Michael L. Gross: Bioethics and Armed Conflict: Moral Dilemmas of Medicine and War.
Stewart, Robert Scott
Michael L. Gross
Bioethics and Armed Conflict: Moral Dilemmas of Medicine and War.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press 2006.
Pp. 400.
US$65.00 (cloth ISBN-13: 978-0-262-07269-4); US$26.00 (paper
ISBN-13: 978-0-262-57226-2).
The issue of bioethics during armed conflict has received
relatively little attention in the philosophical literature. This is odd
in one sense since the acute need to develop an ethics of medical
research on humans (and, derivatively, of the need to develop bioethics
in general) was largely the result of the realization of the atrocities
the Nazis committed during World War II in the name of medical research.
In another sense, however, it is understandable that little attention
has been paid to the application of bioethics to armed conflict because
many assume, along with Pellegrino and Thomasma, that 'the
physician has ethical obligations that transcend self-interest,
exigency, and even social, political and ethical forces' (1). As a
result, many think that the moral principles that we typically employ in
analyzing medical ethics--e.g., autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence,
justice, and so on--must apply more or less in the same way no matter
what the circumstances. This is in fact the official position of the
World Medical Association, which claims that 'medical ethics is the
same in times of armed conflict as it is in peace time' (1).
According to Gross, this position is fundamentally wrong: while it
is an overstatement to say he believes that war changes everything, he
does believe that war changes a great deal. The reason for this is
embedded within the notion of 'military necessity'. Although
Gross never provides a succinct and proper definition of it, he thinks
of military necessity as part of the 'ends and means of war
necessary to preserve the welfare of the state, its army, and its
citizens' (59). Hence, while not everything is legitimated under
the rubric of military necessity, nations do have the right, under just
war theory, to protect themselves and their legitimate interests. In
this sense, military necessity 'reflects a concern for the
collective welfare of the political community that reaches beyond
individual well-being' (59). As such, it will 'sometimes
override the normative force of deontological moral principles central
to bioethics' (59).
In light of this, consider, e.g., the right to life, and the
concomitant obligation of the state to protect the lives of its
citizens. In war, states send young men (and increasingly, young women)
into situations where it is a given that many will die. This will, of
course, have dramatic consequences for bioethics in times of war.
'Ordinarily,' Gross says, 'individuals enjoy the right to
receive medical care as an extension of their right to life' (43).
But if their right to life is attenuated, then so too is their right to
medical care. This, in turn, raises a whole host of other issues. Do we
owe all our citizens, combatants and non-combatants alike, the same
level of medical care? Or ought combatants receive priority? If they
should, is this the result of a sense of obligation for the risk
soldiers have placed themselves in for our protection? Or do we do it
rather out of the utilitarian consideration that we get them back to the
front to fight again? If we do it for the latter reason, how will this
affect medical triage? Ought we to treat those soldiers first whom we
can return to the front, or should we treat the more seriously wounded
first, even though they will in all likelihood never be fit for combat
again? What about medical treatment for our enemies, whether they be
civilians, combatants, or terrorists? Do we owe them anything? Do we owe
them the same treatment as our own civilians and combatants? Given all
these difficult questions, we can see why Gross subtitled his book,
'the moral dilemmas of medicine and war' and why he also
maintains that '[m]ilitary necessity, therefore, joins the pantheon
of other principles that guide medicine and war as first among equals,
and forces the peculiar and noncaregiving dilemmas that characterize
bioethics during armed conflict' (63).
In addition to these two dilemmas--the just distribution of medical
resources in war (Chapter 3) and wartime triage (Chapter 5)--Gross deals
with a number of others. In Chapter 4 he considers issues of patient
autonomy for soldiers along with the derivative rights of informed
consent, confidentiality and the right to die. He argues that
considerations of utility and respect for individual autonomy flip-flop
from peace to war. That is, in war respect for autonomy diminishes as
'patient rights pass from the hands of soldier patients to the
hands of those charged with the collective welfare, with the expectation
that costs to some individuals are offset by benefits to others'
(136). In Chapter 6 he questions whether medical personnel can and/or
ought to be considered as neutral in armed conflicts. He thinks, despite
the belief of many that medical personnel are of course neutral, that
such personnel actually face difficult dilemmas as they are pulled
toward remaining neutral and toward 'civic responsibility'
(210). That is, health care workers are citizens with obligations to
their state as well as members of a particular profession with its own
set of moral principles. The same sort of tension exists for health care
workers when they consider whether torture or non-treatment (Chapter 7)
or chemical and biological warfare (Chapter 8) are ever justified.
Finally, in Chapter 9, Gross considers whether medicine is obligated to
work actively towards peace.
Many readers will disagree with some or perhaps even all of
Gross' conclusions, sometimes passionately so. I certainly would
take issue with some of his claims regarding torture and
chemical/biological warfare, and indeed also with his claim about the
novelty of the threat posed by terrorism. Critics of his work, however,
will have their work cut out for them because Gross displays
considerable virtuosity with his subject matter as he navigates
bioethics, ethical theory, the history of warfare, and contemporary
geopolitics and presents incisive, penetrating and forceful arguments.
As a result, I believe that this book is destined to become a classic in
its field.
Robert Scott Stewart
Cape Breton University