"Joyce, Aquinas, and the Poetic Process".
McLuhan, H. Marshall
"JOYCE, AQUINAS, AND THE POETIC PROCESS" (1)
By Herbert Marshall McLuhan
ANYONE familiar with the persistent use which Joyce makes of the
labyrinth figure as the archetype of human cognition will have noticed
the same figure as it appears in the dramatic action of a Thomistic
"article." There is first the descent into the particular
matter of the "objections." These are juxtaposed abruptly,
constituting a discontinuous or cubist perspective. By abrupt
juxtaposition of diverse views of the same problem, that which is in
question is seen from several sides. A total intellectual history is
provided in a single view. And in the very instant of being presented
with a false lead or path the mind is alerted to seek another course
through the maze. Baffled by variety of choice it is suddenly arrested
by the "sed contra" and given its true bearings in the
conclusion. Then follows the retracing of the labyrinth in the
"respondeo dicendum." Emerging into intellectual clarity at
the end of this process it looks back on the blind alleys proffered by
each of the original objections. Whereas the total shape of each
article, with its trinal divisions into objections, respondeo, and
answers to objections, is an "S" labyrinth, this figure is
really traced and retraced by the mind many times in the course of a
single article. Perhaps this fact helps to explain the power of Thomas
to communicate a great deal even before he is much understood. It
certainly suggests why he can provide rich esthetic satisfactions by the
very dance of his mind--a dance in which we participate as we follow
him.
His "articles" can be regarded as vivisections of the
mind in act. The skill and wit with which he selects his objections
constitute a cubist landscape, an ideal landscape of great intellectual
extent seen from an airplane. The ideas or objects in this landscape are
by their very contiguity set in a state of dramatic tension; and this
dramatic tension is provided with the dramatic peripeteia in the
respondeo, and with a resolution in the answers to the objections.
This, and much more was grasped by the young Joyce who seems to
have been the first to make explicit the relation in Aquinas between the
stages of apprehension and the creative process. In Aristotle the same
view is also implicit, as Joyce was aware. In the Poetics Aristotle
mentions imitation as connate to man, being the process by which men
learn.
But this fact is not linked with the power of abstraction which in
the De Anima he attributes to the nous poietikos or the agent intellect.
That there is, however, a degree of poetic imitation in abstraction
itself is plain from the fact that even in sensation "things exist
in the soul without their proper matter, but with the singularity and
individuating conditions which are the result of matter" (St.
Thomas De Anima, article 13). That this is so is the effect of the nous
poietikos which has the power of individuating anew in a bodily organ
that which it has abstracted from existence. "For in things made by
art the action of an instrument is terminated in the form intended by
the artisan" (Ibid., article 12). Again, "for every object
produced by art is the effect of the action of an artificer, the agent
intellect being related to the phantasms illuminated by it as an
artificer is to the things made by his art" (Ibid., article 5). And
in the same place the creative efficacy of the nous poietikos as
"illuminative" is referred to the text in the Psalms (4:7):
"The light of thy countenance is signed upon us, O Lord."
For Joyce and Eliot all art is a shadow of the Incarnation and
every artist is dedicated to revealing, or epiphanizing, the signatures
of things, so that what the nous poietikos is to perception and
abstraction the artist is to existence at large:
The artist who could disentangle the subtle soul of the image from
its mesh of defining circumstances most exactly and re-embody it in
artistic circumstances chosen as the most exact for its new office, he
was the supreme artist. (Stephen Hero, p. 78).
Ordinary experience is a riot of imprecision, of impressions
enmeshed in pre-conceptions, clich6s, profanities, and impercipience.
But for the true artist every experience is capable of an epiphany:
By an epiphany he meant a sudden spiritual manifestation, whether
in the vulgarity of speech or gesture or in a memorable phase of the
mind itself.... Imagine my glimpses of that clock as the gropings of a
spiritual eye which seeks to adjust its vision to an exact focus. The
moment the focus is reached the object is epiphanized. It is just in
this epiphany that I find the third, the supreme quality of beauty.
(Stephen Herr, p. 211).
Joyce identified the three notes of beauty of St. Thomas with the
three operations of the intellect:
Now for the third quality. For a long time I couldn't make out
what Aquinas meant. He uses a figurative word (a very unusual thing for
him) but I have solved it. Claritas is quiddims. After the analysis
which discovers the second quality the mind makes the only logically
possible synthesis and discovers the third quality. This is the moment
which I call epiphany. First we recognize that the object is one
integral thing, then we recognize that it is an organized composite
structure, a thing in fact; finally when the relation of the parts is
exquisite, when the parts are adjusted to the special point, we
recognize that it is that thing which it is. Its soul, its whatness
leaps to us from the vestment of its appearance. The soul of the
commonest object, the structure of which is so adjusted, seems to us
radiant. The object achieves its epiphany. (Stephen Hero, p. 213).
Obviously the business of the artist in this context is that of an
impersonal agent, humble before the laws of things, as well as before
his own artistic activity as revealer. He must strip himself of all but
his mere agency:
I have only pushed to its logical conclusion the definition Aquinas
has given of the beautiful.
Aquinas?
Pulchra sunt quae visa placent. He seems to regard the beautiful as
that which satisfies the esthetic appetite and nothing more--that
the mere apprehension of which pleases ...
The passage in St. Thomas formally distinguishing beauty and
goodness has wide but precise bearings for everything Joyce did as an
artist:
But they differ logically, for goodness properly relates to
appetite
(goodness being what all things desire), and therefore it has the
aspect of an end (the appetite being a kind of movement towards
a thing). On the other hand beauty relates to a cognitive power,
for those things are said to be beautiful which pleases when seen.
Hence beauty consists in due proportion, for the senses delight in
things duly proportioned, as in what is like them--because the
sense too is a sort of reason, as is every cognitive power. Now,
since knowledge is by assimilation, and likeness relates to form,
beauty properly belongs to the nature of a formal cause.
THAT the senses themselves are properly analogous, as are the other
cognitive powers, was not a fact lost on Joyce, who knew that the
creative process itself was a retracing of the stages of apprehension.
In this passage from St. Thomas can also be seen the reasons for
Joyce's preferring comic to tragic art. Any movement of appetite
within the labyrinth of cognition is a "minotaur" which must
be slain by the hero artist. Anything which interferes with cognition,
whether concupiscence, pride, imprecision, or vagueness is a minotaur
ready to devour beauty. So that Joyce not only was the first to reveal
the link between the stages of apprehension and the creative process, he
was the first to understand how the drama of cognition itself was the
key archetype of all human ritual myth and legend. And thus he was able
to incorporate at every point in his work the body of the past in
immediate relation to the slightest current of perception. He could well
afford to look patronizingly on the psychological gropings of Freud and
Jung and on the inferior poetic consciousness of a Yeats or Proust,
saying in "The Holy Office":
So distantly I turn to view
The shamblings of that motley crew,
Those souls that hate the strength that mine has
Steeled in the school of old Aquinas.
There was no shambling and no guesswork in anything Joyce did as an
artist. An absolute clairvoyance and precision attended his work from
the first page of The Portrait to the end of Finnegans Wake. And the
reason for this, as he insisted, was his grasp of the full creative
implications of the Thomistic analysis of cognition:
But, during the formulation of his artistic creed, had he not found
item after item upheld for him in advance by the greatest and most
orthodox doctor of the Church ... while the entire theory in accordance
with which his entire artistic life was shaped, arose most conveniently
for his purpose out of the mass of Catholic theology? (Stephen Hero, p.
205).
It is the Thomistic view that beauty relates to a cognitive rather
than a volitional power that led Joyce to prefer comedy to tragedy. The
long passage from his notebooks given by Herbert Gorman (James Joyce,
pp. 96-97) will become a locus classicus:
An improper art aims at exciting in the way of comedy the feeling
of desire, but the feeling which is proper to comic art is the
feeling
of joy ... the feeling which the possession of some good excites
in us.... For desire urges us from rest that we may possess
something
but joy holds us in rest as long as we possess something ...
All art which excites in us the feeling of joy is so far comic and
according as this feeling of joy is excited by whatever is
substantial
or accidental in human fortunes the art is to be judged more
or less excellent... From this it may be seen that tragedy is the
imperfect manner and comedy the perfect manner in art. All art,
again, is static for the feelings of terror and pity on one hand
and
of joy on the other hand are feelings which arrest us. It will be
seen
afterwards how this rest is necessary for the apprehension of the
beautiful... For beauty is a quality of something seen but terror
and pity and joy are states of mind.
It is hard to know where to begin to discuss any phase of Joyce
because he is so much of a piece. Anything of his includes all the rest.
Thus, for example, his statement of the problem of genres seems simple
and natural:
There are three conditions of art: the lyrical, the epical and the
dramatic. That art is lyrical whereby the artist sets forth the image in
immediate relation to himself; that art is epical whereby the artist
sets forth the image in mediate relation to himself and to others; that
art is dramatic whereby the artist sets forth the image in immediate
relation to others. (Gorman, pp. 97-98).
But the complex generic idea operative here is a shadow at once of
the three operations of the intellect and of the procession of Persons
in the Trinity. There is also a note of Joyce's dated at Paris
(March 27, 1903) which concerns Aristotle and imitation:
he tekhne mimeitai ten physin--this phrase is falsely rendered as
"Art is an imitation of Nature." Aristotle does not here define
art; he says only, "Art imitates Nature" and means that the
artistic process is like the natural process.... (Ibid., p. 98).
It is in Stephen Hero that there are the texts which explain what
Joyce understood by "natural process":
For Stephen art was neither a copy nor an imitation of nature: the
artistic process was a natural process.., a veritably sublime process of
one's own nature which had a right to examination and open
discussion. (Stephen Hero, p. 171).
That this process is that of ordinary apprehension is made plain on
page 212:
What we symbolize in black the Chinaman may symbolize in yellow:
each has his own tradition. Greek beauty laughs at Coptic
beauty and the American Indian derides them both. It is almost
impossible to reconcile all tradition whereas it is by no means
impossible to find the justification of every form of beauty that
has
ever been adored on earth by an examination of the mechanism of
esthetic apprehension whether it be dressed in red, white, yellow,
or black. We have no reason for thinking that the Chinaman has
a different system of digestion from that which we have though
our diets are quite dissimilar. The apprehensive faculty must be
scrutinized in action.
It is impossible to exaggerate the importance of this last phase
for an understanding of Joyce's art, because he never ceased to
evolve technique for scrutinizing sensations and impressions "at
the very instant of their apparition." And this meant for Joyce
neither impressionism nor expressionism but the revelation of the
profoundly analogical drama of existence as it is mirrored in the
cognitive powers in act:
They sat sometimes in the pit of a music-hall and one unfolded to
the other the tapestry of his poetical aims while the band bawled
to the comedian and the comedian bawled to the band. Cranly grew
used to having sensations and impressions recorded and analyzed
before him at the very instant of their apparition. (Ibid., p.
125).
Dubliners, for example, is a tapestry of such arrested apparitions
variously woven into the natural process of childhood, youth, maturity
and age. The Portrait is likewise static as the title insists, an
inclusive moment focussing the stage of artistic apprehension in a
vivisection of the young artist. It is noteworthy that Joyce excludes
from the esthetic discussion in The Portrait just those features of the
Thomistic analysis of cognition which were most important to him as a
mature artist--namely the fact of the creative process as the natural
process of apprehension arrested and retraced. The Stephen of The
Portrait (probably named after the Dedalian St6phane Mallarm6)
understands Aquinas via Mallarm6, whereas Joyce the artist, while led to
Aquinas by Mallarm6 and the symbolists, finally was able to complete the
work of the symbolists because he discovered how to perfect their
insights by means of Aquinas. Yet it needs also to be said that the
feebleness of grasp among Joyce critics is not so much their ignorance
of St. Thomas as their half-awareness of what Joyce found in Flaubert,
Rimbaud, and Mallarm6. Because Joyce and Eliot have surpassed these
writers, only, however, with their assistance, it is enforced on the
English critic to perfect their knowledge of them if only that the
French in turn may come to enjoy the achievement of Joyce and Eliot.
There is a passage in Stephen Hero which will serve to suggest the
kind of debt Joyce owed to Flaubert and his successors:
The modern spirit is vivisective. Vivisection is the most modern
process one can conceive. The ancient method investigated law
with the lantern of justice, morality with the lantern of
revelation,
art with the lantern of tradition. But all these lanterns have
magical
properties: they transform and disfigure. The modern method
examines its territory by the light of day ... It examines the
entire
community in action and reconstructs the spectacle of redemption.
If you were an esthetic philosopher you would take note of all
my vagaries because here you have the spectacle of the esthetic
instinct in action. The philosophic college should spare a
detective
for me. (p. 186).
The use of the words "vagaries" and "detective"
is here precise and significant. For on the one hand the figure of the
labyrinth is used everywhere by Joyce as the archetype of cognition and
esthetic apprehension, and on the other the modern detective since Poe
employs the technique of retracing in order to reconstruct an action
exactly as it occurred. Edgar Poe is rightly regarded in France as the
father of symbolism because he was the first to formulate the poetic
process as one of discovering by retracing. The precise poetic formula
for any emotion, he pointed out, was to be found by working backwards
from effect to the arrangement of words which would produce that effect.
It is also his esthete Dupin who first displays the same method in the
service of crime detection. The modern psychologist, historiographer and
archaeologist use this method in common with the physicist, the chemist,
and the "private eye." Professor Gilson's Unity of
Philosophical Experience has the distinction of being the first work of
philosophy in which this method of reconstruction is fully employed.
BUT a great deal of poetic experiment and development preceded the
discovery of the technique of reconstruction as discovery. And most of
all is owing to the practitioners of the picturesque school of landscape
that began with James Thomson in 1724. By the time of Scott, Byron, and
Chateaubriand the possibilities of discontinuous landscape as a means of
including and controlling a vast range of otherwise chaotic material was
available to the novelist as a means of examining "the entire
community in action." First Stendhal and then Flaubert and Dickens
went ahead on these lines. But Flaubert was the first to see in his
Sentimental Education that it means the abandonment of the continuity of
unilateral narrative in favor of the more profound effects to be
achieved by analogical juxtaposition of characters, scenes, and
situations without copula. So that the Cartesian cries against cubist
discontinuity have always been raised by those ignorant of analogy and
equivocity.
But Joyce, while alert to all that Flaubert had achieved for him
was not content with controlling just the larger areas of his
discontinuous landscapes. He wanted and got a simultaneous control of
the widest perspectives and the most intimate and evanescent moments of
apprehension. And this he was able to achieve by analysis of the
labyrinth of cognition which Aristotle and Aquinas had revealed to him,
It is thus, for example, that he is able to include in the first two
pages of The Portrait the entire experience of the race, the ground plan
of all his unwritten work, and the most individual features of
Stephen's expanding awareness. The opening words place the hero in
the traditional labyrinth and confront him with a minotaur adapted to
his infant years:
Once upon a time and a very good time it was there was a moocow
coming down along the road and this moocow that was down along
the road met a nicens little boy named baby tuckoo ...
Stephen Hero is so named because the artist in that work confronts
and slays scores of minotaurs. The book swarms with labyrinths of many
kinds and levels:
At the door he had to resign her to others and see her depart with
insignificant courtesies and as he came home alone he led his
mood through mazes of doubts and misgivings. (p. 159).
Following this passage there is another labyrinth which is both
exterior and interior. It presents one of the Daedalus family migrations
inside Dublin:
On the night before the day fixed for his legal eviction he moved
his camp by night. The little furniture which remained to them was
carried on a float and Stephen and his brother and his mother and
his father carried the ancestral portraits themselves as the
draymen
had drunk a good deal more than was good for them. It was a clear
night of the late summer freshened with cold as they walked in a
body beside the sea-wall.... The tide was lapping softly by the
wall, being at the full, and through the clear air Stephen heard
his
father's voice like a muffled flute singing a love-song. He made
his
mother stop to listen and they both leaned on the heavy
picture-frames
and listened:
Shall carry my heart to thee....
Traditionally there are two kinds of labyrinth, stone and sea.
Joyce uses both constantly. Here both are fused in the
"sea-wall"--the family treading the maze between two powers
(earth and sea) and carrying the household goods is arrested by the
song. The moment of arrest is an epiphany, a moment not in time's
covenant, and it is by the bringing of complex perceptions to a focus in
such moments that the minotaurs of the labyrinths are always overcome.
But the technical means of capturing these moments is by landscape,
as Wordsworth and others were aware. The Pre-Raphaelites and then
Swinburne, Pater, and the early Yeats had sought for the means to
prolong these moments. But the symbolists discovered that the moment was
not an end but a beginning. It was a point from which to begin a
retracing of the labyrinth of apprehension in order to find the
inevitable art form for that moment:
In the centre of her attitude towards him he thought he discerned a
point of defiant ill will and he thought he understood the cause of it.
He had swept the moment into his memory, the figure and the landscape
into his treasure-room, and conjuring with all three had brought forth
some pages of sorry verse. (Stephen Hero, p. 67).
Since the relation of labyrinth and landscape calls for separate
treatment it will serve for now to have pointed out that the conjunction
of landscape and labyrinth provided Joyce with that vivisection of the
stages of esthetic apprehension of which he was the only begetter. As
much, therefore, as the ancient Daedalus who made the labyrinth in
Crete, Joyce had the right to name his hero "Stephen Dedalus"
(the French form of the word). But it is not only the labyrinth of
cognition in which Joyce made himself at home, tracing and retracing
with delicate precision. The labyrinthine structure of the eye it is
that gives such salience in his work to the figure of the Cyclops. Most
of all he was at home in the labyrinth of the inner ear where he met
Persse O'Reilly, who is per se, son of the Real and father of Sir
Henry Harcourt-Reilly in The Cocktail Party. On the labyrinth of the
ear, organ of the Incarnation, Joyce built those metaphysical analogies
which enabled him to restore the orchestra of the seven liberal arts to
its plenary functions. He is never less than the artist of the Word.
Ulysses is reared on the labyrinth-landscape of the human body as the
body politic; and Finnegans Wake whispers throughout with the voice of
the river of human blood and immemorial racial consciousness. Joyce was
at home in all labyrinths because of his original conquest of the stages
of apprehension, of the mind in act.
HAVING suggested that Joyce took up the analysis of this matter at
the very promising stage at which Mallarm6 had left it at his death in
1898, I should like to point to what is, so far as I know, the first
stage of philosophic awareness concerning the retracing of apprehension
as the poetic process. It occurs in Thomas Brown's posthumously
published lectures on The Philosophy of the Human Mind. Brown was
professor of moral philosophy at Edinburgh until his death in 1820. And
it is in lecture XXXVII where he is considering the "secondary laws
of suggestion" as they affect genius that he states the difference
between the imagination of genius and the fancy of ordinary minds. The
mind of genius, he suggests, works in some sort of reverse direction to
ordinary minds:
In a poetic mind of a higher order, the conception of this very
subject
cannot exist for a moment, without awakening, by the different
tendency of the suggesting principle, groups of images which
had never before existed in similar combination ... new forms, of
external passion, would crowd upon his mind, by their analogy to
ideas and feelings previously existing; and this single change of
the direction of the suggesting principle would be sufficient to
produce
all those wonders, which the poet of imagination ascribes to
the influence of inspiring genii ... The inventions of poetic
genius,
then, are the suggestions of analogy: the prevailing suggestions of
common minds, are those of mere contiguity.
In these lectures Brown is a severe critic of Locke and Hartley and
the associationists, and seems to use "analogy" in a
traditional sense. To what extent he was aware of the speculations of
Coleridge, I cannot say. But Coleridge seems not to have had any inkling
of the retracing process of the poetic process. It is noteworthy that
his celebrated definition of the primary imagination merely states the
notion of Aristotle and Aquinas concerning the nous poietikos or the
agent intellect:
The primary imagination I hold to be the living power and prime
agent of all perception, and as a repetition in the finite mind of
the
eternal act of creation in the infinite I AM.
That this has not been noticed as the nous poietikos is only less
curious than the fact that Coleridge never seems to have commented on it
again. His definition of the poetic or secondary imagination has aroused
great interest and enthusiasm but is far from the precision of his
definition of the primary imagination:
The secondary Imagination I consider as an echo of the former,
co-existing with the conscious will, yet still as identical with
the
primary in the kind of its agency, and differing only in degree,
and
in the mode of its operation. It dissolves, diffuses, dissipates,
in
order to recreate: or where this process is rendered impossible,
yet
still at all events it struggles to idealize and unify.
Nothing could well be vaguer than this. It does not look very
impressive beside Brown's statement. And Brown's view is in
the line that leads through Burke to Poe, Baudelaire, Rimbaud, Mallarme,
and Joyce.
(1) Renascence 4.1 (1951): 3-11.