Conscious and unconscious placing of ritual (Li) and humanity (Ren).
Neville, Robert Cummings
This essay in contemporary cross-cultural Confucian philosophy
raises a question unlikely to arise from either Chinese Confucianism or
Western philosophy alone. The Confucian tradition from ancient times has
said that both ritual (Li) and humanity (Ren) need to be learned and
practiced so much that they become spontaneous responses. Western
philosophers would rightly understand this as a kind of learning that
requires conscious attention at first but that becomes habituated with
practice, like learning to ride a bicycle or being kind to elderly
strangers. In addition, however, Western culture understands unconscious
behavior to have a structure of its own that sometimes is at odds with
the structure of conscious life. Two principal lineages of the Western
point about the unconscious have currency now. One is the Freudian,
emphasizing unconscious psychological structures that cause us to do
things other than what we consciously intend or think we are doing. The
other is the Marxist, emphasizing real economic motivations based on
social location and class structure that are often different from our
conscious motivations structured by a self-serving ideology.
Both Western senses of the unconscious call for a Confucian
rectification of names. With regard to the psychological sense of the
unconscious, the Confucian project of embedding ritual and humanity in
the deepest center of the person requires a transformation of
unconscious structures. The techniques of ritual learning and becoming
humane are Confucian contributions to psychodynamic procedures for
transforming the unconscious, especially transforming it so that it does
not mislead or betray important conscious intentions. With regard to the
Marxist sociological sense of the unconscious, the Confucian project of
education in ritual and humanity requires a transformation of our
conscious structures and categories so that we admit honestly our true
motivations stemming from social location and come to terms with them.
The Confucian tradition also, of course, emphasizes the transformation
of social structures and personal social location, although that is a
different point from the one I am making here. The sagely project of
becoming sincere (Cheng) requires a contemporary Confucian to think
through the tasks of transforming the psychological unconscious, so as
to be reconciled with conscious intentions, and transforming conscious
beliefs about motives that are ideological in disguising real socially
structured motivations.
A final preliminary word should be said about why the Confucian
virtues of ritual propriety and humaneness are so important in the
contemporary world. As in Confucius' time, our world is sorely
lacking in rituals needed for diplomacy, for common courtesy among
persons and nations of different religions, and for harmonizing
societies whose citizens have genuinely different interests and social
locations. Part of the contemporary Confucian agenda is the
identification and criticism of the dysfunctional rituals that are in
place and the areas where rituals are simply lacking. A related part of
the agenda is to devise, institutionalize, and teach improved rituals
that address the situation. The contemporary promotion of the Confucian
virtue of humaneness is especially important now because Confucianism is
one of the two influential traditions to emphasize human responsibility
for social structures as well as personal action. The other tradition is
Western Enlightenment thought that has become attached to the
rationalism of the capitalist market economy, which is inhumane. Should
capitalists seek to limit their rational profit-making in order to
promote justice and humanity in some circumstance, they are
ideologically self-deceived because the market is against them. The real
market decisions are made by the millions of investors around the world,
large and small, who move financial investments by way of the internet
to the places that maximize profit. Should a company choose to lower its
profit in order to be humane, anonymous investments will be moved away
from its production to some other company. Capitalism is not about to be
dislodged soon as the world's economic system, and the alternative
systems seem so much worse. Perhaps a Confucian promotion of humaneness
can be integrated with the practice of market capitalism.
1. Ritual and Humanity
Ritual and humanity are extremely complicated practices within the
Confucian tradition or, better, the Confucian traditions. (1) Diverse as
Confucianism has become over the centuries, every branch of it needs to
give an interpretation of ritual and humanity as cardinal virtues. With
the different contributions of such a diverse heritage, the conceptions
of ritual and humanity are impossible to describe accurately in a brief
compass. As we apply them to new circumstances in global societies,
outside the East Asian social and family context in which they
originated, those virtues are made even richer. A brief word, however
abstract, can indicate their importance.
If we ask what Confucius actually did, the most straightforward
answer was that he ran a traveling school for teaching young men rituals
for all phases of life, quite a different model from Plato's and
Aristotle's seminar system. (2) What was the point of centering a
school around the teaching of ritual? Confucius thought the calamitous times in which he lived suffered from such a decay of the ritual
structure of life that harmonious and prosperous living was simply
impossible. Because the rituals of government and public life had
declined, only warlords could keep a peace that was dubious at best.
Because the rituals of economic exchange within a deeply divided class
society had broken down, the economy was unproductive, and distribution
was unjust. Because the rituals of family life had been neglected,
people failed to learn how to be humane. Good rituals make possible
civilized life. Without good rituals, no matter what the intent or how
good the will of people with different interests, civilized life is
impossible, according to Confucius. His points about the degeneracy of
ritual in government, community, and family life have close analogues
today.
The theoretical underpinnings of the ancient Confucian approach to
ritual were expressed by Xunzi. According to Xunzi, the natural
endowments given to human beings by Heaven and Earth are underdetermined
and require human conventions or rituals to give them civilized
determination. (3) For instance, our bodies are capable of a very wide
range of movements, yet we need to learn and teach our young certain
specific ways of walking, eating, making eye contact, and speaking. It
matters little whether we walk toes straight forward or angled, eat with
forks or chopsticks, greet people with bold eye contact or a deferential downward glance, or speak English or Chinese, as long as we in our
community share some one way that works. Higher-level rituals make
friendship possible and allow families, communities, and large empires
to accommodate different needs, to integrate divergent people into a
harmonious social dance, and to provide leisure, deference, and respect
so that the arts and practices of high culture can flourish.
Xunzi pointed out that two kinds of ritual learning pretty much
take care of themselves. The starry heavens move slowly around us, and
we cannot do anything about that except to respond with rituals of
admiring deference; many religious rituals today have to do with simple
awe and gratitude for the fundamental constitution of the universe. At
the other extreme, the peasant society of Xunzi's time had rituals
for coping with seasonal life that were learned with the mother's
milk, as it were, from direct encounter, like learning a language; just
about everybody today learns some language, though not all learn the
subtleties so as to express themselves well. In between these extremes
are the large problems of social life, such as droughts, floods, and
sudden attacks from marauding barbarians. For these, the individuals,
communities, and especially governments have to develop ritual
institutions of coping. Clearly, today we need to think about rituals
for such problems as ecological management, international diplomacy, and
global economic interactions, for we do not have successful ones.
Politics sometimes is about particular actions, but more often it is
about policies and laws that institutionalize rituals, say for the care
of the newborn or elderly, for dealing with breaches of contract, for
public care of transportation, safety, the economy, and the like.
Western culture since the Enlightenment has had a love affair with
grounding human values in nature, so that it has often viewed convention
or ritual as merely artificial. The Confucians have the better
understanding in their claim that the human completes Heaven and Earth
or, to put it in Western terms, that nature needs to be supplemented by
human convention or ritual in order to attain to the values of deep
civilization. In fact, ritual behavior, especially in family life, was
essential to the development of the current human biology that requires
a long dependent nurturing period.
Humaneness (Ren), the other Confucian virtue under scrutiny here,
seems initially to be more familiar to Western notions. Ren has often
been translated "love," with associations with the Christian
virtue. The Christian virtue of love is extraordinarily complicated, and
good parallels exist at many points. Zhu Xi's "Treatise on
Ren" gives it an ontological function similar to the Christian
sense that God's creating and loving are the same. (4) Ren has also
been translated as "human heartedness," a kind of feeling for
others and the whole cosmos that best manifests human greatness and
sensitivity. Roger Ames and David Hall translated it as
"authoritative conduct or person." (5) Ren also has
similarities to the Buddhist notion of compassion, particularly when the
Confucian project of "becoming one body with the universe" is
in mind.
What is distinctive about the Confucian virtue of humaneness comes
from the institution where it primarily is learned, the family. In one
sense a person learns to love by coming to understand how his or her
parents love him or her. But, in another sense that is closer to the
Confucian family practice--you begin to love mainly as a parent.
Everyone automatically, almost biologically, loves a baby. As the baby
becomes a child, you learn more complicated modes of loving through
teaching discipline and coping with that fast-moving and fast-talking
bundle of qi. Learning to love your adolescent child requires enormous
patience and far greater subtlety. You love your grown children through
educating them and setting them up in life, and then they leave you. You
have to love them when they do that, too. Your love is full only when
you bring up your children so that they are free and virtuous. From
their standpoint, the obligation of filial piety is not only to take
care of you when you get old, but to become so virtuous themselves that
you are released from your obligation to bring them up well: A virtuous
grown child sets his or her parents free. Of course a child cannot be
fully virtuous, fully humane (Ren) without raising children of his or
her own, so the parents' learning to be humane requires at least
two more generations. To be sure, not everyone has an extended family or
children, or even living parents, and the Confucian glorification of the
family is overly romantic on one hand and bordering on totalitarian on
the other. Many analogies for families exist in the social order,
however.
The upshot of taking the family as the prime analogue for learning
humaneness is that the Confucian virtue requires regarding other people
as embedded in a multi-generational stream and individuated through a
host of social relations that change with different stages of life.
Confucian humaneness does not regard people only according to the
situation, but construes that situation to be a focus within a field of
a much more complex interactive life for those people, and indeed to be
an incident in the life of those people that has a past and, hopefully,
a future. To put the point more strongly, Confucian humaneness treats as
merely abstract the here-and-now situation of others and rejects the
vision of others as merely in the situation. It insists that the other
persons in the situation be addressed in terms of their larger life
history and social network. To be humane to another person is to watch
for the clues to that person's whole identity, past and future,
filled with these relations and those. To be humane is to defer to that
person's larger identity than appears in the situation and to
respond appreciatively to the whole.
Capitalism, according to Adam Smith's "invisible
hand" theory, makes everyone better off than they were otherwise:
The poor get wages they otherwise would not have, the rich get richer,
and no one is forced to choose anything among real options that would
not be to his or her advantage as best perceived in the economic
situation. Confucian humaneness rejects this philosophy of the
"optimizing choice points." It says that the real values in
the choice points cannot be discerned without taking into account the
network of social and cultural relations, the place in the life span of
people, and the personal and communal participation in a
multi-generational group. Very often, what is best for the individual in
terms of contributions to the lives of others affected by his or her
actions and for growth in stages of life might not be the choice that
optimizes profit. Capitalism brutalizes the sensitivity to life's
choices that a Confucian with humane virtue would make. Confucian
humaneness can civilize capitalist definitions of optimizing profit.
Both ritual and humaneness can be described externally as
behaviors. They also need to be acknowledged as matters of the heart.
Mature ritual mastery and humaneness are spontaneous and fresh.
Therefore, we must look to their subjective embeddedness.
II. The Freudian Unconscious
Confucian ritual mastery and mature humaneness need to spring from
the heart. In the case of ritual mastery this involves first learning
the ritual and then practicing it so much that it becomes a matter of
unconscious and automatic habit. Rituals are learned in complex ways.
Sometimes they are learned unconsciously by imitation, as children [earn
to walk and speak without realizing that they are doing so. Often we
learn relatively isolated bits of ritual behavior, without realizing
until later (if ever) that those bits fit into a larger ritual dance.
The Marxist point about ideological self-deception puts a special twist
on this common failure to appreciate the extent of the ritual in which
we are involved. Sometimes we learn a ritual through a self-conscious
search for a pattern of behavior that lets us interact with others, as
when we first visit a foreign culture and look for ways to greet people,
find lodging and food, buy and sell, without offending them. Actions
such as eye contact, body posture, volume of voice, and proximity of
approach to people that mean one thing in our own ritual patterns might
mean very different things in theirs. When whole cultures interact, as
the Muslim and Western cultures are doing with such danger in our day,
new integrative rituals need to be devised that respect the differences
but enable both sides to dance together. Sometimes rituals are learned
in the very invention of them.
A ritual mastered to the point of habit fits in with the other
habits of a person's life, or of a group's life for that
matter. It needs to be compatible with the other habits already
ingrained or to alter those habits so as to make a place for itself. A
person's life is articulated by a very great many habits,
interpreting aspects of reality and responding in habituated ways. Some
of these are tightly connected, others less so. Because habits do engage
reality and receive feedback, they are often changing and reshaping
themselves. So, for a new habit to fit in with the old ones is not just
to find a place but also to find a balancing point so as to keep abreast of the changes in all the other habits. Often habits are contradictory
to one another and yet buffered by other habits. For instance, a person
can have the habit of being deferential and kind to elderly people and
also have the habit of being demeaning to people of another race, with a
contradiction in the treatment of elderly people of the other race.
Avoiding elderly people of the other race buffers the contradiction.
Where confrontation occurs, one habit must give way to the other.
Many situations in life are so filled with ambiguities that the
inconsistencies among our habitual responses are bearable. Our social
rituals are often inconsistent, speaking respectfully, for instance,
while standing in a disrespectful posture. Part of maturity of ritual
mastery is making the ritual behaviors consistent. The higher forms of
ritual provide behavioral patterns for being able to sustain many kinds
of inconsistency such as those rituals that allow us to interact
productively with people we hate, whose culture and social location are
different from ours, whose objective interests compete with ours, and
whom we misunderstand. Many of the paradigms of rituals come from court
rituals that allow social inter-course to proceed productively despite
various forms of deception, disagreement, hate, and intrigue:
"courtesy" (from "court" rituals) does not require
that you love your partners as your family.
The Freudian point about the unconscious, however, is that, whereas
you consciously believe that you love your family, your unconscious
feelings about them are filled with infantile aggressions, jealousies,
resentments, slights, and desires to dominate or submit, murder or
copulate. The unconscious has a structure of its own, a primary or
infantile process that reflects your drive to life reacting to the
persons, events, and situations that comprise your context. For most
people, the unconscious has an extremely selfish infantile orientation
to motives with regard to people, events, and situations. Its habits are
not acceptable at the conscious level and are expressed in overt action
and speech only "by mistake," in what we, half humorously,
call "Freudian slips." Freud's model was that the
conscious ego is captivated by an acceptable story it tells itself about
proper feelings and motivations, with proper images of other significant
people, events and situations. The alternative, unacceptable,
unconscious structure of feeling and motivations keeps up a relentless
pressure for expression, however, and sometimes breaks through.
A contemporary Confucian contribution is to see ritual as
integrating the conscious and unconscious, motivationally different,
sets of habits. At a superficial level we have many rituals that allow
the underside its day in the light, a time of carnival, a ritualized
drinking party, vicarious aggression toward those we unconsciously
resent and hate through war or sports, even more through sports
fanaticism. By jokes about "Freudian slips" we even ritually
make acceptable in polite social intercourse the unacceptable feelings
of the unconscious.
The Confucian point, however, is to modify the unacceptable
unconscious feelings themselves by having those feelings participate in
rituals of harmonization. The psychodynamic Freudian mechanism for
modifying the unacceptable unconscious feelings has been to get them
expressed and understood in a controlled environment, such as
psychoanalytic treatment. This mechanism has not been very successful,
and often the goal of treatment is just to learn to live with the
unacceptable feelings. The Confucian tradition, too, has emphasized
self-analysis and discernment. Nevertheless, it has also emphasized
practices of harmonious meditation, movement, and the development of
skills such as calligraphy for the purpose of tranquilizing the violent
contradictions of the unconscious heart. The ritualized practice of
harmonious feeling and movement can bring infantile rage into peaceful
repose. Of course, all this must be embedded in larger patterns of
harmonious social and personal life, but that, too, is part of the
Confucian project.
The next turn in this Confucian argument is to note that the
harmonization of the unconscious is itself a condition for making ritual
mastery spontaneous. To the degree that the unconscious forces in a
person run counter to the social rituals that engage others
harmoniously, the person cannot play those social rituals from the
heart. Of course, the social rituals can be played, but with a kind of
hollowness or false consciousness. This is not a bad thing. It is far
better to play productive social rituals hypocritically than not to play
them at all. Most of the time we do not realize that we are playing the
rituals with a false consciousness and just behave automatically. But,
even when we are thrown into a kind of self-loathing by the recognition
that we are pretending to respect those we despise, it is a good thing
to bear the self-loathing if the situation is made better by the playing
of the ritual.
Nevertheless, the cost of self-integration and personal harmony is
very high if we cannot participate in important social rituals without
self-loathing or a feeling of inner contradiction. For that reason it is
important to engage in the rituals that modify the infantile aggressive
unconscious so that it harmonizes with the playing of the larger rituals
in social life to which we are called. Although a person who has not
brought unconscious feelings to harmony with the whole of life can play
social rituals successfully, that play cannot be spontaneous as coming
from the heart. Often other people will detect this and distrust the
maturity of the person's ritual mastery. The Confucian project for
this situation is to bring the unconscious into harmony with the whole.
At this point a comment is appropriate about the Confucianism of
this argument. Since the Song and Ming Neo-Confucians, it has been
common to place Mencius above Xunzi, which means, among other things,
placing humaneness above ritual propriety. Tu Wei-ming, a contemporary
Confucian in Boston, represents the Mencian line when he argues that
humaneness is innate and that ritual is its externalized expression. (6)
The argument in this essay, by contrast, comes to humaneness through
ritual. Like Xunzi, the Freudian perspective sees the infantile stage of
human life and the unconscious infantile part of mature personality to
be selfish and in great need of harmonization. Mencius was right that
the heart can respond to things in their aesthetic and moral worth when
it sees them with clear discernment. He was right that its responses in
turn are harmonious and appropriate under the conditions of action that
is direct and at ease with itself and the world. However, those
conditions, clear discernment, and direct action constitute sincerity
(Cheng) and are not natively given. They are the great accomplishments
of the sage. Xunzi was right that the developing mastery of rituals is
part of the means by which sincerity is accomplished.
As to humaneness in the unconscious, the unconscious needs to be
brought into harmony if the heart is to be humane and express itself in
humane attitudes and behavior. The West has had two principal models of
love, which is part of Confucian humaneness. The Platonic model is that
the loveliness in the object arouses eros in the lover. The Freudian
model is that love, or sexual energy, is a force within the individual
looking for an object on which to cathect. The Confucian model of the
self combines both points in a broader picture. The heart innately is
the special, Heavenly endowed, human nature that is capable of grasping
the worth of things and responding appropriately. On the one hand are
the ten thousand things with values to be understood and respected. On
the other hand is the heart that can appreciate those values and respond
so as to create value and respect the values of the things affected. The
grave human difficulty is clearing the path between the heart and the
ten thousand things so that they can be seen for what they are worth and
so that the heart's responsive actions can be carried out without
deflection.
Many obstacles of personality, emotions, cognition, and even
physical development, usually summarized as "selfishness" by
Confucians, lie in that path. Mencians emphasize the fact that the heart
would automatically perceive and respond well if society had not taught
selfishness. Xunzians counter that the connection between the ten
thousand things and the heart itself needs to be created by appropriate
rituals or habitual meaning structures. If the learned rituals are bad,
selfishness is reinforced. But, if the person is relatively
unritualized, the heart will be like the baby's infantile
selfishness. The way to create a path between the world and the heart
necessarily includes teaching civilizing rituals. Learning to be humane
through the raising of children--and analogues to this, as mentioned
earlier--needs to be supplemented by learning the rituals that allow the
learner to relate with sincerity to those to be loved. Ritual, of
course, is not the whole of learning, but it is a significant part.
III. The Marxist Unconscious
The Marxist point about the unconscious does not focus on the
infantile feelings of primary process but, rather, on the real but
unacknowledged motivations for behavior that result from social
location. Social location is a function of social class, Marx said, and
social class is a function of economic structure. In Marx's view
the main classes were the owners of the means of production and those
who owned nothing but their work and, hence, subsisted on wages.
Marxists and other thinkers have made this view of social class far more
complex than Marx's original version, but the general point still
stands: much of our behavior is motivated unconsciously by the interests
of our social location, which includes not only economic class
differences but also cultural and age differences. Because the crude
selfishness of social-location interest is unacceptable and because we
have to get along with others in competing social locations, our
conscious thoughts about social relations are captivated by fictions
that disguise the real motivations.
The result is that many of us live within a story of morality,
social justice, and often religion that seems to give us moral projects
and a righteous direction but that, in fact, justifies or leaves
untouched real evils of social injustice. Marx was concerned that the
poor would be misled by religion to accept their economic condition and
that the rich would think they were being moral by doling out charities
to people whose poverty was, in fact, was caused by the system that
provided most advantages to the rich. The point can be generalized. Some
American Christians use the religious ideology of righteousness to
justify attacking so-called "evil" Muslim nations with
assertive governments when the real motivations are Western dominance
for the sake of oil. Some Muslim fundamentalists use the religious
ideology of righteousness and divine will for Muslim law to justify
attacking the Great Satans of the West when the real motivations are
control of the oil and their economy and a longing for lost empire. Most
of us live lives motivated in significant ways by unconscious desires
for advancement and dominance that are covered over by visions of the
roles we play in moral society. In countless ways, the usually
unconscious interests determined by our social location give us a false
consciousness.
Marx was right that religion often is the teacher and reinforcer of
the false consciousness of social location. He put too much emphasis on
the theological or ideological parts of religion, however: The effective
power of religion to produce false consciousness of social location lies
in ritual. Religious rituals usually rehearse a certain approved
stereotype of what social relations are, and people come to see those
approved relations instead of the actual relations of competition and
conflict among social locations. Moreover, many other areas of life
involve rituals expressive of ideal social relations. The economic,
artistic, entertainment, political, and neighborhood spheres of life are
just as ritualized as the religious, and many rehearse the idealized relations of false consciousness as effectively as the religious sphere.
In secular societies, those other spheres are far more important
ritualizers than religion.
The first Confucian contribution to the problem of ritualized
reinforcement of false consciousness of social location is through the
analysis of the rituals actually being played. Because of its
millennia-long emphasis on rituals and their meaning, Confucians should
be adept at discerning just what the rituals do. In line with the
Confucian theme of the "rectification of names," rituals need
to acknowledge not only differences in social location but also the
injustices embodied in systems that allow certain social locations to
oppress or exploit others. Marx's analysis, brilliant for its time,
is far too unsubtle to grasp the intricacies of exploitation and
oppression. Confucians in our time should bring their tradition to bear
upon improving his analysis.
Perhaps the most obvious "ritual" act in recent history
that exposes, expresses, and reharmonizes injustice between social
locations is the "Truth and Reconciliation Trials" in South
Africa. In these encounters, staged in public before judges, members of
the white South African apparatus for enforcing apartheid were forced to
listen to their black victims describe their torture and oppression. The
oppressors had to see what they had done from the standpoint of the
oppressed. The oppressed, who had been silenced and marginalized so as
to become non-people, were able to make their stories heard. The
ritualized character of the proceedings allowed the deep emotions to be
expressed in purging but peaceful ways. In societies as filled with
confusions and injustices as ours, as riddled with secret corruptions
and lies, many rituals are needed to bring to light those evils of bad
relations among social locations. Not only should they be brought to
light, but they should be ritually examined, confessed, and amended. We
need Confucian rituals of reconciliation, and those rituals need to be
woven through the other rituals of religious, economic, political,
artistic, entertainment, and neighborhood spheres of life. This is the
second Confucian contribution regarding rituals of overcoming false
consciousness.
Confucian humaneness demands that honesty about conflicts among
social locations be achieved. False consciousness is a great evil
because, among other things, it prevents people from seeing the humanity
in persons who occupy competing social locations. Or, rather, it
presents a false picture of their humanity, one that does not express
the aspects of oppressing and being oppressed that their social location
bears. There is a huge and wicked false consciousness in "loving
everyone" but not being able to see the details of the consequences
of social location in the particular people around oneself. As argued
above, humaneness requires knowing people not only in the roles they
play in specific situations but also in their life histories and
networks. Social location is part of life history and social networking.
In the contemporary world, in any place on the globe, to be humane
is, among other things, to be able to relate to people in terms of the
truth of their social location, especially as it is defined by
one's own location. On the surface, this means being able to stand
in the other person's perspective, to see how one looks from
someone else's vantage point. More deeply it means having the
scientific and historical knowledge to understand the causal connections
that constitute interrelated social locations in their economic,
political, ethnic, historical, religious, educational, artistic, and
other dimensions. Precisely because of Marx's point about the
self-deception involved in the ideologies arising from social locations,
the other person's own perspective might not be any more truthful
about the realities of the social locations than one's own.
Pressing forward to genuine humaneness often requires complicated and
difficult inquiry. Whereas learning to love one's own children
might be the root from which humaneness grows, learning the realities of
people very different from ourselves requires study--and often personal
change--so as to be able to accept what we learn about other people and
our relations to them.
IV. Summary
This essay has sketched how a contemporary Confucian approach to
ritual and humaneness might deal with the issues of the unconscious as
they have been introduced by Freud on the one hand and Marx on the
other. The operative word in that last sentence is "sketched."
No rituals have been devised, and humaneness has been articulated as
only an ideal. Nevertheless, the essay gives some direction to a
Confucianism that grapples with a global society of conflicting
cultures, classes, and interests.
(1) Most Western philosophers in the twentieth century, especially
those in the analytic tradition, became acquainted with Confucianism as
a technical philosophy through Herbert Fingarette's Confucius--The
Secular as Sacred (New York: Harper and Row, 1972).
(2) See Robert Eno's The Confucian Creation of Heaven:
Philosophy and the Defense of Ritual Mastery (Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press, 1990).
(3) Xunzi discussed ritual throughout his work Perhaps the best
discussions are in books 17 and 19 of his writings, translated by John
Knoblock as Xunzi: A Translation and Study of the Complete Works, voI.
3, Books 17-32 (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994). See
Edward Machle's Nature and Heaven in the Xunzi: A Study of the Tian Lun (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1993) for a close
reading of the chapter on nature. My own summary remarks about ritual in
this essay are greatly amplified in Robert Cummings Neville, Normative
Cultures (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1995), chap.
7.
(4) A good English translation is in Wing-tsit Chan's A
Sourcebook of Chinese Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963).
(5) See the interesting discussion of translation in the
"Glossary of Key Terms" in Roger T. Ames and David Hall,
Daodejing: "Making This Life Significant"--A Philosophical
Translation (New York: Ballantine Books, 2003). pp. 55-71.
(6) See Tu Wei-ming, Humanity and Self-Cultivation: Essays in
Confucian Thought, repr. with a new foreword (Boston, MA: Cheng and Tsui
Co., 1998; orig.-Berkeley, CA: Asian Humanities Press, 1979, [c] 1978),
chap. 2. See my discussion of his theory of ritual and humanity in the
foreword. The school of Boston Confucianism to which Tu and I belong has
two branches. The one north of the Charles River (at Harvard) emphasizes
the Mencian tradition, whereas the one south of the Charles (at Boston
University) emphasizes Xunzi's tradition on the point of ritual.
These differences are only matters of emphasis.