James Connelly and Stamatoula Panagakou, eds.: Anglo-American Idealism: Thinkers and Ideas.
Murphy, Richard
James Connelly and Stamatoula Panagakou, eds.
Anglo-American Idealism: Thinkers and Ideas.
Bern: Peter Lang 2010.
xii + 389 pages
$86.95 (paper ISBN 978-3-03910-895-4); $86.95 (ebook ISBN
978-30353-0019-2)
This edited volume provides an insightful and informative
perspective on all aspects of contemporary concern with idealist
philosophy. As Connelly and Panagakou remind us in the introduction,
because for idealist philosophers each part of philosophy was connected
to every other, to write about one part was implicitly to write about
the whole. Hence the book is impressively wide and comprehensive in its
scope.
The volume is a welcome addition to the expanding literature on
idealism and is particularly helpful in displaying its variety and
inter-connectedness, along with its impact and relevance to today. The
papers examine the works of Bradley, Green, Bosanquet, Royce, and Caird,
as well as later thinkers such as R.G. Collingwood and Michael
Oakeshott. Recent and contemporary idealists are also represented with
essays by Leslie Armour and Timothy Sprigge. As many recent discussions
on idealism seem to give a primary role to moral and political
philosophy, it is particularly pleasing to see that this volume also
gives prominent consideration to idealist metaphysics, epistemology,
philosophy of religion, and aesthetics.
James W. Allard's opening paper argues that idealists were
central to a transformation of logic. For Green and Bosanquet,
scientific knowledge has metaphysical presuppositions. Logic thus
becomes a study of the structural unity of judgements and inferences and
their interrelationships--which in turn are constitutive of reality and
knowledge. Allard argues that this logic was modified by Bradley and
that the modification was embodied in the philosophical revolution of
Moore and Russell which inaugurated analytical philosophy.
Elizabeth Trott's paper raises the question 'is the
Absolute obsolete?' Trott answers this question negatively, and
defends Leslie Armour's philosophy, according to which there are
not two separate domains of logic and experience--there is only the
on-going dialectical process of discourses creating the world. The world
is likened to a work of art, where no one description exhausts the
potential for meaningful encounters. The 'absolute' is also
the subject of Leslie Armour's essay, which argues that we cannot
grasp nature, except by transforming it into knowledge and so exhibiting
it as a work of mind. Armour's 'absolute' theory is
pluralistic rather than unitary: each distinct thing reveals a unity
with a different focus. For Armour, the 'Absolute' is the full
achievement of dialectical individuality. Entities are most fully
individuated when they most clearly reflect the whole from a particular
point of view. But this unfolding of the highest order determinable is
an unending process.
The idealism of Josiah Royce provides a solution to the
metaphysical problem of 'the one and the many', according to
Joseph P. McGinn's paper. McGinn seeks a 'middle way'
between the ontologies of monism and pluralism, and Royce's view of
selfhood shows how a unity can express itself as a real multiplicity.
For Royce, the Absolute constitutes an infinite self representative
system in which finite selves exhibit and embody the same
self-representative structure that is exhibited and embodied by the
system as a whole. Efraim Podoksik's essay, on the other hand,
argues that although idealism was a factor in Oakeshott's very
early thought, he departs from idealism from the publication of
Experience and its Modes onwards. Podoksik argues that Oakeshott became
influenced by Neo-Kantianism in the 1920s, which led him to abandon the
idealist notion of the spiritual unity of experience. Experience and Its
Modes was Oakeshott's reconciliation with modernity by perceiving
it as radical plurality.
Quite a different approach is taken by Jan Olof Bengtsson, whose
paper intriguingly contrasts idealism with the perspective of Eric
Voegelin. For Bengtsson, Hegel is a Gnostic thinker and Voegelin's
secularisation thesis has been 'massively confirmed' (110).
The process of immanentisation of the eschaton took the shape of modern
rationalism and romanticism, and this transformation of the Western
worldview can best be described as a pantheistic revolution. However,
Bengtsson argues that modern idealism, particularly Personal Idealism,
contains philosophical insights and resources which enable us to reach
beyond romantic-rationalistic modernity to an 'alternative
modernity' and a creative traditionalism (129).
The immanentist approach that Voegelin was so critical of is
evident in Bernard Bosanquet's views on religion and moral
philosophy, as explored in Stamatoula Panagakou's paper. Bosanquet,
as Panagakou explains, shifts focus from the transcendent and the
supernatural to the ethical nature of social existence, through which we
participate in the divine, with society providing the framework for
self-realisation. The idealist approach to religion is also central to
Timothy Sprigge's essay, which discusses the traditional
theological problem of evil. Sprigge sketches an idealist metaphysics,
according to which all the evils in the world are essential to the
existence and perfection of the Absolute, which is timeless and eternal.
Sprigge argues that everything which happens does so of necessity, and
that the good could not exist without the evil.
Karim Dharamsi discusses Collingwood's philosophy of mind,
comparing it to Donald Davidson's, and showing how
Collingwood's holistic and historical approach resolves and
transcends the 'cause-reason' debate. Dharamsi points out
that, for Collingwood, to discover the thought expressed in an event is
sufficient to understand it. For Collingwood, the logic of mind is that
it dictates and adjudicates 'objectivity' by its ability to
share thoughts and rethink them, and there is no truth that is
independent of history. Collingwood's philosophy of mind was also
central to his moral theory, which Timothy Lord refers to, in his paper,
as hierarchical moral pluralism. Collingwood rejected realist and
intuitionist theories because of their failure to account for the
complexity of morality. Lord outlines Collingwood's three kinds of
goodness: utility, right, and duty. Duty is linked with historical
consciousness, and in any given situation my duty is an individual
unique act necessitated by my particular circumstances. Lord, however,
finds this unsatisfactory, arguing that Collingwood is led to adopt a
'veiled intuitionism' (212).
Idealist social and political theory is the subject of the next two
papers. Derrick Darby defends New Liberalism and communitarianism from
the charge that they do not take individuals seriously enough.
Retrieving new liberalism from the shadows of the liberal tradition
reminds us that liberalism and perfectionist politics are not
necessarily opposed to one another. A social recognition conception of
rights, Darby asserts, bridges gaps between contemporary liberals and
communitarians. Recognition is also central to Bosanquet's social
theory, as discussed by Chris Colgan. For Colgan, the scientific
approach is problematic as it leads to difficulties in accounting for
the humanistic values that are essential to social work. Colgan then
argues for a new way of understanding 'facts' in social
theory, based on idealist philosophy, according to which facts are
incomplete, subject to debate, fixed through discussion and agreement,
but always open to later revision.
Collingwood's affinities with Hegel are examined in Gary
Browning's essay. For Browning, rethinking is central to
Collingwood's philosophy--both to the historian's activity in
understanding the past and to the philosopher's activity in
explaining the inter-connections of human conduct and thought. However,
in Browning's view, despite their similarities, Hegel provides a
conception of history that tends to underplay alternative
interpretations, contingency and complexity, while Collingwood
recognises alternative forms of civilisation and acknowledges the
contingency of liberal civilisation. Sverre Wide also defends a Hegelian
interpretation of Collingwood. Wide claims that the argument of
Collingwood's An Essay on Metaphysics is only valid for natural
science. While scientific concepts are closed, philosophical concepts
are open, in the sense that their meaning is not determined once and for
all but always submitted to an inner development. For Wide, following
Hegel, philosophical concepts are attributes or dimensions of the world,
and at least partially reflect the true nature of the world. From their
partial falseness truth arises through a dialogical process.
T.J. Rosser examines affinities between Collingwood and Heidegger
in the philosophy of art. Both Collingwood and Heidegger distinguish art
from craft. Both argue that art is the founding of truth, and see art as
having a role in redeeming humanity from the vulgar and dehumanising
aspects of modernity. However, for Heidegger only great artists can
bequeath the rest of us new possibilities of being, while Collingwood
believes that people can bring about their own redemption through
artistic activity--a more satisfactory approach in Rosser's view.
Collingwood's philosophy of art is also the subject of Marie-Luise
Raters' paper. Raters argues that in attempting to combine the
idealist claim for the truth of the beautiful with an understanding of
the work of art driven by the aesthetics of feeling, Collingwood
departed from idealism. The absolute truth claim of idealist aesthetics
is reduced to the claim which one can place on the subjective honesty of
an individual artist. This, however, is a reasonable limitation,
according to Raters.
The concluding paper by Philip MacEwen makes some insightful
observations about the nature of language and scholarship while
discussing Edward Caird's writings on Kant. MacEwen draws upon
Northrop Frye's distinction between descriptive, conceptual,
rhetorical, and kerygmatic language--each of which is used in
Caird's work. However, the early twentieth century saw a
descriptive turn in British philosophy and Caird's approach became
outdated. MacEwen argues that philosophy needs to have a place for
kerygma and rhetorical language, as a predominantly descriptive approach
makes philosophy the arena of a few technical experts from which most
people are excluded.
In conclusion, despite its decline in influence and fragmentation
in the early twentieth century, there has been a recent re-emergence and
re-evaluation of idealism. As this edited volume shows, it is still a
philosophical tradition that has much to offer to us today. The
impressive breadth of philosophical approaches here demonstrates the
multi-faceted nature of idealism and how it can cast light on many
different areas of contemporary philosophical debate, while also drawing
together these various strands into a cohesive view of philosophy
overall.
Richard Murphy
Durham University