Normative thoughts, normative feelings, normative actions: a Protestant, relational psychoanalytic reply to E. Christian Brugger and the faculty of IPS.
Hoffman, Lowell W. ; Strawn, Brad D.
The present article is a response to E. Christian Brugger's
2008 article, Anthropological Foundations of Clinical Psychology,
published in the Journal of Psychology & Theology (Volume 36, Number
1). In the article, Brugger argued that all psychological theories
contain implicit anthropologies complete with values and ethics. Brugger
called on theoreticians to overtly explicate their philosophical and
theological model. He then presented such a system from his own Catholic
tradition and invited authors from other Christian traditions to
constructively interact. The authors of this article dialogue with
Brugger's model using Reformed and Wesleyan theology and Relational
Psychoanalysis.
**********
In the Spring 2008 issue of the Journal of Psychology and Theology
(Volume 36, Number 1), E. Christian Brugger and the faculty of the
Institute for the Psychological Sciences published an article entitled
Anthropological Foundations for Clinical Psychology: A Proposal. In
their article, they argued that embedded within all psychologies and
theories of psychotherapy arc implicit anthropological assumptions which
contain value systems and judgments that are ethical in nature. Brugger
further remarks that the values/judgments in these theories are often
unacknowledged. While theories explicate what is considered
pathological, the antecedent theories of normative behavior, or in
ethical language, "the good," are rarely explicitly stated.
Brugger is not the first to espouse this type of critique. Don
Browning (1987) in his seminal book, "Religious Thought and the
Modern Psychologies", (now in its second edition, Browning and
Cooper (2004) persuasively argues a similar position, suggesting that
each theory of psychotherapy contains latent "metaphors of
ultimacy" (1987, p. 20). Browning examined several of the most
popular schools of psychotherapy and demonstrated that each theory
assumes unacknowledged, forgotten, and/or dissociated metaphors of
ultimacy which actually make each theory a religio-ethical system
replete with an implicit anthropology, values, morals, and derivatively
a system of ethics. More recently, Richardson, Fowers, and Guignon
(1999) as well as Cushman (1995) have also deconstructed modern
psychology and psychotherapies, exposing their unacknowledged ethics and
biases.
In the wake of this deconstruction, Brugger challenges contemporary
theorists to explicitly acknowledge the theological and philosophical
anthropologies couched in his theory construction. Brugger believes
there are three reasons why it would be helpful for theoreticians and
clinicians to develop explicit accounts of the human person (i.e., an
anthropology). "First, it is a way of evaluating the coherence of
the ideas" (p. 5). "Second, it can assist the project of
theory development" (p. 5). And third, "... formulating and
publishing an account of human nature sets forth an example and
invitation, even as a challenge, to other scholars forthrightly to
follow suit" (p. 6). The present authors agree with Brugger's
assertion that ethical psychological theory construction should be
explicit with respect to anthropologies that animate those theories.
We believe that Brugger's challenge to theoreticians and
clinicians also contains implications that transcend academic and
clinical settings. The Christian sub-cultures, and culture at large, are
adrift on seas of pragmatism that engulf the human spirit in
solution-seeking activities based on inadequate theological and
anthropological assumptions. One need only read the current headlines to
encounter the latest demise of a Christian minister/leader informed by
such inadequate assumptions, with disappointing and even calamitous
results. A return to mindful moorings of our narratives of ultimacy can
anchor us and thereby deter perilous drifting.
Brugger's call for full disclosure by theoreticians is
consistent with contemporary philosophical hermeneutics, which
recognizes the inevitability of embedded beliefs within every tradition.
We are grateful for this article by Brugger, and we accept his challenge
to offer constructive alternatives and additions to his project in the
form of a response paper, which highlights areas of difference in a
fashion that is not intended to be exhaustive. While Brugger is writing
from within the Catholic tradition, the present authors are a
Presbyterian and a Wesleyan (strange bedfellows indeed!). Nevertheless,
being in the larger "Protestant" tradition, we conceptualize
issues more alike than not. We are also both trained and practice from a
psychoanalytic perspective, particularly the relational psychoanalytic
tradition. Both our religious and clinical traditions will shape the
anthropology that we articulate.
SUMMARY AND RESPONSE
Brugger takes up his own challenge in the second half of his
article, by explicating a theory of the human person. He suggests three
theological anthropological premises (each with multiple corollaries),
which then lead to 5 philosophical anthropological premises (also with
multiple corollaries). The three theological premises are: a) human
persons are created, b) human persons are fallen, and c) human persons
are redeemed. The five philosophical premises are: a) humans are
substantially one, b) humans are bodily, c) humans are interpersonally
relational, d) humans are rational, and e) humans are volitional and
free. While we will principally embrace his eight foundational
anthropological premises, we will focus in this article on our points of
difference.
Theological Anthropology
Premise One. We agree with the first theological anthropological
premise that "the human person is created ... 'in the
image' and after the likeness' of God," (p. 12) and we
particularly appreciate the emphasis in corollary three (p. 12) upon our
Creator God as a "communion of Persons" (cf. Zizoulas, (1985)
and LaCugna, (1992)) for we believe that a social God made us first and
foremost as relational beings to love and be loved. "The doctrine
of the Trinity is not ultimately [or simply] a teaching about
'God' but a teaching about God's life with us and our
life with each other. It is the life of communion and indwelling, God in
us, we in God, all of us in each other" (La Cugna, 1992, p. 223
emphasis in original). We do however question the author's linking
of human communion with God and each other to the assertion that"
... humans are created as per sons to know all truth, especially about
God. ..." (p. 12). We find Brugger's linking of this gnosis
with koinonia to be a gloss that does injustice to the primacy of human
relationality and are reminded of the Apostle Paul's
admonition,"... Knowledge puffs up, but love builds up. Anyone who
claims to know something does not yet have the necessary knowledge, but
anyone who loves God is known by Him" (I Cor. 8: 1, 2 NRSV).
We concur with the second corollary of this first premise that the
human person is "constituted of a material body and spiritual
soul" (Brugger, 2008, p. 12) in the limited sense that Shults
(2003) articulates: "... a sense of duality, i.e., a distinction
between biological and mental events, but not [a] dualism, in the sense
of two separate substances." (2003, p. 180). We will say more about
this below.
Premises two and three. Following the second theological premise
that "the human person is fallen," with which we are in
consensus, we come to our first substantive difference with the third
theological premise that "the human person is redeemed" ( p.
12). While we agree with the author and Scripture that "Christ
redeemed us from the curse" (Gal. 3:13); we understand that the
purpose of this redemption was for Christ Jesus to come to us so that
"we might receive the promise of the Spirit." (Gal, 3:14). The
emphasis of this promise (cf. Joel 2:28) is not anthro-pocentric, i.e.
that humans are redeemed; rather the promise is Christocentric, i.e.
"as all die in Adam, so all will be made alive in Christ" (1
Cor. 15:22). Humans will be conformed to (share in) the likeness of the
One who is "the firstborn" of us all (Rom. 8:29) and "the
firstborn of all" (Col. 1:15, 18). Christ is not a reconstituted
first Adam, but "the last Adam, ... a life-giving spirit" (1
Cor. 15:45). We find this distinction crucial so that our self-awareness
is not egocentric and self-referential, i.e., "I am redeemed;"
instead our awareness transcends ourselves and is other-focused, i.e. I
am in Christ (Rom. 8:1), Christ is in me (Col 1:27) and being in Christ,
I am a "new creation" (2 Cor. 5:17).
For Karl Barth, this distinction is foundational to his life work:
The last word I have to say ... is not a concept ... but a name:
Jesus Christ. ... He is the ultimate One beyond world and church and
even theology. We cannot lay hold of Him. But we have to do with Him.
And my own concern in my long life has been increasingly to emphasize
his Name and to say, 'In Him.' In Him is the spur to work,
warfare and fellowship. In Him is all that I have attempted in my life
in weakness and folly. It is there in Him. (Erler & Marquard, 1986,
p. 113)
Our insistence on a Christocentric understanding of the human
person derives from our belief that in the coming of Christ, we have
apprehended not only a renewed and more comprehensive relationship to
our Trinitarian God, but also a more comprehensive relationship with
ourselves. In Christ's life--His relationships, His recorded
normative thoughts, normative feelings and normative actions--we come to
a fuller experience of what it is to be wholly human, wholly ourselves.
In this Christocentric realization, we come to a more complete
experience of who we are as made in the image of God. Jurgen Moltmann
(1985) understands that our "true likeness to God is to be found,
not at the beginning of God's history with mankind, but at its
end" (1985. p.225). He further distinguishes this truer likeness to
God as a developing process with an cschatological fulfillment in human
beings becoming the glory of God (1985, p.228, see also, Grenz, 2001).
The project for a normative theory of the human person for us cannot
proceed, or even begin, without our recognition of the God-man Jesus of
Nazareth, who in the course of human history is unique in His solitary
achievement of a wholly normative human existence in space and time. We
would therefore amend the third premise to state, "the human person
is re-created," and parse the Christocentricity of our developing
identity in Jesus Christ.
We will also note, but not discuss, that corollary three of the
third theological premise which states "persons can become
holy" (p. 12), is not uniformly agreed upon across the communions
of the Christian faith. While some Protestants, notably those of a
Wesleyan theology, as influenced by the Eastern centers of Orthodox
Christianity, will find an affinity with this understanding of persons
becoming holy (e.g., deification), other Protestants in the Reformation
traditions of Luther and Calvin would articulate a bifurcated
understanding of persons being simultaneously holy and just in Christ
and continuing in evil apart from Christ.
Philosophical Anthropology
Premise four. Turning to the five philosophical premises concerning
a normative anthropology, we are in significant agreement with the
fourth premise and its correlates that "the human person is
substantially one," (p. 12) although we would prefer the
utilization of "soulishness" instead of "soul" with
reference to the "animating principle of the living human
body." By arguing that "The Soul is the animating principle of
the living human body; therefore a living human body is presumptive
evidence of the presence of the soul ..." (p. 12), Brugger employs
a tautological argument. We prefer the signifier "soulishness"
to soul "to understand that soul needs to be referred to not as a
substance, but in terms of relationality" (Bal-swick, King, &
Reimer, 2005, p. 24). We find affinity with Ray Anderson's (1998)
sensibility of the soul "as that which represents the whole person
as a physical, personal and spiritual being, especially the inner core
of an individual's life as created and upheld by God" (1998,
p. 193). Further we find affinity with the work of Brown, Murphy, &
Malony (1998) who understand "soulishness" as an emergent
property of human relatedness. While we, like Brugger, wish to avoid a
reductive materialist position, we believe that one can stay true to the
biblical witness (Green, 1998, 2004a, 2004b), and to emerging
neuroscience findings, without positing an "immaterial,
incorruptible and immortal soul" (Brugger, p. 12). For us, Brugger
adds nothing of substance to his theological or philosophical
anthropology by positing such a soul. The chasm which separates human
beings from all other creatures, is not our possession of an immaterial
and immortal soul, but our unparalleled capacity for relationship with
God and each other. Our uniqueness resides in God's choice to
relate to us as sons and daughters. Our soulishness is our conception of
how God creates us, animates us, lives in us, recreates us and communes
with us. We understand that God is intimate with us in a manner not
experienced by His other creations. What is essential to us here is to
emphasize our function as relational beings over speculative attempts to
conceptualize our form, which gives voice to our relational purposes and
telos.
Premise five. The fifth philosophical premise that "the human
person is bodily," with the fourth corollary that emotions are a
set of bodily "responses and reactions," is our second
substantive difference with the authors. The author's placement of
emotions as bodily responses and reactions could be understood both as a
Thomist conception that denigrates the emotions as base or animalistic
and an Augustinian bias that affect is the seat of utterly perverse
bodily impulses. Both the Thomist and Augustinian characterizations of
emotion privilege intellect and will as that which is most normatively
human. Correspondingly, Brugger posits rational and volitional faculties
as the seventh and eighth anthropological premises, while subsuming
emotions as an indiscrete bodily subcategory of premise five. Curiously,
he holds forth a contemporary understanding of the "human person is
interpersonally relational" with premise six, while retaining a
medieval taxonomy that privileges reason and will over affect in premise
five.
We turn to the work of John Macmurray (1992) to consider a
philosophical alternative to the author's minimalist conception of
human emotions. Macmurray's starting place is the question "Is
there reason in the emotional life?" He defines reason as "the
capacity to behave consciously in terms of the nature of what is not
ourselves;" also "reason is the capacity to behave in terms of
the nature of the object, ... to behave objectively. Reason is thus our
capacity for objectivity" (1992, p.7). For Macmurray, the
"truth or falsity" of thoughts and feelings does not lie in
them, but in the "relation between them and the things to which
they refer" (1992, p. 10). We can feel rationally or irrationally
and we can think rationally or irrationally.
We suggest, in agreement with Macmurray, that both thoughts and
feelings are best understood as aspects of rationality. We would
understand the placement of emotions as conjoined with the author's
seventh philosophical premise that "the human person is
rational," both intellectually and affectively. That
"rational" expressions of affect are normative is best
attested in the emotions of our Lord. Benjamin Warfield (1912) has
provided an exegetically precise and descriptively thorough study of our
Lord's emotions. He concludes:
... All that is human manifested itself in Him in perfect balance
and proportion. The senses of emotions attributed to our Lord in the
Evangelical narrative ... illustrate ... this balanced comprehensiveness
of His individuality. Various as they are, they do not inhibit one
another; compassion and indignation rise together in His Soul; joy and
sorrow meet in his heart and kiss each other, ... not mere joy but
exaltation, not mere irritated annoyance, but raging indignation, not
mere surface-distress, but an exceeding sorrow even unto death. ...
(1912, pp. 137,138) (1)
Additionally, psychoanalytic research has demonstrated that affect
and thought/cognition/intellect have a binary relationship to each
other. Ruth Stein's (1999) meta-analytic study of emotions leads
her to state the following proposition:
Affects cannot be separated from cognitions (Lichtenberg, 1987;
Mandler, 1975;Novey, 1959, 1961; Stern, 1985). Affects supply valuable
and vital knowledge of personal significance to the person who
experiences them (Lazarus, 1982, 1984a, 1984b; Sandler 1985, Taylor
1985; and writers on counter-transference, e.g. Heimann 1950; Little,
1951; Racker 1958; Searles, 1955, 1979; Winnicott, 1958, 1977). Thus
affects are themselves a kind of cognition or knowledge; in a way, they
are interpretations of the environment and of the person to himself [or
herself]. A related point is the mutual relationship of affect and
thought: thought influences changes or reinforces feeling, and feelings
in turn generate thoughts that fit with them; the relationship is
reciprocal. (1999, p. 173)
Research in cognitive neuroscience further supports these analytic
findings. Damasio (1994) has demonstrated through a series of
experiments with individuals that have suffered damage to the orbital
frontal cortex of the brain, that even though these individuals may have
intact intelligence, memory, and even normal moral and ethical reasoning
abilities, they suffer deficits in making responsible everyday
decisions. A disconnect appears to take place between what the
individuals know they should do and their ability to rationally stop
themselves from making wrong choices. This caused Damasio to posit a
theory of Somatic Markers. "According to this theory, experience
with the contingencies of life cause individuals to develop anticipatory
evaluative (negative or positive) autonomic responses (called by Damasio
"somatic markers') that become coupled to knowledge of the
world" (Strawn & Brown, 2004). Often these markers are not
entirely available to conscious awareness but may be made known via
vague feelings toward a situation or persons. And although they may be
unconscious, they nevertheless play an important role in
decision-making. In other words, these unconscious, or even preconscious
emotions/feelings, have their own rationality (albeit distorted at
times) that assists conscious reason. In fact, we might argue that
rational thought cannot occur without the availability of these emotions
(as seen in the brain damaged patients).
Premise six. Brugger's philosophical premise six states:
"the human person is interpersonally relational" (p. 13). In
that we find primary affinity in our psychological theory and practice
with relational psychoanalysis, we understand this premise as the
keystone of the five philosophical anthropological premises.
Brugger's sixth corollary of premise six that humans are
"communally situated" (p. 13) is particularly important to us
in that "it is only in relation to others that we exist as persons.
... We live and move and have our being not in ourselves but in one
another" (Macmurray, 1991, p. 211). We concur with Paul Vitz (2006)
who asserts that "the only serious understanding of early
interpersonal relationships of an interpersonal kind-at least with
regard to later mental and interpersonal problems-is that found in the
psychoanalytic tradition known as object relations theory" (2006,
p. 120). (2) We further concur with Vitz concerning life span
development, that "As human beings grow and change and become
inter-personally and intellectually more mature, they recognize a
process and a trajectory of transcendence in their own life" (2006,
p. 127, emphasis in original). We value Jessica Benjamin's (1990)
theory of inter-subjectivity as contributing to an understanding of
transcendence. Benjamin, building upon Hegel, Winnicott (1989), and
Mitchell (1988), asserts that subjectivity--that is, alterity in the
sense of "transcendence,"--is acquired through, and only
through, relationship with another subject. Hence, a mother is
primitively perceived by her infant as undifferentiated from itself
until the mother's individual needs conflict with those of her
infant to such an extent that the infant attacks the mother. The
mother's "survival" of the infant's assaults
disabuses the infant of its sense of omnipotence (immanence as
demonstrated by control of mother) and promotes the infant's
recognition both of the mother's otherness (i.e., transcendence)
and of the limits of the infant's sense of self. This recognition
becomes the basis of the infant's respect for, and love of, the
"other" [or mother]. Throughout the process of healthy
lifespan maturation, people re-experience the dissonance of the
other's subjectivity and are enriched through the difference of the
"other." In relational theory, this maturational trajectory of
transcendence is cumulative though discontinuous and is often lost and
repeatedly rediscovered. (3)
Premises seven and eight. Having given considerable attention to
emotions as rational, we will in the interest of space, not comment
further on philosophical premise seven that "the human person is
rational" (p. 13) and focus our attention on philosophical premise
eight--that "the human person is volitional and free" (p. 13).
The literature on "free will" is so extensive and therefore so
ambiguous, that we would suggest that the authors replace the signifier
"free" in this premise with another word that they utilize as
synonymous, i.e. agentic.
We value again the philosophy of Macmurray (1992) and his
understanding of freedom and choice:
The controversy about free will is insoluble ... because the
problem itself is wrongly conceived. [We assume that the person] must
necessarily behave in terms of his own nature, like anything else. [i.e.
organic and material objects]. This assumption is at fault. Reason is
the capacity to behave not in terms of our own nature, but in terms of
our knowledge of the nature of the world outside. (1992. pp.7-8 )
As psychoanalysts, we understand that the freedom to choose is
mediated by the extent to which a person is compromised by unconscious
processes, including irrational emotions and distorted perceptions of
reality and personal history, which actualize irrational, immoral,
destructive and /or unloving choices. Macmurray continues:
The main difficulty that faces us in the development of a
scientific knowledge of the world lies ... in our own emotional life. It
is our desire to retain beliefs to which we are emotionally attached ...
In practice, the desire for truth is the desire to be disillusioned. ...
The development of reason in us means overcoming all of this ... to
acquire greater and greater capacity to act objectively and not in terms
of our subjective constitution. (1992. pp. 7-9)
In relational psychoanalytic theory, "acting not in terms of
our subjective [distorting] constitution" (see above) is living in
the intersubjective tension of being oneself while recognizing and
thereby respecting the separateness of the "other." According
to Benjamin (1990), mutual recognition (recognition of both self and
other as subjects) is a pre-condition for the personal freedom to choose
for good for self and other, [i.e. loving one's neighbor as
one's self]. Aron (1998) utilizing the work of James (1890) and
Bach (1985, 1994), and expanding on Benjamin's thoughts, posits the
inevitability and desirability of self-interest, describing a
"reflexive mind" that oscillates between concern for self and
concern for other. In the absence of a reflexive mind, a person is
handicapped by an " inability to tolerate ambiguity and paradox, to
deal with metaphor, or to maintain multiple points of view, especially
about the self. Instead, in psychopathology, we find polarization,
splitting, either-or- thinking, manic and depressive mood swings and
sadomasochistic role reversals" (Aron, 1998, p. 7).
Psychoanalytic formulations regarding the limitations upon free
will are also supported by findings in cognitive neuroscience. Human
conscious awareness is a limited resource. We can only attend to so many
things at one time. Because of the high demands of information
processing in every-day life, and the limited amount of conscious
awareness one is capable of, automaticity is an essential survival tool.
This means that much of our behavior is determined by previous learning.
In fact researchers in the cognitive study of automaticity suggest that
only about 5% of our moment-to-moment behavior is consciously controlled
(see Strawn & Brown, 2004). This leaves 95% of our behavior outside
of conscious awareness. Automaticity is therefore the unconscious
elicitation of procedural memory and unconscious motivations and affects
(Strawn & Brown, 2004).
While the concept of automaticity may suggest that humans are not
as free as they would like to think they are-this does not mean that
they are wholly determined either. Humans do have the ability to direct
their limited attention to aspects of their behavior that previously has
been outside of awareness (in psychoanalytic terms-unconscious). This
possibility, albeit difficult capability, is certainly inhibited by
Damasio's (1994) barely conscious, (or not conscious at all),
somatic markers. We believe that psychoanalysis can be particularly
helpful in aiding a patient to look at, perhaps for the first time,
affect, cognition, and behavior that heretofore has been unacknowledged,
and yet may be causing the patient great distress in life. This
possibility is adroitly developed, within a relational psychoanalytic
perspective, by Donnel Stern in his 1997 title Unformulated Experience:
From Dissociation to Imagination in Psychoanalysis.
Brugger acknowledges limitations to freedom in the second corollary
concerning volition, but believes that these can be overcome by the
development of moral virtues, which, will actualize the choice for good,
and avoidance of evil. We could not disagree more. We find this failing
paradigm for the avoidance of evil to be unsatisfying, especially in the
light of countless told and untold accounts of moral failures by our
religious leaders and spiritual mentors. While consideration of
personified evil may be beyond the scope of the author's proposal,
we must tarry with the understanding that evil human motives frequently
breach the parapets of moral virtue. The evil wolf deploys in many garbs
including sheep's clothing. Sue Grand (2000) understands evil as
the "perverse hungering for [unhealthy early object-relations) as a
reprieve from the objectlessness of annihilation (Fairbairn, 1952a, b;
Guntrip 1971)." She explains:
... Evil seduces with its perverse promise of recognition. Evil
will always be constituted so that victim after victim is accompanied by
her perpetrator to the obscure solitude of extinction. In each new
victim, the perpetrator shares his own catastrophic loneliness, in what
Bollas (1995) calls the "companionship of the dead." Evil
always reaches its terminus in shared loneliness and in the shared
disappearance of selves. (2000, p. 7, also cf. Prov. 1:10-19).
We believe that moral and intellectual virtues are often
insufficient to the overcoming of evil with good unless the virtues are
imbued with conscious normative emotions. "It is emotion which
stands directly behind activity [i.e. choice] determining its substance
and direction, while thought is related to action [choice] indirectly
and through emotion, determining only its form and that only
partially." (Macmurray, 1992, p. 11). Our psychoanalytic and
theological understanding (supported by cognitive neuroscience) of the
person, leads us to believe that one may not simply apply cognitive
knowledge to a moral dilemma and overcome it if there are aspects of the
personality (e.g., unconscious object relations and affects) that are
motivating the person in unknown ways. These unknown and unacknowledged
personal dynamics will deploy as defensive operations (repression,
denial, dissociation, etc.) and continue to propel a person toward
rationally objectionable but affectively desirable choices. As Paul
writes, "I do not understand my own actions. For I do not do what I
want, but I do the very thing I hate" (Romans 7:15, NRSV). Clearly
Paul knew what he wanted to do and was prone to utilize reason in his
pursuit of "the good." Consequently, we concur with Fairbairn
(1952b) and Guntrip (1952) that psychotherapy (and we believe the
process of spiritual transformation) involves a kind of exorcism of
internal/unconscious/ irrational affects, cognitions, and object
relations. Hence humans are in need of re-creation through relationship
with the "other" which potentiates the development of more
normative object relations, affects and cognitions; these in turn can
prompt choices to act in the service of individuals living in friendship
and love. Without a "stripping of the psyche," a new coat of
paint may look good for a while, but will eventually result in cracking,
further deterioration and ultimately destruction.
A FINAL ETHICAL CONSIDERATION
Finally, because we concur that explicitly exposing one's
anthropology is essential, we would further state that there is one more
important reason for being clear about one's implicit anthropology,
personal tradition, and psychotherapeutic orientation. If, as Brugger
asserts, all psychologists enter their work with unspoken
anthropological "traditions," and if these traditions contain
deep metaphors of ultimacy, then they are indeed religio-ethical systems
(Browning, 1987; Browning &c Cooper, 2004). In this case, the
practice of psychotherapy itself has a moral dimension. We agree with
Cushman (1995) that psychotherapy can therefore be understood as a moral
discourse between patient and therapist. Every therapist's
subjectivity is permeated by explicit and implicit beliefs concerning
what is normal, healthy, and even how one "ought" to live a
"good life." Patients' subjectivities may contain very
different ethics than those of the psychotherapist. The task of the
ethically sensitive therapist is neither to hide one's values
"under a bushel", nor to flood the patient with
self-disclosure, advice or moral reproof. As psychologists who happen to
be Christians, we must become aware, as much as we can, of our
traditions, values, and countertransferences. We may then come to
recognize that our psychotherapy is a conversation between two
individuals about ethics as well as pathology.
CONCLUSION
Again, we express our gratitude to the author for this significant
and valuable project of formulating a harmonious account of normative
human nature for clinical psychology. We have focused on our alternative
perspectives regarding the author's a) elevation of belief in the
human capacity to "know all truth" to the same level of
significance as the human capacity for communion with God and each
other, b) assertions regarding the form of the human soul, c)
anthropocentric focus on the redemption of humankind, d) marginalization
of human emotions, and c) reliance upon the instillation of moral
virtues as sufficient for choosing good and avoiding evil. We have also
articulated a relational perspective of the intersubjective field as the
cauldron where narcissism can be transformed to love through
encountering the "other." We have been explicit regarding our
subjectivities as variant Protestant Christians and relational
psychoanalysts. We have called for integrity not only in theory
construction but also in psychotherapeutic relating. We hope that our
musings will be of benefit to the author's project and that the
author will have experienced our words as not only deconstructive, but
as constructive dialogue.
REFERENCES
Anderson, R, (1998), On being human; The spiritual saga of a
crcaturely soul. In. W. S. Brown, N. Murphy, & H. N. Malony (Eds.),
Whatever happened to the soul- Scientific and theological portraits of
human nature (pp. 17.5-84). Philadelphia; Fortress.
Aron, L. (1998). The relational body and the reflexive mind. In L.
Aron and F S. Anderson (Eds.), Relational perspectives on the body (pp.
3-37). Hillsdale, NJ: The Analytic Press.
Bach, S. (1985). Narcissistic states and the therapeutic process.
New York; Aronson.
Bach. S. (1994). The language of perversion and the language of
love. Northvale, NJ: Aronson.
Balswick, J. O., Kind, P. E., & Reimer, K. S. (2005). The
reciprocating self: Human development in the theological perspective.
Downers Grove, IL: Inrervarsity Press.
Benjamin, J. (1990). Recognition and destruction: An outline of
subjectivity. In L. Aron & S. Mitchell (Eds.), Relational
psychoanalysis: The emergence of a tradition (pp. 181-210). Hillsdale,
NJ: Analytic Press.
Bollas, C. (1995). Cracking up: The work of unconscious experience.
NcwYork: Hill & Wang.
Brown, W. S., Murphy, N., & Malony, H. N. (1998). Whatever
happened to the soul? Scientific and theological portraits of human
nature. Philadelphia, PA: Fortress.
Browning, D. S. (1987). Religious thought and the modern
psychologies: A critical conversation in the theology of culture.
Philadelphia, PA: Fortress.
Browning, D. S., & Cooper, T. D. (2004), Religious thought and
the modern psychologies (2nd ed.). Philadelphia, PA: Fortress.
Brugger, E. C. (2008). Anthropological foundations for clinieal
psychology: A proposal, journal of Psychology & Theology, 36(1),
5-15.
Cushman, P. (1995). Constructing the self, constructing America.
Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes' error: Emotion, reason and
the human brain. New York: C. P. Putnam.
Erler, R. J. & Marquard, R. (Eds.). (1986). Karl Barth, A Karl
Barth Reader (G. W. Bromiley,Trans.). Grand Rapids: W.B. Erdroans.
Fairbairn, W. R. D. (1952a). An object relations theory of the
personality. New York: Basic Books.
Fairbairn, W. R. D. (1952b). Psychoanalytic studies of the
personality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Grand, S. (2000). The reproduction of evil: A clinical and cultural
perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Green, J. B. (1998). Bodies-that is, human lives: A re-examination
of human nature in the Bible. In W. S. Brown, N. Murphy, & H. N.
Malony (Eds.), Whatever happened to the soul? Scientific and theological
portraits of human nature (pp. 149-174). Minneapolis, MN: Fortress.
Green, J. B. (2004a). What does it mean to be human? Another
chapter in the ongoing interaction of science and scripture. In M.
Jeeves (Ed.), From cells to souls--and beyond: Changing portraits of
human nature (pp. 179-198). Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.
Green, J. B. (2004b). Resurrection of the hody: New testament
voices concerning personal continuity and the afterlife. In J. B. Green
(Ed.), What about the soul? Neuroscience and Christian anthropology (pp.
85-100). Nashville, TN: Abingdon.
Grenz, S. (2001). The social God and the relational self.
Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.
Guntrip, H. (1952). The psychotherapist as parent and exorcist. In
J. Hazell (Ed.), Personal relations therapy: The collected papers of
H.J. S. Guntripipp. 63-88). Northvalc, NJ: Jason Aronson.
Guntrip, H. (1971). Psychoanalytic studies of the personality.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Heimann, P. (1950). On eountertransfcrence. International journal
of Psychoanalysis, 31, 81-84.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard Univ. Press.
LaCugna, C. M. (1992). God for us: The Trinity and Christian life.
San Francisco: Harper.
Lazarus, R. S. i 1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion
& cognition. American Psychologist, 37,1019-1024.
Lazarus, R. S. (1984a). Cognition, emotion and motivation: The
doctoring of Humpty-Dumpty. In K. R. Scherer and P. Ekman (Eds.),
Approaches to Emotion (pp. 221-238). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Lazarus, R. S. (1984b). The primacy of cognition. American
Psychologist, 39,124-129.
Lichtcnberg, J. D. (1987). Infant studies and clinical work with
adults. Psychoanalytic Inquiry, 7,311-30.
Little, M. (1951). Transference neurosis and transference
psychosis: Toward basic unity. London: Free Association Books.
Macmurray, J. (1991). Persons in relation. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Humanities Press.
Macmurray, J. (1992). Reason and emotion. Amhearst, NY: Humanity
Books.
Mandler, G. (1975). Mind and emotion. New York: Wiley.
Mitchell, S. (1988). Relational concepts in psychoanalysis: An
integration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.
Moltmann, J. (1985). God in creation: A new theology of creation
and the spirit of God (M. Kohl, Trans.). San Francisco: Harper and Row.
Murphy, N. (2006). Bodies and souls, or spirited bodies? Cambridge:
Cambridge.
Novey, S. (1959). A clinical view of affect theory in
psychoanalysis. International journal of Psychoanalysis, 40,94-104.
Novey, S. (1961), Further considerations on affect theory in
psychoanalysis. International journal of Psychoanalysis, 42, 21-31
Racket, H. (1957). Transference and countertrans ference. London:
Marscfield.
Richardson, F. C, Fowers, B. J., & Guignon, C. B. (1999).
Re-envisioning psychology: Moral dimensions of theory and practice. San
Francisco, CA:Jossey-Bass.
Sandler, J. (1985). Towards a reconsideration of a psyehoanalync
theory of motivation. Bulletin of Anna Freud Center, 8, 223-44.
Searles, H. F. (1955). Collected papers on schizophrenia and
related subjects. New York: International Universities Press.
Searles, H. F. (1979). Countertransference and related subjects.
New York: International Universities Press.
Shults, F. L. (2003). Reforming theological anthropology: After the
philosophical turn to relationality. Grand Rapids, MLW.B.Erdmans.
Stein, R. (1999). Psychoanalytic theories of affect. London: Karnac
Books.
Stern, D. (1985). The interpersonal world of the infant. New York:
Basic Books.
Stern, D. B. (1997). Unformulated experience. Hillsdale, NJ:
Analytic Press.
Strawn, B. D., & Brown, W. S. (2004). Wesleyan holiness through
the eyes of cognitive science and psychotherapy, journal of Psychology
& Christianity, 23(2), 121-129.
Taylor, C. (1985). Human agency and language: Philosophical papers
I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
The Holy Bible, NRSV(1989). Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan.
Vitz, P. (2006). The embodied self: Evidence from cognitive
psychology and neuropsychology In P. Vitz, & S. Felch (Eds.). The
self: beyond the postmodern crisis (pp. 113-127). Wilmington, DE: IS1
Books.
Warfield, B. B. (1912). The person and work of Christ.
Philadelphia: Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing.
Winnicott, D. W. (1958). Hate in the countertransference. In
Through pediatrics to Psychoanalysis: Collected papers (pp. 194-. 203).
London: Tavistock.
Winnicott, D. W. (1977). Ego distortion in terms of true and false
self. In The maturational processes and the facilitating environment:
Studies in the theory of emotional development (pp. 140-152). New York:
International Universities Press.
Winnicott, D. W. (1989). The use of an object and relating through
identification. In C. Winnicott, R. Shepherd, & M. Davis (Eds.),
Psycho-Analytic explorations (pp. 218-227). Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ.
Press.
Zizioulas, J. D. (1985). Being as communion: Studies in personhood
and the church. Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir's Semi-
AUTHORS
HOFFMAN, L. W. Address: 1150 Glenlivet Drive, Suite A-15,
Allentown, PA 18106. Title: Clinical Psychologist and Co-Director,
Brookhaven Center for Counseling and Development; Co-Director, Society
for the Exploration of Psychoanalytic Therapies and Theology (SEPTT).
Degrees: BA, Bob Jones University; MAR, Theology, Westminster Seminary;
MS, Counseling, Villanova University; PhD, Clinical Psychology, Union
Institute; Certificate, Post-Doctoral Program in Psychotherapy and
Psychoanalysis, New York University. Specialization: Relational
Psychoanalysis and Psychoanalytic Psychotherapy.
STRAWN, B. D. Address: 6729 NW 39th Expressway, Bethany, OK, 73008.
bstrawn@snu.edu. Title: Vice President for Spiritual Development and the
Dean of the Chapel, Southern Nazarcnc University, Bethany, OK: Assoc.
Director, Society for the Exploration of Psychoanalytic Therapies and
Theology (SEPTT). Degrees: BA, Point Loma Nazarenc University; MA,
Theology, Fuller Seminary; PhD, Clinical Psychology, School of
Psychology, Fuller Seminary. Specializations: Integration of
psychology/psychoanalysis and theology and psychoanalytic psychotherapy.
LOWELL W. HOFFMAN
Brookhaven Center for Counseling & Development
BRAD D. STRAWN
Southern Nazarene University
Please address correspondence to L. W. Hoffman, PhD, 1150 Glenlivet
Drive, Suite A-15, Allentown, PA 18106. Email: lowellwmhoffman@aol.com.
(1) We arc indebted to John Carter, Ph.D. for reminding us of
Warficlds contribution to this topic.
(2) Object relations theory along with interpersonal psychoanalytic
theory is foundational to the developments of relational psychoanalysis.
We recognize as well the valuable contributions of attachment theory and
understand this area of study to be consistent with and explanatory of
object relational concepts.
(3) I (LWH) am grateful to Marie Hoffman, Ph.D. for her careful
reading of this manuscript and in particular, her suggestions regarding
this section.