44) Leibniz holds that what is
responsible for the motion of the first being is merely an ideal ground
of the second being's motion.(45) However, from the perspective of
a proponent of physical influx it is difficult to see why such a ground
is ideal and not real, that is, causal.
Leibniz might reply to Knutzen's explanation with his
"world apart" doctrine,(46) which states that the appearances
would (or could) be entirely the same as they are even if nothing other
than God and I existed (as, so to speak, a world apart), and the
plausibility of this doctrine might appear to be evidence in favor of
the sufficiency of internal causes. Despite the fact that there is no
evidence showing that Knutzen accepts the "world apart"
doctrine, Knutzen can grant this doctrine and still claim that internal
causes are not sufficient. How? The "world apart" doctrine
states that if only God and one being (namely I) existed, the
appearances would be no different from what they are now. However, such
a claim is in fact irrelevant to what Knutzen is arguing. For Knutzen is
concerned with the relationship that exists between what in fact exists.
Surely a different relationship would hold in the counterfactual
situation in which only God and one being existed.(47) Thus, applying
the "world apart" doctrine to our second being, to say that
what is contained in the complete concept of the second being would be
sufficient for its own motions if nothing else existed is not to say
that what is contained in the complete concept of this being is
sufficient for its own motions, given that other beings do in fact
exist. For unless Leibniz and Wolff are to beg the question, the
presence of other beings could be causally relevant. And this is
precisely what Knutzen is claiming to be the case. Why? Because he is
claiming that the motion of one being necessarily implies the motion of
another. That is, the force a being has of moving itself implies the
force to move another being. Thus, since it is not logically possible
that the second being could not move, given the motion of the first
being, it seems that there is a sufficiently strong relationship between
the first and second beings that Knutzen is justified in calling the
first the (or at least a) cause of the motion of the second.
Knutzen need not, however, rely only on common sense or standard
linguistic agreement here. Consider a Leibnizian definition of action.
In [sections]21 Knutzen states: "A being is said to he acting when
it contains in itself the reason for the existence (or change) of a
certain thing."(48) If this definition is accepted, then it seems
correct to infer, as Knutzen does in this first main argument, that the
force of one being to move itself does imply the force to move another,
since the change of the one does contain in itself the reason (or at
least part of the reason) for the other's motion. Could a
Leibnizian simply reject this definition of action? Not easily, since it
would seem that any narrower characterization might simply beg the
question. For if action is simply defined in such a way that a being can
act only on itself, then such a definition obviously involves a petitio
principii.
Now a Leibnizian might object to this kind of response in the
following way: If one accepts the account of causal action developed
above, then, due to the expression thesis(49) (namely that every
substance expresses or mirrors the entire universe), one would be
committed to saying that every substance would cause every change in
every other substance, which is rather implausible. Of course one might
accept the above account of causal action and take this argument as
grounds for rejecting the expression thesis. However, Knutzen could
accept the expression thesis and still make a distinction amongst
grounds in such a way that any being will not cause all changes in all
other beings. How? The difference between a case in which one being
moves so as to displace another being and a case in which one being
simply moves, say, closer to the other without moving it is that in the
former case there must be some intrinsic change in the being that is
displaced, whereas in the latter case there need be no such intrinsic
change, since the change that occurs is merely relational and can be
attributed wholly to the first being, which cannot be done in the first
case.(50) In other words, one can distinguish between grounds that
require an intrinsic change in a distinct being and those that do not.
Only the former, Knutzen can suggest, are really causally active on
distinct beings.
Let us now briefly turn to the second version of Knutzen's
argument, a version considerably weaker and less controversial, but
still sufficiently strong to present difficulties for a Leibnizian. If a
being has the force to move itself, then, even if the being contiguous
to it moves of its own accord, the first being must nonetheless have the
force to move it, in case it had not moved of its own accord. If the
first being had the force to move itself only if the second being moved
itself of its own accord, then it is not appropriate to say that the
first being really has the force to move itself, since it does not
contain the sufficient conditions for its motion in itself (which is the
standard condition Leibniz would set for the ascription of a causal
power). In other words, it must at least be possible that the first
being move the second, even if God sets the world up in such a way that
this force need never be exercised. However, if it is possible that the
first being move the second, then Knutzen can conclude that
Pre-established Harmony is false insofar as it implies that
intersubstantial causation is not even possible (on the grounds that it
is not even conceivable). Thus, even this second, weaker version of
Knutzen's argument can be presented against Pre-established
Harmony.
The Argument from Impenetrability. In [sections]29 Knutzen provides
a second argument for Physical Influx, which, though distinct from the
first argument, clearly stems from similar considerations. He writes:
The same can also be demonstrated another way: simple elements are
impenetrable, according to the opinion of the illustrious Leibniz,
who
asserts that all finite substances are impenetrable. See his Letter
to C1.
Wagner p. 201. Tom. I. Epist. Edit. Kortholtianae. Hence, it cannot
be the
case that one [substance] is in the place of another. Therefore,
there is
something real, by whose force one simple excludes and pushes up
against another, lest the other invade its place. For since it is
most
certain that simples are moved ([sections]. 27) and that distinct
simples are
not moved according to an opposite line of direction, consequently
it is
impossible that they penetrate each other mutually, or rather what
we
may gather from the conflict of bodies and their collision is that
in fact
they are carried in a contrary direction mutually away from each
other;
It follows in this case that one must hold that either simples
penetrate
each other mutually, which goes against Leibniz's assertions,
or if they
resist each other mutually, they must act on each other mutually.
Q.e.d.(51)
As in the first argument, Knutzen tries to show that some property
that a Leibnizian will want to ascribe to finite substances implies
intersubstantial causation. The basic idea in this argument is that
impenetrability is intelligible only if one substance is attempting to
penetrate a second substance, whereby the second substance is said to be
impenetrable in virtue of resisting the first substance. But, the
argument continues, how can one substance be said to resist another
substance if not causally? That is, surely resistance is a causal term,
and a substance cannot resist itself, so that if resistance (or
impenetrability) is a real property of substances, then there must be
interaction between substances. In the case of impenetrability and
resistance, even more than in the case of the motion of one being
implying the motion of another, natural linguistic usage suggests causal
interaction amongst substances.(52)
Leibniz's most plausible response to this kind of argument is
to argue that one should divorce such causal connotations from the
concept of resistance. According to Leibniz, resistance must be,
properly speaking, simply a fact about substances, namely that
substances cannot be in the same place. However, Knutzen seems justified
in pressing Leibniz on this point, since the fact that substances cannot
be in the same place seems quite distinct from the issue whether
substances are impenetrable and can resist each other. (One would
naturally think that resistance is the means for keeping substances from
occupying the same place.) To put the problem with Leibniz's
response in words closer to his own, Pre-established Harmony seems to
arrange the motions of bodies with such great harmony that they have no
need to resist each other in the first place! Thus, ultimately,
Knutzen's second argument forces a Leibnizian either to accept
Physical Influx or to reject impenetrability and resistance as real
properties.(53) I suspect that if Leibniz were faced with this choice,
he would retain Pre-established Harmony and cast resistance aside,
albeit reluctantly, since then it would follow that two substances could
be in the same place at the same time (even if they never in fact are
so).
The Argument from the Simplicity of (Divine) Action on Others.
These first two arguments are quite general; the first holds for any
being that can move itself and the second for impenetrable simple
elements or substances. In [subsections]30-2 Knutzen makes preparations
to extend the scope of Physical Influx from beings per se or
"simple elements" to the mind-body relationship by explaining
what perception is ([sections]30) and by arguing that simple elements
perceive ([sections]31).(54) However, in [subsections]33-34, instead of
simply applying to the mind in a straightforward way the arguments that
he has already constructed for simplex, Knutzen introduces a third
argument for Physical Influx, an argument that takes a rather
interesting turn. For in [sections]33 Knutzen considers the nature of
absolute perfection. "Perfection that implies no limitation per se
or, alternately, that can exist together with any other possible entity
(as the Scholastics say) is called perfection absolutely or simpliciter.
However, it is demonstrated in natural theology that anything truly
ascribed to God is a perfection simpliciter, which does not contradict
anything, except limitations or imperfections."(55) In [sections]34
Knutzen then uses this conception of perfection to establish that
physical influx is possible for the mind-body relationship, since it
involves no contradiction. His justification is as follows:
The physical influx of the mind on corporeal simples and of those
simples
in turn on the mind is completed by an act ([sections]32).
Therefore, if
one must demonstrate that physical influx is possible, then one
must show in
what way the action of the mind outside itself on other simples
does not
involve a contradiction ([sections]. 85. ontol.): Therefore,
let's
investigate especially
whether one can discover anything in the mind that contradicts the
mind's
actions on external things. We discover in the mind those things
that
primarily
amount to this: that the mind is a simple being and surely that
this being
perceives or is a perceiver, and in a far greater degree of
eminence than
that of
simple elements, since it perceives distinctly or is provided with
an
intellect or
a will [sections]. 17. 18). The action of the mind on external
things
cannot contradict
[the] simplicity [of the mind] because not only does God act
outside himself
(according to the Princ. of Nat. Theol.), but also the simple
elements act on
each other mutually ([sections]. 29.). Nor can this action
contradict the
mind to the
extent that it is a being that perceives or is perceiving because
simple
elements take pleasure in the perception of external things
([sections].
31); however,
an action of this kind cannot be denied to these simples.
Therefore, nothing
remains other than that eminent perfection by which the human mind
is
separated from simples that have inferior perceptions, and that
places the
faculties of understanding and willing in the mind, and if the
external
action of
the mind does not contradict this, then the possibility of physical
influx
will
have been established beyond doubt. But action on external things
is a simple
perfection because it can be ascribed to God ([sections]. 33); and
therefore it cannot
be inconsistent except with limitation and imperfection ([sections]. cit.):
therefore, it
cannot be inconsistent with intellect and volition, which exceed
the mere
faculty of perception, and which at the same time confer a greater
perfection
on the being, since, as was already shown, this kind of action is
agreeable
with a merely perceptive being and a more perfect being. Therefore,
who could
doubt that the mind can act on the body? However, because it was
demonstrated above ([sections]. 29.) that action on other simples
must be
attributed
to the simples of which the body consists; surely the mind, insofar
as it is a
simple substance, can act on such simples (according to the
demonstr.): there
will be no reason why anyone should judge the action of the
body's simples
on the mind to be impossible. Therefore, it is established that
physical
influx is possible.(56) Knutzen's main argument in this
passage is that since we know that it is possible for less perfect
simples to act on each other, it is legitimate to infer that it is
possible for more perfect simplex, that is, for substances endowed with
intellect and will, as minds are, to act on other simples. Indeed, this
is precisely the argument we expect. However, Knutzen supplements this
argument with the idea that physical influx is possible for minds
because God has the perfection of acting in this way, presumably in
creation and in miracles. In other words; what is interesting is that
Knutzen characterizes acting on others (that is, physical influx) as a
perfection and what allows him to do so is the fact that God has this
perfection in creation. This characterization strengthens his argument
because the mere fact that the substances or simple elements that
constitute bodies can act on each other does not imply that other kinds
of substances or simple elements can act on bodies, even if the latter
are more perfect than the former. However, given that acting on others
is a perfection (and it undoubtedly is, if God does it), it is more
plausible that if a lesser being can do it, so can a greater being
(especially if the differences between the two are differences of degree
rather than of kind).(57)
Another important factor involved in the argument concerns
simplicity. Not only is acting on others apparently a perfection, but it
is also absolutely simple. This is relevant in two ways. First, that
such an action is simple is the crucial feature in showing that it
cannot result in a contradiction. In criticizing Descartes'
ontological argument, Leibniz often remarks that the argument shows only
that if God is possible, then He necessarily exists. What Descartes
still needs to show is that God is possible. Sometimes Leibniz leaves
the reader wondering whether such an argument can be developed, but
occasionally Leibniz does suggest that such an argument can be given by
considering that all of God's perfections are simple and simples
cannot contradict each other.(58) Thus the fact that acting on other
substances is simple is important for showing that there is no
contradiction in asserting that the mind can act on the body. Second, it
brings out a feature of Knutzen's version of Physical Influx that
was only implicit in the previous discussion, namely that the force of
acting on others is primitive or basic; that is, it cannot be explained
in more basic terms. In other words, Knutzen is at least implicitly
arguing that one cannot go any deeper than to say that a substance has
the capacity, force, or power to act on another substance. Any
suggestion that such an action must be explained further in terms of
accidents migrating from one substance to another (as Leibniz likes to
do, perhaps unfairly, on behalf of the proponent of Physical Influx) is
illegitimate.
What is of further significance is that a Leibnizian cannot object
to such a primitive force of action because Leibniz himself assumes such
a force insofar as it is through a conatus or force that a substance
strives to change from one state to the next! In other words, by
accepting intrasubstantial causation Leibniz must be accepting some kind
of capacity for a substance to act on itself. So the very idea of such
an action cannot be objectionable. The difference between Leibniz's
and Knutzen's force is of course that Leibniz's force acts on
itself, whereas Knutzen's force acts on other substances. But why
should this difference be important? The insight underlying
Leibniz's suggestion that one substance can act on another only if
an accident were to migrate from the one substance to the other is
presumably that a property cannot pop into existence but rather must
come from some source (namely from the substance that is acting). If it
comes from the substance that is acting, then it must somehow get from
the one substance to the other and how could it do that if it did not
migrate there?
Knutzen has a number of responses to this point. First, this
objection still does not clarify what the special difficulty is with one
substance acting on another substance as compared to a substance acting
on itself. For if it is legitimate to ask about the source or origin of
a property, both accounts face the same dilemma: Either the property is
already present in the substance, in which case no force is necessary in
order to make it true of the substance. Or it is not already present in
the substance, and then creation ex nihilo will be equally problematic
for both inter- and intrasubstantial causation, for if creation ex
nihilo is solved by the concept of force, then that concept should solve
it for both Pre-established Harmony and Physical Influx. Second, even if
there is some special (albeit unspecifiable) problem with the
"inter" part of intersubstantial causation, Leibniz has not
countenanced Knutzen's specific version of Physical Influx, since,
as we have seen above, for Knutzen two forces are involved in the
production of a property, one in the substance Knutzen wants to call the
cause and one in the substance of which the property will be true.(59)
It seems open to Knutzen to respond to Leibniz's charge by claiming
that the second of the two forces alleviates this problem. Thus Knutzen
has cleverly undercut any Leibnizian grounds for objecting to a
substance's simple force of acting on others.
The Argument From Probability. Knutzen's final argument for
Physical Influx stands one of Leibniz's arguments for
Pre-established Harmony on its head. After establishing in
[subsections]33-4 that Physical Influx is possible, in [sections]35 he
turns to show that it is more probable than the other two causal
theories by considering a number of criteria of truth. First, it agrees
with experience, a point Wolff admits. Second, as [sections]34 has
shown, it is possible. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, Knutzen
argues that it agrees with divine wisdom. "For it is shown in
natural theology: God, in conformance with his greatest and infinite
wisdom, chooses the natural, shortest path."(60) Knutzen proceeds
to explain what the shortest path is, namely, that "those things
that can come about naturally through a select few will not be completed
through many or by the longer path."(61) In the explanatory text to
this passage, Knutzen emphasizes that it is not enough that God choose
the shortest path, but it must also be a natural path, by which he means
one containing the fewest miracles.(62) In the next section
([sections]36) Knutzen then explicitly argues that Pre-established
Harmony involves "roundabout ways because so many skills are
necessary for producing this harmony both in the body and in the mind,
that they may surpass every form of comprehension."(63) In other
words, the Harmony in Pre-established Harmony is guaranteed by
God's benevolence and wisdom rather than by the natural powers of
finite substances alone and thus extends well beyond our understanding,
which Knutzen takes to be tantamount to miraculous.(64) Knutzen's
point here is well-taken. If we would have to perform infinite analysis
in order to understand a simple causal connection between two events, an
impossible task, then it appears that Physical Influx, according to
which we would need to understand only the causal powers of both
substances, is the shorter, preferable, and thus more probable path.
Objections and Replies. In the third part Knutzen states and
responds to ten objections to Physical Influx, many of which are raised
by perhaps the leading Wolffian defender of Pre-established Harmony,
Georg Bernhard Bilfinger(65) in his works De harmonia praestabilita
(1723)(66) and Dilucidationes philosophicae de Deo, anima humana, mundo
et generalibus rerum affectionibus (1725). While it is not possible to
consider all of these objections in this context, it is worth discussing
three of them insofar as they elicit Knutzen's reply to the one
charge against Physical Influx that has not yet been given due
consideration: that Physical Influx violates the law of the conservation
of motive forces.(67) Objection 6 ([sections]53) considers this
objection explicitly, while Objections 7 and 8 discuss it implicitly,
since they concern the proportion (in [sections]54) and cause-effect
relationship (in [sections]55) that are supposed to hold between the
motions of the body and the decrees of the mind. Briefly, the difficulty
concerning proportionality is that causes and effects must be
proportional to one another, but the mind and the body are not
homogeneous and thus cannot be proportional.(68) The difficulty
concerning the cause-effect relationship is that the effect would be
greater than the cause if a certain motion in the body could cause not
only another motion but also a thought in the mind, as Physical Influx
asserts.(69)
Knutzen's main response to the objection that Physical Influx
violates the law of the conservation of motive forces is to deny that
the law holds for mind-body interaction. But he does so in two distinct
ways. He first notes that the law has been proven only for elastic
bodies, not for inelastic bodies, much less for the mind and the body.
This is part of what he means when he emphasizes: "I deny .. . that
it follows from Physical Influx that a certain quantity of living forces
is not conserved in the collision of bodies amongst each other"(70)
and "as long as it has not yet been shown and cannot be shown that
this law of motion about conserving a certain quantity of living forces
is not only dictated for bodies acting on each other mutually, but also
for the mind acting on the body and vice versa, there is absolutely no
objection present that injures Physical Influx."(71) Indeed Knutzen
even provides a reason why this law should not hold for the mind. Since
Leibniz derives the conservation of motive forces from the law of
inertia ("that any body remains in its state of rest or uniform
motion in a direction unless it is forced to change its state by an
extrinsic cause") and "it is most evident that the mind does
not at all remain in its state of rest and uniform motion in a direction
until forced to change its state by an external [cause]"(72) (that
is, the law of inertia does not hold for the mind), there is no reason
for the conservation law to hold for the mind.
However, in his discussion of the objections concerning proportion
and the cause-effect relationship Knutzen considers the relationship
between bodies and minds in more detail and then suggests another way in
which to respond to the charge that Physical Influx violates the laws of
nature. For example, in [sections]55 Knutzen writes:
One must note the following concerning physical influx: 1) that the
impression of motion that is communicated to monads causes
perceptions
in them, for the communication of motion cannot be completed
except through the modification of forces that are present in
elements
and that Leibniz calls perceptual. And thus beyond the
communication
of motion nothing else is required in order to cause perceptions;
and as
it is in the case of the monads of the body, so it is in the
soul.(73)
In this passage and others,(74) Knutzen can, I think, be understood
to be making a more fundamental criticism of Leibniz's objection
along the following lines. Naturally, the law of the conservation of
motive forces holds for bodies, and at least for the Leibniz of the
Monadology bodies pertain to the realm of well-founded phenomena.(75)
Thus bodies and their motions are well-founded insofar as a
corresponding monadic, that is, representational state, whatever it may
be like, underlies them. Further, we know about this founding
relationship only that the law of efficient causes holds for the
phenomenal realm of bodies (and their motions) and the law of final
causes holds for the realm of monads that founds the phenomenal realm.
Thus Leibniz is committed to holding that the laws of motive forces will
hold for the phenomenal realm, apparently regardless of how the monads
exercise their freedom. In other words, no difficulty arises for Leibniz
that the activity at the monadic level, however free it might be, could
violate the laws that govern the phenomenal level. The crucial point to
note in this explanation of how Leibniz avoids the problem presented by
freedom is that no mention is made of Pre-established Harmony.(76) In
other words, Leibniz's own way of avoiding the problem of
reconciling freedom and the law of the conservation of motive forces is
to drive a wedge between monads and bodies, claiming that the motions of
the latter are somehow grounded in the perceptions of the former, though
the laws for each are completely distinct. Accordingly, the laws of
motion will presumably be what they are, whether each monad acts only on
itself according to final causes of one sort or whether they act on each
other according to final causes of another sort. Also, whether this
monad causes a motion in the body that results from it (as
Pre-established Harmony would have it) or whether it causes a motion in
a body that does not result from it (as Physical Influx would allow), is
not obviously relevant to whether the law of the conservation of motive
forces holds. Thus, contrary to what Leibniz suggests, Pre-established
Harmony is not the only solution to this problem.(77) I take it that
Knutzen is aware of this when he remarks that the law of the
conservation of motive forces holds only for bodies and that the
mind's perceptions and free decrees will correspond to the motions
in the body, since "in whatever way it is in the monads of the
body, it is similar in the soul."
Since this is an important point, let's consider it from a
different angle. The objection to Physical Influx is that when the mind
causes a body to move, this action adds to the total amount of motion
(or motive forces) in the world, that is, motion (or motive forces) is
not being conserved. The inference Leibniz wants to draw from this
objection is that one should deny that the mind acts on the body.
However, one can also infer (and such an inference is suggested by
Leibniz's ultimate position) that one should distinguish between
the realm of bodies and the realm of minds or monads and claim that the
latter founds the former in some general way. Thus when the mind causes
a motion (or motive force) in bodies, there is no reason to think that
there is more motion (or motive force) afterwards than beforehand
because presumably this action is just part of a general founding
relationship that exists between the two realms. In other words, the
"new" motion (or motive force) would have occurred even if the
mind had not chosen to act in the way it did, and the reason the motion
could have occurred is that it is simply obeying the laws that hold for
its respective realm, laws that, generally speaking, are founded on the
monads. So what is crucial to solving the problem posed by the law of
the conservation of motive forces is not Preestablished Harmony, but
rather restricting the law to bodies (as Knutzen explicitly does), since
minds have their own laws (or free decrees) though they correspond to
(or found) the bodies. In this way Knutzen can give a philosophically
interesting response to Leibniz's second main objection to Physical
Influx, namely that it violates the laws of nature.
Summary. Martin Knutzen's treatment of Physical Influx and
Pre-established Harmony is of fundamental importance to the debate both
historically and philosophically. Knutzen's work surely represents
the crucial turning point in 1735 against Pre-established Harmony and in
favor of Physical Influx. Whereas previously Wolffians had generally
followed Wolff on the issue and Gottsched's unofficial wavering did
little to change this, after Knutzen's work it becomes acceptable
(even for Wolffians) to adopt Physical Influx. For example, Crusius,
Darjes, Ploucquet, and even Euler all accept Physical Influx in the
1740s.(78) And recall what Knutzen has accomplished. He has given four
arguments in favor of Physical Influx, at least two of them rather
interesting ones, and all of them based on Leibnizian principles. He has
responded to two of the most important objections that were lodged
against Physical Influx, by noting that the law of the conservation of
motion (or motive forces) holds only for bodies and by developing a
model of intersubstantial causation. According to this model, physical
influx is not literally a migration of accidents, as Leibniz alleges the
scholastics to have supposed, but rather the force of one substance to
act on another substance. In addition to being distinct from the
migration model, this model has the advantage that it appeals to a
concept of force that a Leibnizian has no reason to find objectionable,
since an analogous force is invoked by Leibniz himself to explain the
unfolding of a substance's complete concept. Knutzen also provides
a rather sophisticated description of the model, since the powers of
both substances must be involved in physical influx insofar as the power
of one substance modifies or activates the power of another, which then
produces the new property. For example, when the body acts on the mind,
a corporeal element is causally efficacious by modifying the substantial
representational power of a noncorporeal element in such a way that
corresponding new representations are produced out of it. This model
allows him to avoid the untoward consequence that, for instance, a body
(something material) is sufficient to produce representations (something
Knutzen holds to be immaterial), since the noncorporeal element (that
is, its representational power) can be responsible for producing the
specifically mental dimensions of the representations, even if it is not
sufficient for explaining these representations in their entirely.(79)
Accordingly, not only does Knutzen explain that substances can act
directly on each other, as Gottsched does, but he also provides a more
detailed model of how they can do so.
Although Knutzen's development of this sophisticated model of
Physical Influx signals the victory of Physical Influx over
Pre-established Harmony, I maintain, against Erdmann,(80) that the
debate is not yet over. Two issues are still of particular importance to
proponents of Physical Influx. First, what is the best way to argue for
Physical Influx? This is especially important because Pre-established
Harmony would experience something of a revival in the late 1730s and
early 1740s with Baumgarten's and Meier's spirited defense.
Second, what version of Physical Influx ought one to maintain? For some
answers to these questions, we can turn to Christian August Crusius.
III
Crusius's Version of Physical Influx. Crusius develops his
version of Physical Influx most clearly in his Entwurf der nothwendigen
Vernunft-Wahrheiten in 1745 and in his Weg zur Gewi[beta]heit und
Zuverla[beta]keit der menschlichen Erkenntnis in 1747. Let us consider
each of these works in turn.
The Entwurf. In his Entwurf der nothwendigen Vernunft-Wahrheiten
Crusius first discusses Physical Influx in his section on cosmology. One
might think(81) that Crusius presents an argument for Physical Influx
from the very definition of the essence of the world.(82) For he defines
the world as "a real connection of finite things that is not itself
in turn a part of another to which it belongs by means of a real
connection."(83) Also, it is natural to think that what Crusius
means by the term `real connection' is intersubstantial causation.
However, on close reading of Crusius's explanation of this phrase,
we can see that Physical Influx is not implied by, even if it is
compatible with, this definition. Crusius's intent in adding `real
connection' is rather to allow for a distinction between possible
worlds. As Crusius puts it, "we distinguish a world from several
simultaneously existing creatures or sums thereof that do not stand in
any connection. The world is to be a unity (eines) and one that is a
unity outside our thoughts as well. Consequently, the things belonging
to it must stand in real connection."(84) The justification for
calling the connection real is that if the connection were ideal (that
is, consisted in our thoughts alone), then there would be only one
possible world, since every possible object of thought could be
connected ideally (that is, in our thoughts).(85) However, if it were a
necessary truth that there is only one world, common linguistic usage
would be violated, since we tend to think that there are various
different ways the world might have been rather than just one.
If this argument is an adequate reconstruction of Crusius's
considerations here, then Physical Influx does not follow from it, or at
least not directly. What the definition of the (essence of the) world
requires is that we be able to distinguish more than one possible world.
This requirement can be met by distinguishing between real and ideal
connections. It may be the case that a real connection implies Physical
Influx, but then the argument for Physical Influx is located not so much
in the definition of the world as in the notion of a real connection.
For presumably Pre-established Harmony need not contain an ideal
connection in the sense intended by Crusius, but rather what he would
call a real connection. Wolff, for example, claims that monads are
directed toward all other monads in a single world, but is agnostic about whether or not `directed toward' is to be interpreted as the
ideal connection of Leibuiz's `representing'. Thus
Wolff's agnosticism about `directed toward' leaves open the
possibility of distinguishing possible worlds in terms of a real, albeit
noncausal relation. For example, it would suffice for present purposes
if God were simply to stipulate what constitutes a given possible world,
so that God is responsible for the "real connection".(86) Thus
it is not the definition of the world that directly implies Physical
Influx,(87) but rather the general notion of real connection.
In an earlier section ([sections]94), Crusius provides just such an
argument for Physical Influx. In describing the various possible kinds
of connection between things, Crusius notes that
any connection of finite things that is to be a real undo
existentialis outside
thought must rest on a causal connection of things due to which at
least one must act on the other, but also both can act on each
other
reciprocally as well as be passive with respect to each other. For
there
is otherwise nothing else outside thought that can provide a ground
of
connection between complete things. But as soon as one takes this
away, then one must connect them only in a concept in the
understanding, that is, the things thus have either no or a merely
ideal
connection. Consequently, I cannot, for example, admit that those
who
believe in pre-established harmony leave a real connection between
body and soul.... Their connection is only ideal even with respect
to God. One cannot even say that they are connected by the
intervention of
God. For then at least the arrangement (Einrichtung) of the
essences
(Wesen) of the body and soul would have to be attributed to God.
But the
defenders of pre-established harmony can never say this in the
Leibuizian
sense because they do not leave God any honor beyond bringing the
essences of substances into existence, rather than arranging them,
because
all beings are to be eternal. Thus, a mere correspondence rather
than a real
connection remains.(88)
Crusius's main argument(89) is that the ground of a real
connection must be a causal connection because nothing other than a
causal connection can provide a ground for a real connection. Yet in
order not to beg,the question against Pre-established Harmony, Crusius
must explain why, for example, God cannot be a sufficient ground of a
real (mundane) connection. Crusius argues that proponents of
Pre-established Harmony (or at least Leibniz) can ascribe to God's
action only a mere correspondence(90) between substances rather than a
real connection (and dependence) because although God brings beings into
existence, God is not responsible for their essences (since their
essences are given necessarily in the Divine understanding and cannot be
altered by the Divine will).(91) Thus Crusius is claiming that,
according to Pre-established Harmony, although God can bring into
existence substances that correspond to each other, God cannot bring
substances into existence with a real but noncausal connection. However,
Crusius's claim seems both dogmatic and question-begging. For it
does not obviously follow from the fact that God must choose between
various previously given essences that these essences cannot be related
via a real but noncausal connection.
Yet even if one were to grant Crusius the above objection against
Pre-established Harmony, Crusius has not excluded Wolff's version
of Pre-established Harmony. That is, one might still think that although
God cannot be directly responsible for the real connection between
substances, perhaps God can be indirectly responsible for such a
connection due to the fact that He creates substances that are
"directed toward" every other substance. In other words, Wolff
could maintain that each finite substance is "directed toward"
all others and this directedness constitutes a real connection. Crusius
seems to anticipate this move and replies that such a defender of
Pre-established Harmony cannot "fabricate a special class of
connection which one would call the metaphysical [class], and which is
to consist in the one thing representing the other, for then the
original concept of real connection is abandoned."(92) Yet it seems
simply false to claim that `directed toward' must be interpreted as
`representing' (which presumably makes the connection ideal)(93)
and dogmatic to assert that a proponent of Pre-established Harmony
cannot posit a real connection between substances. Why can one not say,
as was suggested above, that God simply stipulates that two arbitrary
sets of objects are distinct possible worlds?(94) Because Crusius
defines a real connection negatively as any connection that does not
exist in thought alone (that is, that exists outside thought), in order
for him to substantiate his claim that real connection implies physical
influx, he must exclude all other possible nonideal connections, a task
he does not seriously undertake, much less accomplish.(95) Thus
Crusius's argument is essentially incomplete, though still rather
sophisticated in a way that Gottsched's and even Knutzen's are
not.(96)
Although Crusius's arguments for Physical Influx in the
Entwurf may not be convincing, he contributes to the debate between the
proponents of Pre-established Harmony and Physical Influx in a number of
other ways. Besides presenting the new line of argumentation considered
above, he also responds to the traditional objections levied by Leibuiz
and Wolff against the intelligibility of Physical Influx, and he
develops the notion of basic forces further than earlier proponents of
Physical Influx do.
Consider three objections proponents of Pre-established Harmony
might raise and Crusius's responses.
The first objection against Physical Influx is that at/owing minds
to act on bodies would turn minds into matter. The idea underlying this
objection is that if mind and matter can act on each other, then they
must not be radically distinct (as Descartes thinks they are). But if
they are not radically distinct, then there is no essential difference
between the two; mind is essentially the same as matter. Crusius replies
to this objection that although mind and matter share a property, namely
the general capacity (General-Eigenschaft) to move, the fact that they
share a property does not imply that there are no relevant differences
between mind and matter. For the capacity to move lies in the general
essence (General-Wesen) of mind and matter, rather than in each
one's specific difference (Differential-Wesen), which is what
accounts for the differences between mind and matter.
The second objection states that it is not possible for a mind to
have the capacity to move a body, since that would violate a mind's
basic essence (Grund-Wesen) as a thinking thing. His response to this
objection is essentially the same as to the first objection. One can
explain the capacity of a mind to move a body if one considers the
general essence of a mind.(97) Whereas the error underlying the first
objection stems from ignoring the specific difference between mind and
matter, the error in this case arises from ignoring their general
essence.
The third objection Crusius considers is the traditional objection
raised against Physical Influx that Physical Influx would violate both
the law of the conservation of motion and the law of the conservation of
moving forces. Crusius bites the bullet and rejects as impossible these
particular laws, noting that if they were true, the absurd result would
follow that minds could not cause any motion and that matter would not
be able to fulfill the purpose for which God intended it, namely as a
means to rational and free beings.(98) Thus Crusius turns the argument
around and challenges the conservation laws.(99)
Crusius is also important insofar as he develops a detailed
ontological foundation for Physical Influx.(100) For the proponent of
Pre-established Harmony it is sufficient to endow each substance with a
single force that is responsible for unfolding itself (that is, the
substance) from one state to the next. Although Leibniz adds further
forces, such as the representational power and the active and passive
dynamical forces, they are not added due to the conditions of causality.
In short, in order to maintain intrasubstantial causation, only a single
force is required. With Physical Influx, however, the situation is
entirely different. As Gottsched and Knutzen both demonstrate, a
substance must have the force to act directly on other substances, and
Knutzen argues that two forces are necessary. However, neither Gottsched
nor Knutzen develops a sophisticated and detailed account of such a
force, although such an account is required if one is to have a fully
developed account of physical influx. Crusius is important because he
provides just such an account.
At [subsections]79-81 of the Entwurf Crusius provides an explicit
and detailed account of basic forces. Crusius distinguishes forces as
follows:
Whatever a cause contributes to the production of an effect, it
accomplishes either 1) through its mere existence because through
it
the existence, or a certain manner of existing, of another thing is
made
possible or impossible or necessary.... Such causes are called
existential-grounds. [sections]36 The force thereof can be called
the
inefficacious capacity of an existential ground (facultas
existentialis)....
Or 2) the cause acts due to an inner property of its essence which
is
now directed toward the production of this effect: Thus, one
attributes
to it an activity or self-activity. It is called an active cause
and its force
an active force (Facultas actiua). Thus, an active force is a
property
connected to a substance belonging to its inner essence due to
which
something else is actual through it or comes to be....
[sections] 80. The difficulty found in an object of accepting the
action of a cause is called the reaction or resistance....
[sections] 81. Among active substances an activity can depend in
turn on another of which it is an effect. But this series cannot
proceed
infinitely, but rather one must ultimately come to first actions
that arise
from the force of subjects not through another action but rather
immediately and are nothing other than the application of the first
basic
forces themselves. I want to call these basic activities (actiones
primas). Two species of these are conceivable. First, such basic
activities that persist due to the essence of the substance and
that
constitute the inner essence of the active substances.... Further
there
is such a species of basic activities that do not constantly
act.(101)
Crusius proceeds to distinguish the notion of basic forces into
various further headings. However, we can already see that he has
developed a much more sophisticated model of physical influx than either
Gottsched or Knutzen.(102) For he has proposed a full-blown account of
Physical Influx, not just a sketch or an outline.
The Weg zur Gewi[beta]heit In his Weg zur Gewi[beta]heit(103)
Crusius not only develops further objections to Pre-established Harmony
on the basis of the general metaphysics presented in the Entwurf,(104)
but, more importantly, he also explains in greater detail how Physical
Influx applies to the mind-body relationship. First, like Gottsched and
Knutzen, he rejects the idea that accidents could be transferred from
the mind to the body or vice versa, since "ideas are mental
activities, which are neither motions nor possible through
motions." He also adds that ideas are not "a special class of
things that would be an intermediary between a substance and an
accident"(105) (though he does not clarify what their positive
ontological status is). Instead, Crusius attempts to address in as much
detail as possible how the mind and the body act on each other, given
that it is not through a transfer of accidents. Accordingly, Crusius
states that
a real action cannot however consist in the fact that motions in the
body preceding the sensation bring about the sensation-idea For that
would be contradictory because there would be more in the effect than in
the cause.... For just that reason an idea cannot be either the
proximate or the sufficient cause of a motion. For it conflicts with our
understanding of an idea because an idea is only an activity through
which something is represented in the understanding, but not something
from which an effect of the soul outside itself is considered possible.
Consequently, either a motion must be only a condition upon whose
presence an idea arises by means of a mental force whose efficacy,
however, is tied to the motion; or the motion must arise as a byproduct from the efficacy of such a mental force as is awakened at the same time
through the liveliness of another mental force as through its
condition.(106)
Crusius explains this model in more detail as follows: "The
motion in the instruments of the external senses causes a motion of the
substance of the soul. And this motion of the substance of the soul has
been made by God, by means of certain laws of actions in nature, into
the condition under which certain mental forces, which are the true
efficacious causes of representations, become lively and
efficacious."(107) Crusius sees the need for a motion of the
substance of the soul because "a motion can bring about nothing
other than another motion. Consequently, in this way nothing other than
a motion of the substance of the soul can be caused which can thus be
only the condition of the sensation-idea that arises."(108)
Further, "with this motion [of the substance of the soul] the
matter that immediately surrounds the soul, which are presumably the
life spirits, must be able to yield easily and move out of the
way."(109) In short, motions can cause only motions so that if the
body is to act on the soul, then the soul must be in motion. The
soul's motion is then in some way a necessary condition for its
mental activity. In this way Crusius develops a more detailed solution
to the mind body problem that is sensitive to the kinds of demands that
one would want to place on the causal powers of minds and bodies.(110)
IV
Summary. In sum, we can see a significant degree of development
from Gottsched through Knutzen to Crusius insofar as each develops a
model of physical influx in increasing detail in terms of a
substance's capacity to act on other substances, thereby responding
to one of the central criticisms raised by proponents of Pre-established
Harmony. We have also seen that these proponents of Physical Influx are
capable of developing interesting arguments for their position,
arguments that are sensitive to Leibnizian principles. Further, these
developments are not lost on one rather significant philosopher, off
working away in East Prussia: Kant.(111) In his pre-Critical period
(starting as early as the True Estimation of Living Forces [1746], but
continuing through the Nova dilucidatio [1755] and the Inaugural
Dissertation [1770]) Kant develops increasingly sophisticated arguments
for his own version of Physical Influx. (112) However, if one were to
move directly from Leibniz to Hume's critique of the very notion of
causality, this rich and interesting story would be missed.(113)
Correspondence to: Department of Philosophy, Virginia Polytechnic
Institute and State University, Blacksburg, Virginia 24061. (1) See, for
example, Louis Loeb, From Descartes to Hume. Continental Metaphysics and
the Development of Modern Philosophy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1981), and Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy (New York:
Image, 1959-1960). Exceptions are Max Wundt, Die deutsche
Schulphilosophie im Zeitalter der Aufklarung (1945; reprint, Hildesheim:
Olms. 1964); John Yolton, Locke and French Materialism (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1991); and Karl Ameriks, "The Critique of
Metaphysics: Kant and Traditional Ontology," in The Cambridge
Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992), 249-79. (2) See Eric Watkins, "Kant's Third
Analogy of Experience," Kant-Studien (forthcoming) and Eric
Watkins, "Kant's Theory of Physical Influx," Archiv fur
Geschichte der Philosophie 77 (1995): 285-324 for correctives to this
view. (3) Eileen O'Neill considers the historical development of
this doctrine up to Leibniz, in her "Influxus Physicus," in
Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and
Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania
State University Press, 1993), 27-55. (4) `Pre-established
Harmony', `Occasionalism', and `Physical Influx' refer to
the theories of pre-established harmony, occasionalism, and physical
influx. I should also note that Physical Influx is not a theory that
applies only to material substances. Accordingly, the term
`physical' in physical influx should be taken not literally (as
corporeal), but rather as natural (as opposed to hyperphysical or
supernatural). It is worth noting that physical influx is also sometimes
contrasted with moral influx. Cf. Johann Peter Reusch, Systema
metaphysicum (Jena, 1735), [sections]264. (5) Unless otherwise noted,
`substance' refers to finite (that is, non-divine) substances along
with their natural (non-miraculous) properties. (6) It is also the way
in which they were generally understood in the debate in early
eighteenth-century Germany. (7) Cf. A New System of the Nature and
Communication of Substances, and of the Union of the Soul and Body, in
Philosophical Essays, ed. and trans. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989), 138-45, esp. 143-4. Unless otherwise
noted, all quotations from Leibniz will be from the Philosophical Essays
and referred to by "PE." It should be noted (against Leibniz)
that it is not clear that any Scholastic ever held such a model of
physical influx. Although Suarez at times uses the term `influere',
he certainly does not subscribe to this model. (8) Cf. [sections]80 of
the Monadology (PE, 223). For a helpful discussion of this issue, see
Daniel Garber, "Leibniz: physics and philosophy," in The
Cambridge Companion to Leibniz, ed. Nicholas Jolley (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1994), 270-352; and Martha Bolton,
"Locke and Leibniz on a Dilemma for Mechanism: Mind-Body
Causality." Paper presented at the Midwest Seminar in the History
of Early Modern Philosophy, Purdue, December 5, 1994. (9) Cf. A New
System of Nature (PE, esp. 143-5). (10) For a discussion of
Leibniz's conception of substance, see Christia Mercer and Robert
Sleigh, "Metaphysics: The early period to the Discourse on
Metaphysics," in The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz, 67-123. (11)
See, for example, Primary Truths (PE, 32). (12) Franz Budde, Georg
Walch, and, to a lesser extent, Andreas Rudiger, to mention only the
most important Pietists directly engaged in the dispute. (13) For the
full story, see Wolff, Eigene Lebensbeschreibung (Leipzig, 1841), 28;
Wundt, Die deutsche Schulphilosophie, 230-64; and Eduard Zeller,
"Wolff's Vertreibung aus Halle; der Kampf des Pietismus mit
der Philosophie" Preussische Jahrbucher 10 (1862): 47-72. (14)
Ludwig Philipp Thummig (1697-1728) publishes his own textbook
Institutiones Philosophiae Wolffianae (Frankfurt, 1725-26) which, as the
title indicates, presents Wolff's philosophy in Latin. [Note: For
all references to texts published prior to this century, I shall cite
only the place and date of publication.] See below for more on
Bilfinger's importance and authorship. Johann Peter Reusch
(1691-1754) publishes two textbooks entitled Systema logicum and Systema
metaphysicum (both in Jena, 1734 and 1735 respectively). Friedrich
Christian Baumeister (1709-85) publishes Institutiones philosophiae
rationalis (Wittenberg, 1735), Philosophia definitiva, (6th ed.;
Wittenberg, 1743) and Institutiones metaphysicae (Wittenberg, 1743).
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (1714-62) publishes Metaphysica (Halle,
1739), Acroasis logica (Halle, 1761), and Aesthetica (Frankfurt, 1750).
Georg Friedrich Meier, in addition to translating Baumgarten's
Acroasis Logica into German, authors Beweis der vorherbestimmten
Harmonie (Halle, 1739) and a number of specific treatises, such as
Beweis, da[beta] keine Materie dencken konne (2d ed.; Halle, 1751).
Samuel Christian Hollmann publishes his three-volume textbook,
Institutiones philosophicae, from 172734 and a number of other, smaller
works during the 1730s, including correspondence with Bilfinger and
Schreiber. (15) While the situation is complicated by other factors, it
is relevant to note that a similar debate arises in both England and
France. And, at least in France, it seems to have been raised in part by
the German debate, given that it begins only a short time after the
debate was raging in Germany. Cf. Yolton, Locke and French Materialism.
In England, it was Locke's suggestion that matter might think that
complicated the debate. Thus it seems to be the case both that the
debate was Europe-wide and that Germany was one of its principal
sources; this underscores its historical importance for modern
philosophy as a whole. (16) For a more comprehensive account of both
this particular issue and related ones, see Eric Watkins, "From
Pre-established Harmony to Physical Influx: The Reception of Leibniz in
Early Eighteenth-Century Germany," in Leibniz and the Sciences, ed.
Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
forthcoming). (17) Rudiger, who is loosely affiliated with the Pietists
as well as with Thomasius, was Crusius's teacher. (18) Both
Gottsched's dissertations and his Weltweisheit were originally
published in Leipzig. (19) It is unclear whether these objections were
actually made by any Cartesians in this form against Physical Influx,
since Gottsched cites only Descartes's Principia philosophiae
(Amsterdam, 1644). (20) Gottsched, Vindiciarum systematic influxus
physici, pt. 1 (1729), 34-5. (21) Descartes holds that the quantity of
motion (that is, mv) is conserved, whereas Leibniz argues that living
forces (that is, [mv.sup.2]) are conserved. Cf. Leibniz, Specimen
dynamicum in PE, esp. 121, and the Discourse on Metaphysics [sections]17
in PE, 49-51. (22) I suspect that this dichotomy between official and
unofficial positions is caused by Gottsched's conflicting desires
(1) to publish a popularization of Wolff's philosophy (which
maintains Pre-established Harmony) and (2) to present what he believes
to be true (Physical Influx). Gottsched attempts to resolve the tension
between these desires by not taking an official position on the issue,
while still making his views known. Benno Erdmann interprets
Gottsched's statements in such a way that Gottsched was either
(*) The Development of Physical Influx in Early Eighteenth-Century
Germany: Gottsched, Knutzen, and Crusius" has been selected as the
winner for 1994 of the Dissertation Essay Competition, which is
sponsored by The Philosophy Education Society, Incorporated, publisher
of the Review of Metaphysics. Details of the Competition are listed in
the September 1995 issue. confused or simply could not decide: "A
mind like Gottsched could never make it to definitive clarity":
"Zu entschiedener Klarheit zwar konnte ein Geist, wie Gottsched,
nie kommen"; Benno Erdmann, Martin Knutzen und seine Zeit
(Hildesheim, 1876), 81. (23) "Keine derselben ist noch vollkommen
erklaret oder demonstriret; eine jede davon hat noch ihre
Schwierigkeiten: es kann sich also ein jeder an diejenige halter, die
ihm am besten gefallt. Mir ist es indessen allezeit vorgekommen: daB man
nicht eher Ursache habe, die alleralteste und gemeineste Meynung vom
naturlichen Einflusse zu verwerfen; bis man sie vollkommen widerleget,
und ihre Unmoglichkeit erwiesen haben wird. Dieses aber ist, noch zur
Zeit, von niemanden geschehen"; Gottsched, Erste Grunde der
gesammten Weltweisheit, [sections]1077, Ausgewahlte Werke, vol. 5, pt.
1, 6th ed. (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1983), 586. Note: all passages quoted
from the sixth edition are present in the first edition, except where
differences are explicitly noted. Also, all translations are my own.
(24) Gottsched, Erste Grunde der gesammten Weltweisheit,
[subsections]1078-9. In [sections]1079 of the sixth edition of the
Weltweisheit, Gottsched refers to Knutzen's position and notes that
Knutzen expounds in more detail the position that he (Gottsched) has
defended since 1729 in his dissertations. Erdmann argues that Knutzen
develops his view independently of Gottsched; see Erdmann, Martin
Knutzen, 82. It should also be noted, in light of the discussion below
concerning Gottsched's position on the general cosmological issue,
that both this point and the next do not seem to bear on the general
issue. (25) Ibid., 582. (26) Knutzen will give a very similar response
to the first of these objections (see Systema Causarum efficientium
[Leipzig] [subsections]48-49), and he will give a similar response to an
objection that differs slightly from the second objection, namely that
Physical Influx implies the falsity of the immortality of the soul
([sections]57). (27) "Die Seele hat namlich eine Bemuhung, neue
Empfindungen hervor zu bringen (1051. [sections].). Diese kann sie nicht
haben, wenn ihr Korper nicht eine solche Lage und Stellung in der Welt
hat, daB, vermittelst der sinnlichen GliedmaBen, die materialischen
Bilder im Gehirne erwecket werden konnen. Also strebet sie denn zu
gleicher Zeit, nach dieser veranderten Stellung oder Lage des
Korpers"; Gottsched, Weltweisheit, 587. (28) "Es sind schon in
den flussigen Theilen des Leibes so viele Krafte vorhanden: daB selbige
gleichsam nur eine Aufweckung und Bestimmung bedorfen, wenn sie wirken
sollen. Konnen wir es aber noch nicht erklaren, wie es damn'
zugehe, daB die Seele irgend den Nervensaft in Bewegung brings; so
konnen wir es ja auch in den Korpern noch nicht vollig begreifen, wie
eine an die andere stoBende Kugel dieselbe in Bewegung setzet. Denn da
in alien Puncten, wo sich dieselben beruhren, Monaden oder Elemente
vorhanden sind: so mussen diese doch in einander wirken, und die
Bewegung fortpflanzen konnen, ob wir gleich nicht wissen wie";
ibid., [sections]1081, 587-8. (29) It is difficult to discern from this
passage whether Gottsched is making the further claim that two forces
must be exercised for a change to occur (as Knutzen will argue) or
whether one suffices. (30) "Konnte aber die Seele alle Empfindungen
auch ohne denselben haben: wozu ware ihr ein Leib nutze? Ein Idealist
haste sodann eine weit bessere Meynung; well er durch das Laugnen der
Korper, unzahlige Schwierigkeiten uberhoben wurde"; Gottsched,
Weltweisheit,, [sections]1082, 588. It is worth noting that this
objection is frequently cited in the ensuing debate (for instance, by
Reusch and, below, Crusius). (31) Somehow Gottsched seems not to have
understood that, properly speaking, Leibniz is an idealist. (32)
"Doch ich gebe dieses alles nur fur bloBe MuthmaBungen aus, und
lasse es dahin gestellt sein: welche Meynung bey einem reifern
Erkenntnisse der Seele und des Leibes, mit der Zeit die Oberhand
behalten wird"; ibid., 588. (33) Benno Erdmann, in Martin Knutzen
und seine Zeit, gives a nice, if not always entirely accurate, account
of Knutzen and his historical setting, including an account of
Knutzen's other works. For example, Erdmann notes that
Knutzen's Philosophischer Beweis von der Wahrheit der Christlichen
Religionis reprinted five times and is even translated into Danish (p.
53). (34) For information on which of Leibniz's works were
published and available at what date, see Emile Ravier, Bibliographie de
Oevres de Leibniz (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1966). (35) For one account
of the differences between Wolff and Leibniz, see Charles Corr, "C.
Wolff and Leibniz," Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (1975):
241-62. (36) How the position Knutzen is attacking is Leibnizian will be
demonstrated in footnotes accompanying the relevant argument. What we
shall find is that Knutzen gives a number of different arguments at
different levels of generality so that the position he is attacking will
be Leibnizian in some way, whether it be the "middle" or
"later" Leibniz. (37) It is somewhat unfortunate that Knutzen
seems to focus on the New System of Nature, since Leibniz's
position in that treatise is somewhere between his middle and later
positions. (38) Knutzen's argument is quite similar to
Leibniz's in the New System of Nature. For Knutzen argues as
follows:
"[sections]. XX. The existence of monads in bodies or the
composition of bodies from monads is shown.
Bodies consist of simples or monads. Bodies are composite entities
([sections]. 19.), and therefore consist of parts (according to the same
[sections]). Either these parts are in turn composite, that is, they
will have other parts that again have others and so on to infinity, or
one must reach at last parts that do not consist of others. If the
former, there is an infinite number of parts the existence of which
implies a contradiction (as is demonstrated in the diss. de Aeternitate
Mundi impossibili [sections]. 21): therefore, a body is composed of
parts that do not have other parts. Therefore, it consists of simplex,
or monads ([sections]. 18)." (39) Cf. [sections]XXVII. "It is
demonstrated that simple elements are in a place and are moved, although
they do not fill a space." (40) "[sections]. XXVIII. Vis
seipsam mouendi inuoluit vim alia quoque mouendi realiter.
Vis mouendi, quae efficit, vt ens quodpiam locum suum proprium mutes, sine vi mouendi, res alias, quibus cingitur, concipi nequit, sed
ista posita haec simul ponatur, necesse est. Vis enim mouendi, quae
efficit, vt ens locum suum proprium mutes, non est, nisi conatus, hunc
suum mutandi locum ([sections]. 24.) i. e. occupandi locum ab eo, quem
iam occupat, dinersum et quidem eidem continuum ([sections]. cit.). Sed
coexistentia alia, quae vbique mobile cingunt, loca ista a loco mobilis
diuersa obtinent; duo autem diuersa entia simul in eodem loco esse
nequeunt ([sections]. 23.): ens ergo vi se ipsum mouendi praeditum, res
alias loco pellere nitetur, si illae resistant. Quod si vero etiam
sponte cedere supponantur, tamen id quod in nisu tall, qui requiritur ad
motum extra se perficiendum, siue alias res loco pellendas, in motu
progressiuo iam adest; cum resistentia sit tantum cause occasionalis
motus, nec vi intrinsecae quicquam addat: Ens ergo, quod se ipsum moues,
conatu gaudet mutandi locum coexistentium seu vi mouendi res alias
([sections]. 24.). Vis ergo, se ipsum mouendi, sine vi mouendi res alias
concipi nequit, sed ista posita, haec ponitur simul." (41) Note
that Knutzen formulates this argument quite generally so as to pertain
to any being of which a Leibnizian will claim that it can change its own
place. Thus the argument will certainly apply to bodies, to corporeal
substances of Leibniz's middle period, and perhaps even to the
monads of the later Leibniz (since monads are in some sense in a place
and responsible for the changes that occur in bodies, so that one could
say that they change the place of their body). For a discussion of
Leibniz's conception of substance in his middle and later periods,
see Robert Sleigh, Leibniz and Arnauld, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), 98-104; Christia Mercer and Robert Sleigh,
"Metaphysics: The early period to the Discourse on
Metaphysics," in The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz; and Donald
Rutherford, "Metaphysics: The late period," in ibid. (42) As
the argument stands, it is, of course, incomplete. For Knutzen simply
accepts without argument that every being is surrounded in all
directions, that is, that there is no void. Accordingly, the argument
might seem to stand in need of substantial supplementation. However, the
argument would presumably have appeared plausible to Leibniz because he
accepts the Principle of Sufficient Reason which he then takes to
exclude the possibility of a void; cf. Primary Truths in PE, 33. In
fact, Leibniz rejects the void for further reasons as well; cf. Specimen
dynamicum in PE, 130. (43) In fact, ar. anonymous reviewer of this work
makes the same objection to Knutzen's argument. Cf.
Zuverla[beta]ige Nachrichten vom dem gegenwartigen Zustande, Veranderung
und Wachstum der Wissenschaften, Teil 73 (Leipzig, 1746), 48-67, esp.
50-3. (44) Knutzen is quite explicit about this model. In [sections]44,
responding to the charge that Physical Influx is merely the flowing out
and metamorphosis of motion and ideas, Knutzen states the following:
"While the body acts on the mind according to the system of
physical influx, it does not pour ideas of external things into the
mind, nor the force of representation; but rather it modifies only the
force of the mind and its substance in such a grounded way that
representation is caused in the mind. But the mind, when it acts on the
body, does not pour a moving force into it, but rather only modifies and
directs with its actions those things to the extent that are present in
corporeal elements in such a way that finally motion is produced in the
body. For ideas and the force of representation are either accidents or
substances. If they are accidents: they cannot be poured into the mind
by the body and they cannot be transferred into the mind by a certain
local motion from the body. For accidents do not migrate from subject to
subject ([section]. 791. Ontol.). But if you suppose that they are
substances: similarly such a transition cannot be granted; because the
mind is a simple substance ([sections]. 18.), but such a first substance
cannot be the receptacle of a number of other substances. Therefore,
neither ideas nor the forces of representation can be poured from the
body into the mind. However, because representations of external things
appear in the mind through the action of the body ([sections]. 40.
not.): nothing remains other than that the body, while it is acting on
the mind, modifies its force and substance in such a way that
representations of external things in fact appear or are caused in the
mind. For a similar reason it can be shown that no moving force can be
transferred from the mind to the body: and so through the action of the
mind only those forces that the moderns have shown to be present in the
elements [of the body] ([sections]. 196. Cosmol.) are modified and
directed for a certain reason in such a way that determinate motion is
finally produced in the body through the determination of these
forces": "Dum corpus in mentem agit vi systematic physic)
influxus, neque menti rerum externarum ideas infundit, neque vim
repraesentatricem; sed modo vim mentis eiusdemque substantiam tall
ratione modificat, ut repraesentatio in mente oriatur. Mens vero, dum in
corpus agit, nullam eidem vim motricem infundit; sed eam tantum, quae
corporis elementis inest, ita actione sua modificat ac dirigit, ut motus
demum in corpore producatur. Ideae enim ac vis repraesentatrix vel
accidentia sunt vel substantiae. Si sunt accidentia: menti a corpore
infundi ac locali quodam motu e corpore in mentem transire nequeunt;
accidentia enim e subiecto non migrant in subiectum ([sections]. 791.
Ontol.). Si vero substantial esse supponas: similiter eiusmodi transitus
concedi nequit, cum mens sit substantia simplex [sections]. 18.), talis
vero substantia alterius vel plurimarum aliarum substantiarum
receptaculum esse nequeat. Ergo neque ideae, neque vis representatrix e
corpore in mentem transfundi possunt. Cum tamen per corporis actionem
repraesentationes rerum externarum in mente prodeant ([sections]. 40.
not.): nil superest, quam ut corpus, dum in mentem agit, vim eius ac
substantiam ita modificet, vt repraesentationes rerum externarum in
mente reuera prodeant seu excitentur. Simili ratione evinci potest, quod
nulla vis motrix ex mente transeat in corpus: adeoque mentis actione eae
tantummodo vires, quas eiusdem elementis inesse demonstrarunt
recentiores ([sections]. 196. Cosmol.), certa ratione modificentur ac
dirigantur, vt sic demum harum virium determinatione determinatus in
corpore motus producatur"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium,
145-7. (45) For Leibniz a ground is ideal if it exists solely in a
monad's representations. Real grounds can exist independently of
the representations of a monad. See Monadology, in PE, 219 and Letter to
Des Bosses, in PE, 199. (46) See, for example, the New System, in PE,
143. (47) In a sense, no relationship would hold at all between various
substances, if one grants that there are no relationships between
nonexistent substances. (48) "Agere dicitur ens, quando rationem in
se continet existentiae (mutationis) cuiusdam rei"; Knutzen,
Systema Causarum efficientium, [sections]21, p. 78. (49) For a
discussion of the expression thesis, see Robert Sleigh, Leibniz and
Arnauld, 170. (50) Knutzen does not take Leibniz's thesis about the
"equivalence of hypotheses" into account. This omission may
not be of consequence, if the equivalence of hypotheses is taken as a
purely epistemological claim (that we cannot know which of any two
bodies is in motion) as opposed to the metaphysical claim (that bodies
are not in motion, from which the epistemological claim immediately
follows). (51) "Idem quoque aliter posses demonstrari: Simplicia
elementaria sunt impenetrabilia, ex sententia Leibnitii, qui substantiae
finitas omnes impenetrabiles asserit. videatur eius Epist. ad C.
Wagnerum p. 201. Tom. I. Epist. Edit. Kortholtianae. Hinc fieri non
potest, vt vna sit in loco alterius. Ergo datur aliquid reale, vi cuius
vnum simplex alind excludit ac contra nititur, ne in suum irruat locum.
Cum enim moueri simplicia certissimum sit ([sections]. 27.) neque
diuersa simplicia secundum contrariam directionis lineam moueri, adeoque
sibi inuicem occurrere impossibile sit, imo etiam id quod ex conflictu
corporum et occursu eorundem colligimus, reuera contraria directione
contra se inuicem ferantur; sequitur in eo casu statuendum, aut
simplicia se inuicem penetrare, quod contra asserta Leibnitii; aut si
inuicem resistant; in se inuicem agere. Q.e.d."; Knutzen, Systema
Causarum efficientium, [sections]29, p. 95. (52) Knutzen formulates this
argument so as to apply to substances that have resistance or
impenetrability. Thus, again, Knutzen's argument is so general that
it applies to bodies, corporeal substances (in the middle Leibniz), and
again, though this is less clear, perhaps even (the later
Leibniz's) monads (since Leibniz may hold that two monads cannot be
in the same place). (53) It is worth pointing out that in [sections]39
Knutzen explicitly applies these first two arguments to the mind-body
relationship. (54) It is worth noting that Knutzen (like Leibniz before
him and Crusius and Kant after him) considers the issue of causality
both in its completely general form (that is, for any substances
whatsoever) and in the specific guise of the mind-body problem, whereas
many parties to the dispute limit themselves to discussing only the
mind-body problem. As a result, Knutzen's position attains a
greater degree of sophistication. (55) "Perfectio, quae nullam per
se infers limitationem, seu, quae cum omnitudine possibilium (vt
loquuntur Scholastici) consistere potest, perfectio dicitur absolute
talis seu simpliciter simplex. In Theologia natural) autem demonstratur,
quaecunque in Deo T. O. M. locum inueniunt, perfectiones esse
simpliciter simplices, nec, nisi cum limitationibus seu
imperfectionibus, ullam inuoluere repugnantiam"; Knutzen, Systema
Causarum efficientium, [sections]33, p. 107. (Note: T. O. M. is an
abbreviation that stands for ter optimus maximus or "thrice greatest most powerful." Since such an abbreviation is not
currently common, I have omitted it wherever it would occur in the
translation but not in the original Latin.) That Knutzen cites Bilfinger
(and Canz) in the explanatory passage to this definition indicates that
he does not take himself to be positing anything that would be
controversial to the Leibnizians. (56) "Influxus Physicus est
possibilis. Influxus physicus mentis in simplicia corporis et vicissim
eorundem in mentem actione absoluitur ([sections]. 32.). Si adeoque
possibilitas physic) influxus euincenda, ostendendum, eiusmodi mentis
extra se actionem in alia simplicia nullam inuoluere contradictionem
([sections]. 85. ontol.): perpendamus adeoque, num quicquam in mente
reperire liceat, quad eiusdem action) in res external repugnet. Quae in
mente inuenimus, huc potissimum redeunt, quod mens sit ens simplex, nec
non, quod sit ens perceptinum seu percipiens, idque longe eminentioris
gradus, quam simplicia elementaria, siquidem est distincte perceptiuum
seu intellectu et voluntate praeditum ([sections]. 17. 18.).
Simplicitati mentis actio in res external repugnare nequit, cum non modo
Deus T. O. M. extra se agat (per Princip. Theol. N.), sed etiam
simplicia elementaria agent in se inuicem ([sections]. 29.). Neque
quatenus est ens perceptiuum seu percipiens actio haec menti repugnare
potest, cum simplicia elementaria rerum externarum perceptione gaudeant
([sections]. 31.); quibus tamen actio eiusmodi denegari nequit
([sections] 2.9.). The Niligitor superest, quam eminens illa perfectio,
qua mens humane a simplicibus percipientibus inferioribus discernitur,
ac quae intelligendi ac volendi facultatem in mente pooit, cud, si actio
externa mentis non repugnat, influxus possibilitas extra dubium erit
constitute. Est vero actio in res external perfectio simpliciter
simplex, cum in Deo T. O. M. locum habeas ([sections]. 33.); adeoque non
nisi limitation) ac imperfection) repugnare potest ([sections]. cit.):
intellectui igitur et voluntati, quae nudae perception) accedunt,
quibusque simul major enti confertur perfectio repugnare nequit, cum,
enti mere perceptiuo ac imperfectiori actionem eiusmodi conuenire, iam
supra sit euictum. Quis ergo mentem in corpus agere posse dubitare
poterit? Cum autem, simplicibus ex quibus corpus constat, actionem in
alla simplicia tribuendam esse, supra sit demonstratum ([sections].
29.); mens vero, tanquam substantia simplex, in eadem agere possit (per
demonstr.): nulla erit ratio, cur simplicium corporis in mentem actionem
quis iudicet impossibilem. Influxum adeoque physicum possibilem esse,
constat"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficeintium, [sections] 34, p.
108-10. (57) "Unlike the first two arguments, this argument is more
specific in its application, since it applies only to minds. However, it
is clear that Knutzen's understanding of minds does not differ in
any essential way from Leibniz's. (58) See Leibniz's
"Quod ens perfectissimum existit" from 1676 for a passage in
which he is more explicit about this point; Leibniz, Die Philosophischen
Schriften, ed. Carl Gerhardt (1875-90; reprint, Berlin: Olms, 1978),
7:261-2. Please note that I am not suggesting that Kntuzen is aware of
this particular passage. (59) This feature of Knutzen's account is
explicitly stated in Systema Causarum efficientium, [sections]43, p. 142
and [sections]44 (for [sections]44 see note 44 above): "According
to the system of physical influx the human mind is not in every respect
nor specifically in thinking to be conceived of as purely passive":
"Mens humana in systemate Physici influxus nec omni ex parse, nec
speciatim in cogitando mere passiua est concipienda." (60)
"Evincitur enim in Theologia natural): Deum T. O. M. summae ac
infinitae suae sapientiae conformiter, viam eligere naturalem,
brevissimam"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium, [sections]35,
p. 113. (61) "nec ea, quae per pauca fieri naturaliter possum, per
plura seu longior demum via absoluere"; ibid. (62) "Non tamen
breuitatem viae solam vrgeo, sed viam naturaliter breuissimam";
ibid., p. 116. (63) "per ambages [a Deo sapientissimo facta
supponit], cum tot artificia ad hunc consensum, tum in corpore, tum
mente, producendum sint necessarie, vt omnem superent captum";
ibid., p. 117. (64) Of course, the nature of miracles is intensely
debated by Leibniz and Malebranche. (65) It is worth noting that
Bilfinger is influential both in Saint Petersburg and Tubingen. For more
on Bilfinger's general influence, see Heinz Liebing, Zwischen
Orthodoxie und Aufklarung, (Tubingen: Mohr, 1961). (66) For discussion
of this work, see Joachim Kintrup, Das Leib-Seele-Problem in Georg
Bernhard Bilfingers Buch "De harmonia animi et coporis humani,
maxime praestabilita, ex mente illustris Leibnitii, commentatio
hypothetica (1723)" in der geschichtlichen und philosophischen
Zussammensichau (Munster: Munstersche Beitrage zur Geschichte und
Theorie der Medizin, 1974). (67) Although Knutzen is not always as
explicit as one might like, one can perhaps assume that Knutzen accepts
Gottsched's position on the issue of the law of motion;
accordingly, only the issue of motive forces remains. (68)
"[sections]54. Objection VII. A defect in the proportion between
the motion of the body and the decrees that follow from the mind.
Causes and effects are proportional amongst each other or the
effects are proportional to the causes by which they are produced and
the causes in turn are proportional to the effects that have been
produced by them. But the forces of the mind and the motions of the body
are not mutually proportional to each other. Therefore, the motions of
the body are not at all produced by the force of the mind or the forces
of the mind and the motions of the will in the body are not related as
causes and effects amongst each other; thus, to this extent there is no
influx of the body in the mind and vice versa"; Knutzen, Systema
Causarum efficientium, p. 184. (69) "[sections]55. Objection VIII.
that the effect is greater than its cause according to physical influx.
The whole effect is equal to the full cause. But in the system of
physical influx what is considered to be whole effect is not equal to
the full cause. Therefore, what is considered to be the effect in the
system of physical influx is not the effect. Therefore, there is no
influx of the mind on the body nor vice versa. The learned Bilfinger
built a proof of the minor premise on this foundation because in
physical influx the effect is greater than its cause, because sc. not
only is the motion of the fluid nerves in the brain caused by motion in
the sense organs, and they in turn cause the motion of another that then
releases the full effect: but besides this effect and the other there is
sc. representation in the mind that therefore reflects an effect greater
than the cause"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium, pp. 190-1.
(70) "nego minorem, sc. quod ex Physico Influxu sequatur, in
conflictu corporum inter se eandem virium quantitatem haud
conseruari"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium, [sections]53,
p. 177. (71) "Adeoque quamdui nondum euictum est ac euinci potest,
istam motus legem de conseruanda eadem virium viuarum quantitate non
modo corporibus in se inuicem agentibus, sed et menti in corpus agent)
et vicissim praescriptam esse; prorsus nil praesens objectio Influxui
physico nocebit"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium,
[sections]53, p. 178. (72) "quod sc. Corpus quodlibet perseueret in
statu suo quiescendi et movendi uniformiter in directum, nisi a causa
extrinseca statuary suum mutare cogatur" and "Euidentissimum
igitur est, mentem in statu suo acquiescendi ac mouendi uniformiter in
directum, donec ab extrinseco statuary mutare cogatur, haud
permanere"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum effirientium, [sections]53,
p. 182. (73) "Notandum esse in influxu physico 1) ipsam motus
impressionem, qui monadibus communicatur in eisdem excitare
perceptionem, nam communicatio motus non nisi per modificationem virium,
quae elementis insunt et quas perceptiuas statuit Leibnitius peragi
potest; adeoque vltra communicationem motus aliud nil requiritur, ad
excitandum perceptionem; et quemadmodum in monadibus corporum similiter
et in anima"; Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium, [sections]55,
p. 192. (74) See also Knutzen, Systema Causarum efficientium,
[sections]55, p. 195. (75) I do not intend to be taking a stand on the
much-discussed issue of whether Leibniz does or does not hold
phenomenalism with respect to bodies. (76) Here it is important to note
that what we mean by Pre-established Harmony is the doctrine of
intrasubstantial causation because sometimes Leibniz does call the
concomitance between efficient and final causes Preestablished Harmony,
though with a completely distinct meaning. The two doctrines are not at
all logically related. (77) Certainly Occasionalism is in no way
distinct from Pre-established Harmony on this point, though, if Knutzen
is right, neither is Physical Influx. (78) Euler considers and rejects
Pre-established Harmony in his Gedanchen von den Elementen der Korper,
(Berlin, 1746); Reflexions sur l'espace et le temps, (Berlin,
1748); and Lettres a une princesse d'Allemagne sur divers sujets de
physique et de philosophic (St. Petersburg, 1768-72). For Darjes, see
[subsection]54-90 in Elementa Metaphysices, V. II (Jena, 1743-44) and
for Plouquet, see [subsection]456-483 in Principia de Substantiis et
Phaenomenis (Frankfurt, 1753 and 1764). (79) If the noncorporeal element
were sufficient, the corporeal element would be superfluous. (80)
Erdmann, Martin Knutzen und seine Zeit, 94-5. For, as I hope to show,
although the questions change somewhat, it is still the same debate, and
substantial progress is made. (81) In a preliminary version of her
dissertation, Alison Laywine suggests such a line of argumentation; see
Alison Laywine. "Physical Influx and the Origins of the Critical
Philosophy." Ph.D. dies., University of Chicago, 1991. (82)
Crusuis's degree of sophistication over, say, Wolff's is
immediately apparent if one compares, for example, each one's
introduction to cosmology. Both consider the concept of world in order
to give a proper definition. However, whereas Wolff simply claims that
one must know what a world is in order to understand what a soul is
(Vernunfftige Gedancken [sections]540), Crusius presents a number of
methodological points that must be kept in mind if one is to define the
essence of the world, a metaphysical truth, rather than, for example,
any merely contingent truth about this world (Entwurf [sections]347).
(83) "eine Welt hei[beta]t eine solche reale Verknupfung endlicher
Dinge, welche nicht selbst wiederum ein Theil von einer andern ist, zu
welcher sie vermittelst einer realen Verknupfung gehorte"; Crusius,
Entwurf, [sections]350. (84) "Wir unterscheiden eine Welt von
mehrern zugleich seyenden Geschopfen oder Inbegriffen derselben, welche
aber in gar keiner Verknupfung stehen. Die Welt soil etwas eines seyn,
und zwar ein solches, welches auch au[beta]erhalb unserer Gedancken ein
Eines ist. Daher mussen die darzu gehorigen Dinge in einer realen
Verbindung stehen"; ibid., [sections]349. (85) Actually, Leibaiz
does not think that we can know the truth values of counterfactuals,
that is, that we can think monads in other possible worlds. Thus this
problem would not arise for him. However, he is saddled with the
difficulty of explaining why we cannot represent other possible ways the
world could have been. (86) This latter possibility is not so
straightforward because for Leibuiz (unlike Descartes) possible worlds
are given in God's understanding, not determined by God's
will. Accordingly, it may not be in God's power to stipulate what
possible worlds are (even if it is in his power to determine which
possible worlds become actual). (87) It should be noted, for later
purposes as well, that Crusius does derive a number of necessary truths
from the definition of the world: its finitude, its creation and hence
beginning in time, the conservation of the world at every moment by God,
that creation must include rational and free creatures, and so forth
([subsection]351-4). (88) "eine jedwede Vereinigung zufalliger
Dinge, welche au[beta]erhalb der Gedancke eine reale undo existentialis
seyn soil, auf einer Causalverknupfung der Dinge beruhen musse, vermoge
deren zum wenigsten eines gegen das andere thatig wircken mu[beta],
wiewohl auch beyde wechselweise gegen einander thatig seyn, und auch
wechselweise voneinander leiden konnen. Denn es ist sonst nichts anders
ausserhalb der Gedanke moglich, was einen Grund der Vereinigung zwischen
vollstandigen Dingen abgeben ken. Sobald man dahero dieses hinweg nimmt,
so mu[beta] man sie nur durch einen Begriff im Verstande vereinigen,
d.i. die Dinge haben alsdenn entweder gar keine oder doch nur eine
blo[beta] ideale Vereinigung. Daher kann ich z. E. nicht einraumen,
da[beta] diejenigen, welche die prastabilirte Harmonie glauben, eine
reale Vereinigung zwischen Leib und Seele ubrig lessen. Ihre Vereinigung
ist bey Setzung dieser Meynung so gar in Absicht auf Gott selbst nur
ideal. Man ken nicht einmal sagen, da[beta] sie nur vermittelst der
Darzwischentretung Gottes vereinigt werden. Denn alsdenn mu[beta]te doch
Gott zum wenigsten die Einrichtung des Wesens des Leibes und der Seele
zugeschreiben werden konnen. Dieses konnen aber die Vertheidiger der
prastabilirten Harmonie in dem rechten Leibuitzischen Verstande, nicht
sagen, well sie Gott keine Ehre weiter ubrig lessen, als da[beta] er nur
die Wesen der Substanzen zur Wirklichkeit gebracht, nicht aber
eingerichtet habe, well alle Wesen ewig sein sollen. Es bleibt dahero
eine blosse Ubereinstimmung, nicht aber eine reale Vereinigung
ubrig"; Crusius, Entwurf, [sections]94. (89) It may be that Crusius
is insinuating other arguments here as well. For example, his allusion to the eternity of substances (and thus the world) is a consequence he
clearly believes to contradict the Principle of Contingency
([sections]33). He states the principle as follows: "that whose
non-being can be thought really did not exist at one time, which one
calls the Principle of Contingency": "dasjenige, dessen
Nichtseyn sich denken la[beta]t, wirklich einmal nicht gewesen sey,
welches man den Satz von der Zufalligkeit nennen kan." (90) Kant
sometimes alludes to this kind of criticism as well; see Immanuel Kant,
Gesammelte Werke, ed. Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften
(Berlin: De Gruyter, 1902), 28:215. (91) At this point, it is
appropriate to recall that Crusius advances a strongly voluntaristic
position with respect to God. This position explains how Crusius can
object to Leibniz in this manner. (92) "Und wenn man, um eine
Ausflucht zu haben, eine besondere Classe der Vereinigung erdichtet,
welche man die metaphysische nennen will, und welche darinnen bestehen
soil, da[beta] ein Ding das andere vorstellet, so wird hiermit der erste
Begriff der realen Vereinigung verlassen"; Crusius, Entwurf,
[sections]94. (93) Also, Crusius must have known that Wolff does not
specifically attribute representational powers to corporeal substances.
If Crusius wants more explanation of what it means for Wolff that
corporeal substances are `directed toward' all others, then his
point is well taken. However, this lack of an explanation on
Wolff's part does not warrant an argument to the contrary position.
(94) Kripke and Putnam have shown that stipulation need not be taken as
"ideal," since stipulation can be embedded in social practices
with causal histories. Thus there is no a priori inference from the
stipulative character to the ideal character of "directed
toward," even if it is divine stipulation that is at issue. (95)
This charge is not completely just, given the developments discussed
below. However, he himself admits at [sections]94 of the Entwurf:
"it is impossible that a finite understanding should be able to
comprehend all possible kinds of connection": "es ist
unmoglich, da[beta] ein endlicher Verstand alle mogliche Arten der
Vereinigung sollte begreifen konnen." (96) Crusius's argument
anticipates Kant's in several respects. See Watkins,
"Kant's Theory of Physical Infiux." (97) In this context,
Crusius adds that impenetrability is included in the general essence of
the mind without noting that impenetrability and the capacity to move
another body are not necessarily identical. However, in [sections]402 of
the Entwurf he does suggest that impenetrability is the ground of moving
another substance. (98) "For if this were the case [that is, if
this law of the conservation of motion were true], minds could cause no
motion; and if said, that a single sum of motion remains in the material
world constantly, then no part of the motion of matter could be used for
the motion of the substance of minds. But then the material world would
be of no use to minds, and it would have been created completely without
a purpose": "Denn wenn dieses ware, so konnten die Geister
keine Bewegung verursachen; und wenn sags, da[beta] in der materialen
Welt bestandig einerley Summe der Bewegung bleibe, so konnte auch kein
Theil von der Bewegung der Materie auf die Bewegung der Substanz der
Geister verwendet werden. Alsdenn aber ware die materiale Welt den
Geistern nichst nutze, und sie ware vollig ohne Zweck erschaffen";
Crusius, Entwurf [sections]419. (99) See [sections]420 of the Entwurf
for his response to the law of the conservation of motive force. (100)
One can diagnose the fault of the allegedly scholastic version of
Physical Influx as the failure to provide a plausible ontological
foundation; "migrating accidents" are entirely implausible.
(101) "Dasjenige, was eine Ursache zu Hervorbringung eines Effectes
beytragt, verrichtet sie entweder 1) durch ihr blosses Daseyn, well
durch dasselbe die Existenz oder eine gewisse Art zu existiren eines
andern Dinges moglich oder unmoglich, oder nothwendig gemacht wird....
Wir haben solche Ursachen oben Existential-Grunde genennt. [sections]36
Die Kraft derselben kan das unwircksame Vermogen eines
Existential-Grundes heissen, (facultas existentialis).... Oder 2) die
Ursache wircket vermittelst einer innerlichen Eigenschaft ihres Wesens,
welche jetzo zu Hervorbringung dieses Effectes abgerichtet ist: So
schreibet man ihr eine Activitat oder Selbstthatigkeit zu. Sie
hei[beta]t eine thatige Ursache und ihre Kraft eine thatige Kraft,
(Facultas actina) Es ist also eine thatige Kraft eine solche an eine
Substanz verknupfte Eigenschaft ihres innerlichen Wesens, vermogen deren
durch sie etwas anderes wircklich ist, oder entstehet. . .
"[sections] 80. Die in einem Object befindliche Schwierigkeit,
die Action einer Ursache anzunehmen heiet die Reaction, oder der
Wiederstand.
"[sections] 81. In den thatigen Substanzen ken eine Thatigkeit
wiederum von einer andern abhangen, von welcher sie eine Wirckung ist.
Diese Reihe aber ken nicht unendlich fortgehen, sondern man mu[beta]
zoletzt auf erste Actionen kommen, welche aus der Kraft der Subjecte
nicht vermittelst einer andern Action, sondern unmittelbar entspringen,
und nichts anders als die Anwendung der er-ersten Grundkrafte selbst
sind. Ich will dieselben Grund-Thatigkeiten (actiones primas) nennen. Es
lessen sich zweyerley Gattungen derselben dencken. Erstlich solche
Grund-Thatigkeiten, welche vermoge des Wesens der Substanz bestandig
fortdauern, und welche eben das innerliche Wesen der thatigen Substanzen
ausmachen.... Ferner la[beta]t sich auch eine solche Art von
Grund-Thatigkeiten dencken, welche nicht bestandig geschehen."
(102) It is possible that Crusius's sophistication is partially due
to his acquaintance with late scholastics such as Suarez. (103) Crusius,
Weg zur Gewi[beta]heit und Zuverla[beta]gheit der menschlichen
Erkenntnis (Leipzig, 1747). (104) At [subsections]71-6, pp. 124-36 of
the Entwurf, Crusius develops a series of further objections to
Pre-established Harmony showing both a priori and a posterior) that
Pre-established Harmony is neither true, probable, nor possible. (105)
"Denn die Ideen sind geistige Thatigkeiten, welche weder Bewegungen
sind, noch durch Bewegungen moglich sind.... eine besondere Art von
Dingen, welche zwischen einer Substanz und einem Accidente das Mittel
waren"; ibid., [sections]77, p. 140-1. (106) "Diese reale
Einwirkung aber ken nicht darinnen bestehen, da[beta] die vor der
Empfindung vorhergehenden Bewegungen im Korper die Emptindungsidee
selbst hervorbrachten. Denn es ware widersprechend, well in der Wirkung
mehr, als in der Ursache ware.... Aus eben dem Grunde ken auch eine Idee
keine nachste, auch keine zureichende Ursache einer Bewegung seyn. Denn
es streitet mit dem, was wir bey einer Idee denken, well in ihr nur eine
Thatigkeit ist, wodurch etwas im Verstande vorgestellet wird, nicht aber
etwas, worause eine Wirksamkeit der Seele ausser sich als moglich
begriffen wurde. Folglich mu[beta] entweder die Bewegung nur eine
Bedingung seyn, bey deren Gegenwart, die Idee vermittelst einer
geistigen Kraft entstehet, deren Wirksamkeit aber an die Bewegung
gebunden ist; oder die Bewegung mu[beta] als ein Nebenumstand aus der
Wirksamkeit einer solchen geistigen Kraft entstehen, welche durch die
Lebhaftigkeit einer anderen geistigen Kraft, als durch ihre Bedingung
zugleich erwecket wird"; Crusius, Entwurf, [sections]79, pp. 144-5.
(107) "Die Bewegung in den Werkzeugen der ausserlichen Sinne
verursachet eine Bewegung der Substanz der Seele. Und diese Bewegung der
Substanz der Seele ist vermittelst gewisser Gesetze der Actionen in der
Natur von Gott zur Bedingung gemacht worden, unter welcher gewisse
geistige Krafte, welche die wahre wirkende Ursache der Vorstellungen
sind, lebhaft und wirksam werden"; ibid., [sections]80, p. 145.
(108) "Nun ken eine Bewegung nichts anders als wiederum eine
Bewegung hervorbringen. Folglich ken hierdurch nichts anders als eine
Bewegung der Substanz der Seele verursachet werden, welche dahero nur
die Bedingung der entstehenden Empfindungsidee seyn kann"; ibid.,
p. 146. (109) "Bey dieser Bewegung mussen die Materien, welche die
Seele zunachst umgeben, welches vermuthlich die Lebensgeister sind,
bequem nachgeben und ausweichen konnen"; ibid. (110) This solution
does have its costs. For instance, the soul would seem to be at least
partially material since it moves, and the problem of mindbody
interaction is simply pushed back into the depths of the soul because it
remains unclear how the motions of the substance of the soul can be
related to the soul's mental activities. (111) Indeed, they are not
lost on many of the philosophers from this period. For instance, perhaps
the most highly regarded philosopher in Germany in the 1770s, Moses
Mendelssohn, defended Pre-established Harmony (in his Philosophische
Gesprache [Berlin, 1755]). For an account of how Mendelssohn is
important in other ways to the development of Kant's views, see
Paul Guyer, "Mendelssohn and Kant: One Source of the Critical
Philosophy," Philosophical Topics 19 (1991): 119-52. (112) See
Watkins, "Kant's Theory of Physical Influx." (113) I
should like to thank Roger Ariew, Martha Bolton, Jan Cover, Phillip
Cummins, Marjorie Grene, Heiner Klemme, Sven Knebel, Manfred Kuehn, Mike
Murray, and especially Karl Ameriks for their helpful comments on an
earlier version of this paper. Also, I greatly benefited from discussion
with the members of the Fall 1994 Midwest Seminar in the History of
Early Modern Philosophy. Finally, I would like to acknowledge financial
support from the Fulbright Commission and the Germanistic Society of
America for the 1992-93 academic year, during which time I was able to
pursue much of the research