首页    期刊浏览 2024年07月18日 星期四
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Nicholas Adams: Habermas and Theology.
  • 作者:Walter, Gregory A.
  • 期刊名称:Philosophy in Review
  • 印刷版ISSN:1206-5269
  • 出版年度:2007
  • 期号:August
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:University of Victoria

Nicholas Adams: Habermas and Theology.


Walter, Gregory A.


Nicholas Adams

Habermas and Theology.

New York: Cambridge University Press 2006.

Pp. 278.

US$75.00 (cloth ISBN-13: 978-0-521-86266-0); US$29.99 (paper ISBN-13: 978-0-521-68114-8).

Members of religious traditions need to argue fruitfully in public with each other and with those who are non-religious. Since Jurgen Habermas articulates one valuable position in support of public argumentation in his theory of communicative action, many Christian theologians have with some justice adopted Habermas' views. Observing this phenomenon, Habermas does not think that Christian theology would abandon its commitments and tasks if it were recast in the terms of his theory (189-200). Adams agrees with Habermas: he claims that adopting Habermas' theory amounts to the destruction of Christian theology as such since Habermas' views of reason, reflection, and communication displace any tradition-bound argumentation. Adams argues that post-metaphysical theologians can successfully engage in public activity without abandoning their traditions, meeting the challenge that Habermas provides by articulating the practice of 'scriptural reasoning.' Any scholar concerned with public discourse and the role of tradition in it should consider this book. Christian thinkers would especially benefit; Adams challenges those who follow Habermas to take instances of public argumentation seriously as he shows how the practice of scriptural reasoning could function as an alternative to Habermas' thheory of communicative action Theologians and philosophers alike should attend to this work, though Adams largely aims his essay at Christian theologians.

In order to focus attention on specific traditions and their practices, Adams explicates Habermas' readings of religion and theology. Philosophers ought to heed Adams' careful identification of what Habermas considers Christian theology to be. According to Adams, Habermas never intended to be a theologian (200). Much theological writing on Habermas exists, but this book sets itself apart by its attention to his claims about theology and by showing the limited range of modern theologians that Habermas has in mind. In the end, Habermas identifies religion with metaphysical thinking and tradition with self-authenticating authority rather than the authority achieved by consensus.

Adams focuses on a practice of public argumentation rather than a theory about its possibility, since he contends that one cannot theorize its grounds. He points out that there is a ground for public argumentation but, drawing on Schelling's critique of Hegel, he contends that it is impossible in principle to specify that ground (201). For him, one does not need to ask if thinking is possible in order to think. Despite the importance of Habermas' theory of argumentation in the public sphere, Adams holds that Habermas attempts to prove too much, and just so rules out the kinds of practices that members of traditions can use in order to argue successfully (224-6). If the ground of public argumentation could be given, Adams would have to face what it made possible and what it did not.

Arguing that Habermas proves too much does not mitigate his suspicion of tradition and narrative, so Adams still needs to address the difference between narrative and argument. The focus of Adams' concern in the third and seventh chapters is the positive use of traditions in public by their members. He takes up the position of the theologian John Milbank in order to consider narrative in the tenth chapter. Milbank champions the role of specific narratives and traditions, since he considers public argumentation in the manner of Habermas and others to be completely bankrupt. There are, according to Milbank, only traditions; since no apparent ground for public argumentation can be articulated, all traditions are in some way incommensurable. Habermas' position puts a premium on argumentation and sees narrative as something that can only be criticized. For him, narrative is the supreme form of tradition and self-guaranteed authority. Narrative belongs to 'world disclosure' and argument to 'problem-solving' according to Habermas. Adams concludes that the unavailability of a ground for argumentation does not mean that it does not exist or that we cannot articulate it. For Adams, that argumentation is possible should be enough, and therefore the distinction between 'world disclosure' and 'problem solving' can be blurred. Such a position only needs the observation that argumentation occurs and is sometimes successful.

None of Adams's criticism implies that Habermas should be ignored. 'It seems to me that [Habermas'] theological colleagues have rightly grasped that something like Habermas' theory of communicative action is vitally needed. There needs to be some way for members of traditions to be intelligible to their neighbors ...' (200). Adams proposes scriptural reasoning as this way. This is a practice undertaken by members of religious traditions to read each other's authoritative texts and interpret them with each other. No further conditions are required for scriptural reasoning than that the members be committed to reading together as members of their traditions. He devotes the last chapter to a description and defense of scriptural reasoning as an alternative to Habermas.

Adams' argument depends upon the extant but inaccessible ground of public reason in order to clear space for his attention to practices. But this also seems to allow him to address critical distance from within traditions. When Habermas articulates the distance that a person experiences upon reflection on tradition, experiencing the failure of a tradition, or some such other crisis, Adams articulates that this distance can be undertaken on theological grounds. Adams thinks a similar form of critical distance accompanies the Christian claim that no society properly embodies the Kingdom of God. No Christian can identify the two and therefore must maintain a critical distance from any given society, comparing it to the Kingdom of God (85-90). Critical distance might also be expressed by theological consideration of the otherness of God; this otherness could call all human claims into question. Adams argues that the self-criticism available to Christian theology can suffice for the sort of criticism that Habermas desires. This is a very interesting claim but it deserves more explication and warrant.

Adams has a fine account of Habermas and a firm grasp of the issues facing contemporary theology. His attention to theology, narrative, and argumentation as well as practices, combines many of the strengths of theological traditions. Scriptural reasoning seems to function as a way to engage across religious traditions. Can this commendable practice be adapted to other circumstances or fields? Can jurists read their authoritative texts together? Is scriptural reasoning only possible for monotheistic traditions? As a specific, historically situated practice, it is no failing to say no to the first and yes to the last questions. For Adams' proposal to have the fruit he wishes it to bear, other practices that engage non-religious traditions need to be imagined. Nevertheless, Adams has written a book worthy of attention and response.

Gregory A. Walter

St. Olaf College
联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有