After postmodernism: perspectivism, a Christian epistemology of love, and the ideological surround.
Watson, P.J.
Postmodernism liberates the integration of psychology and
Christianity from the domination of modernism, but also leads to a
vertiginous relativism. A movement beyond postmodernism seems essential.
For Christians, such a movement might build upon the "future
objectivity" of Friedrich Nietzsche's postmodern
perspectivism. Writings of the French social theorist Rene Girard
suggest how this "objectivity" might be assimilated within a
Christian metanarrative about Truth. His theory more specifically
implies that the Bible commands an epistemology of love that is
non-authoritarian, critical, and integrative. Methods compatible with an
epistemology of love have been developed within an ideological surround
model of the relationship between psychology and religion. An
epistemology of love supplies a metaperspective for seeing and then
telling a coherent metanarrative about the challenges of integration
after postmodernism.
**********
Christian scholars increasingly claim that "the ideological
engine propelling the movement of modernity is broken down
irreparably" (Oden, 1995b, p. 35) and is being replaced by a
postmodernism that has ambivalent implications for Christianity. For
Oden (1995a), this historical process signals the beneficial decline of
the chauvinistic domination of modernism. "Modern chauvinism,"
he asserts, "regards modernity as the intrinsically superior ethos
by which all premodern views are harshly judged as primitive,
misogynist, or artless" (Oden, 1995a, p. 27). Perhaps more than
anything else, this presumption of being "intrinsically
superior" is what has "broken down irreparably."
Modernism originated in the early Enlightenment quest for an
"objective" rationality that could overcome the religious
violence of 17th Century Europe (Stout, 1988; Toulmin, 1990). Along with
improving life through science, this objective rationality was presumed
to be innocent of ideological aspirations of its own and could thus
supply a value-neutral process for mediating religious conflicts.
Postmodern critiques have argued, however, that all rationality is the
simultaneous product and producer of power (Foucault, 1980).
Enlightenment rationality, in particular, was a powerful construction of
emerging democratic and capitalist social structures and was not more
"objective" than the premodern "subjectivities" it
replaced (MacIntyre, 1988). The power arrangements of one regime of
understanding simply overthrew the power arrangements of another. The
"rationality" of modernist "objectivity" was itself
culturally relative and hence chauvinistic in its presumption of
intrinsic superiority.
Postmodernism radically changes the relationship between psychology
and religion. Psychology can now be seen as a modernist construction
that, among other things, used "objective" rationality to
explain (and often explain away) religion (O'Connor, 2001).
Postmodern critique means that modernist psychology can no longer be
described non-controversially as a value-neutral enterprise capable of
judging religion in terms of an "intrinsically superior
ethos." Psychology instead can be characterized as a modernist
invention that worked toward the overthrow of religion.
"Psychologists of religion," Carrette (2001) recently argued,
"have to be aware that to some extent they have served to provide a
disciplinary apparatus for 'psychologizing' religion, making
religious ideas more responsive to a Western, individualistic and
capitalistic regime" (p. 120). Today, a postmodern framework makes
it possible to see how psychology had origins in religion, how it
attempted to replace religious with more secular norms of conduct, and
how it sometimes preached a new faith based upon self-worship (Kvale,
1992).
By leveling the relationship of religion with psychology (and with
science more generally), post-modernism exerts a potentially positive
influence on Christianity. But negative consequences appear as well.
Radical forms of postmodernism reduce all worldviews to power
arrangements (Rosenau, 1992). The result is a sweeping pluralism in
which the "metanarratives" of all forms of social life become
equally (in)valid. Webber (1999) states the obvious point:
"Evangelicals take the universal character of the Christian
metanarrative as an essential aspect of the framework of Christian
faith. In this matter evangelicals will need to stand against postmodern
relativism" (p. 95). The problem, however, is that they must
"stand against" a paradox. Christian and all other
metanarratives are now trapped within the "intrinsically superior
ethos" of a postmodern metanarrative that tells the story that
there can be no metanarratives:
Postmodernity ... functions as the larger interpretative frame that
relativizes all other worldviews as simply local stories with no
legitimate claims to reality or universality.... The postmodernist
is ... caught in a performative contradiction, arguing against the
necessity of metanarratives precisely by (surreptitious) appeal to a
metanarrative. (Middleton & Walsh, 1995, p. 77)
How is it even possible to "stand against" such a
paradox? Unreflective reassertion of some premodern worldview moves
toward a nostalgic "ghettoization" of thought. For many, this
approach would at best, be irrelevant and at worst, prepare the way for
the authoritarianism and violence that led to modernist scientific and
democratic innovations in the first place. Moreover, in an age of global
communications, is not pluralism an indisputable empirical reality?
Indeed, is not pluralism a reality even within the church (Johnson &
Jones, 2000)? Does not relativism, therefore, seem inevitable in the
absence of universal standards that can avoid the sometimes-coercive use
of power? And given the seemingly endless role of violence in human
affairs, does not an emphasis on power seem to supply the most plausible
(if surreptitious) metanarrative of social life?
Implicitly responding to such questions, Erickson (2001) recently
concluded, "We must work toward a postpostmodernism, not simply
ignoring the phenomenon of postmodernism, and reverting to a
prepostmodernism, but also not merely halting with postmodernism. We
must transcend postmodernism" (p. 293). For Christians, therefore,
the situation seems to demand a movement beyond postmodernism. The
daunting integrative challenge is to articulate new positions that
remain faithful to premodern Christian traditions, that preserve the
widely appreciated scientific and democratic social achievements of
modernism, and that are appropriately sensitive to the realities of
postmodern pluralism.
The goal of this paper is to illustrate how this "daunting
challenge" might be met. It will be argued that one possibility for
moving beyond postmodernism appears in Friedrich Nietzsche's
(1887/1967) postmodern speculations about the pluralistic perspectivism
of a "future objectivity." Ideas developed by the French
social theorist Rene Girard (e.g., 1978) suggest how this "future
objectivity" is not only consistent with, but an actual product of
the premodern Christian witness. Premodern and postmodern supports for
perspectivism necessarily have concrete methodological implications for
modernist social science. Those implications have been explored in an
ideological surround model of the relationship between religion and
psychology (Watson, 1993, 1994). This model has been criticized for
being insufficiently responsive to postmodern insights into power
(Carrette, 2001), but Girard's thought suggests how a Christian
postpostmodernism can avoid the liabilities of a postmodern overemphasis on power.
NIETZSCHE'S "FUTURE OBJECTIVITY"
Pluralism is an indisputable empirical reality that no movement
beyond postmodernism can ignore. This empirical reality was already
obvious to Friedrich Nietzsche, the 19th Century philosopher who stood
at the origins of the postmodern emphasis on power (e.g., Erickson,
2001, pp. 84-92). Nietzsche's (1887/1967) response to pluralism was
a perspectivism that encouraged the development of new knowledge through
what he called a "future objectivity":
But precisely because we seek knowledge, let us not be ungrateful to ...
resolute reversals of accustomed perspectives and valuations ... [T]o
see differently ..., to want to see differently, is no small discipline
and preparation of the intellect for its future 'objectivity'--the
latter understood not as 'contemplation without interest' (which is a
nonsensical absurdity), but as the ability to control one's Pro and Con
and to dispose of them, so that one knows how to employ a variety of
perspectives and affective interpretations in the service of knowledge.
Henceforth ... let us be on guard against the dangerous old conceptual
fiction that posited a 'pure, will-less, painless, time-less knowing
subject'; let us guard against the snares of such contradictory concepts
as 'pure reason,' 'absolute spirituality,' 'knowing in itself': these
always demand that we should think of an eye that is completely
unthinkable, an eye turned in no particular direction, in which the
active and interpreting forces, through which alone seeing becomes
seeing something, are supposed to be lacking; these always demand of the
eye an absurdity and a nonsense. There is only a perspective seeing,
only a perspective 'knowing'; and the more affects we allow to speak
about one thing, the more eyes, different eyes, we can use to observe
one thing, the more complete will our 'concept' of this thing, our
'objectivity,' be.... (p. 119, italics in original)
A Christian movement beyond postmodernism might build upon
Nietzsche's "future objectivity." Nietzsche's
perspectivism, nevertheless, was positioned within his well-known
atheism; so, for the purposes of integration, his ideas would have to be
repositioned within a Christian framework. To that end, Nietzsche's
perspectivism can be interrogated with a series of fairly obvious
questions. Plausible answers to those questions suggest how a
"future objectivity" might be moved in Christian directions.
First, from what vantage point is Nietzsche himself seeing
perspectives seeing? Once the plausibility of perspectivism is admitted,
then this question becomes an obvious concern for all those forms of
"seeing" that are captured within the power of
Nietzsche's interpretative framework. The answer to this question
cannot be that Nietzsche is seeing things from just another perspective
embedded in the "pros" and "cons" of his
contemporary intellectual landscape. If that were so, his thought would
lack the "height" necessary to see a panorama of perspectives.
His thought must be "hovering" above the other perspectives.
He must be "looking down" on them from a
"metaperspective."
When Nietzsche looks down from his metaperspective, is he not
advocating some specific, "correct" response to the pluralism
of perspectives? That certainly seems to be the case. After all, he does
not imply that equally useful solutions can be found in a "future
chaos" or in the assertion of some dominating power that would
maintain order. He advocates instead a "future objectivity."
He encourages us to control our "Pro and Con." He recommends
that we see with more and different "eyes."
Then it sounds like Nietzsche is saying his metaperspective is
"true." How can he say that? In his emphasis on power, did not
Nietzsche reject all belief in "truth"? All kinds of
perspectives probably exist on what Nietzsche was trying to say about
perspectives. Clark (1990), for instance, has argued that
Nietzsche's perspectivism did not reflect a rejection of
"truth," but only of a "metaphysical correspondence
theory of truth, the understanding of truth as correspondence to
things-in-themselves" (p. 131). But Clark might be wrong. Nietzsche
favored art as a way of knowing (e.g., 1887/1967, pp. 153-156). Perhaps,
he merely believed that he was offering a more rhetorically compelling
description of pluralism, that his metaperspective was more
aesthetically satisfying than the other available options. Even here,
however, he would at least implicitly be claiming to offer a
"better" story, one that subsumes all the premodern and modern
stories that he was able to "see" at the time. In other words,
he presented a (surreptitious) postmodern metanarrative that he somehow
believed to be "intrinsically superior."
But if we can now see and at least to some degree appreciate
Nietzsche's ability to see perspectives seeing, from what vantage
point are we seeing this situation? Given the postmodern emphasis on
social construction, does not our own perspective on Nietzsche
necessarily have origins in history? All kinds of answers probably make
sense. Most generally, however, a "lower" prepostmodern
perspective must have within itself the conceptual resources to
"see" and appreciate Nietzsche's own socially constructed
ability to see perspectives seeing. Explicit development of those
conceptual resources could lead to the creation of a metaperspective
that moved beyond postmodernism. From this metaperspective, it should be
possible to "look down" and construct a metanarrative
describing prepostmodern perspectives and Nietzsche's own
postmodern metaperspective.
What prepostmodern perspective has the conceptual resources to
produce such a postpostmodern metanarrative? Among the "future
objectivities" after postmodernism, attempts to answer this
question will likely be the focus of great conflict. For some, the task
will be to construct an increasingly compelling and truthful
metanarrative that describes perspectives, intermediate metaperspectives
like Nietzsche's, and a final metaperspective that moves beyond
postmodernism. Christians will believe that Christianity can and should
serve as the foundation for such a metaperspective. An example of that
possibility may appear in the work of the French social theorist Rene
Girard.
DESIRE, SCAPEGOATS, AND THE BIBLE
Girard's work has been described as "the most sweeping
and significant intellectual break-through of the modern age" and
as "something like a unified field theory" of the humanities
and social sciences (Bailie, 1995, p. 4). The three basic elements of
his thought begin with a theory of desire (Girard, 1965). The theory of
desire leads to an explanation of how culture originates (Girard, 1972),
and an understanding of human cultural development then reveals the
pivotal historical role of the Judeo-Christian Scriptures (Girard, 1978,
1986). As noted previously, these three elements have profound
implications for the tasks of integration (Watson, 1998).
Girard (1965) first argues that human desire develops through
imitation or what he calls mimesis. Like all species, humans inherit
appetites that motivate them to obtain such survival needs as food,
water, sex, and shelter, to name a few. Unlike other species, however,
humans rely more on learning to determine which specific objects should
be desired. An "appetite" for movement, for example, is
essential to the survival of most species. Fish swim, birds fly, and
horses gallop. Humans walk, but they also drive cars, sail ships, and
fly space shuttles. And to take just one of these examples, they do not
just drive cars. They drive cars ranging from the oldest jalopy to the
newest luxury sedan. Either in personal life or through the media, other
people become models for defining which cars an individual should
desire. These models have some "power" that attracts the
admiring attention of others, and behind all human desire is the
ultimate desire to be desired just like the model. Human desire for
specific objects, therefore, is not strictly determined by instincts,
but instead reflects the social history of mimesis.
Mimetic desire is a triangular process involving a subject, a
model, and an object of desire. Each individual "subject" sees
through the actions of a model which specific objects should be desired.
An external mediation of mimetic desire occurs when the model is so far
superior to the subject in acquiring the object that the subject cannot
compete with the model for that object. The social life of external
mediation tends to be harmonious. When a teenage son first learns to
drive, for instance, he may look up to his father and appreciatively
follow his guidance in how to control the car. In human relationships,
however, external mediation tends toward internal mediation. By
following the model's pattern, the subject eventually approaches
the model's abilities along relevant dimensions of functioning and
begins to compete with the model for the object. The model's
abilities are now within or "internal to" those of the
subject. Continued efforts by the model to influence the subject become
potential sources of conflict. Son and father may now argue over all
kinds of issues related to control of the car.
In the absence of limiting factors, the convergence of subjects and
models on the same objects can result in death. Within a Girardian
framework, for instance, The Communist Manifesto (Marx & Engels,
1848/1992) illustrates the dynamics of triangular desire. For
"proletariat" subjects, the "bourgeoisie" models a
desire for property. Bourgeois capitalism necessarily creates larger and
larger numbers of the proletariat and thereby produces its own
"grave-diggers" (Marx & Engels, p. 32). Hence, historical
processes inexorably transform a condition of external bourgeois
mediation into a state of internal mediation in which the proletariat
joins together in a powerful communist movement. This movement will use
revolutionary violence to transform private bourgeois property into
state property held in common for the proletariat. This violence will
have as its model the violence of bourgeois desire that is obvious in
such practices as labor exploitation, slavery, and colonialism. The
logical end of unrestrained desire will be death. Bourgeois violence
will beget the violence of the proletariat.
In the second element of his thought, Girard (1972) claims that the
dynamics of mimetic desire explain the origins of primitive religion and
human culture. As the example of Marx and Engels (1848/1992) makes
clear, mimetic processes associated with a dyad operate at the group
level as well. Girard argues that early bands of proto-humans
periodically fell through rivalries of internal mediation into "a
war of all against all." A species-specific mechanism evolved for
controlling this destructive potential. In that mechanism, the murder of
a hapless scapegoat allowed the group to discharge its violent
frustrations and reestablish peace.
This unity of group murder was the critical process that eventually
transformed proto-human bands into the first human communities. A sound
uttered over the body of a victim became the first "word" of
communal life and signified what must have seemed like a
"god." Killing the scapegoat had "magically"
transformed bloody chaos into communal harmony. To the primitive mind,
the scapegoat must have "caused" the original chaos because
killing the scapegoat ended the chaos. Only an awe-inspiring
"god" could have been that powerful. Newly formed communities
then protected themselves from future violent crises by reenacting the
founding event. They periodically purged themselves of the mounting
frustrations of desire by staging the more controlled and less
chaotically dangerous murders of a human sacrifice.
Ritualized human sacrifice, thus, defined the first efforts of
primitive religion to forestall the socially disintegrating effects of
desire. Sacrifices produced periods of peace during which cultural
innovations could occur. In other words, sacrifices gave communities
time to make innovations in the structure of social relationships that
allowed them to better control desire and to better use nature to
satisfy desire. Some changes even worked on the sacrificial process
itself, for example, by substituting animal for human victims. The peace
of cultural innovations then worked as a self-reinforcing dynamic. Peace
led to cultural innovation, which led to longer peace, which then led to
greater cultural innovation, and so on.
Even with successful innovations, however, social solidarity was
periodically threatened by desire. Humanity was trapped in a cyclical history of peace, desire, frustration, violence, sacrifice, and peace.
Social solidarity required power arrangements that could discharge, when
necessary, the violence of communal rivalries into the sacrifice of
scapegoats. Girard finds vestiges of this mechanism in the seemingly
interminable "holocausts" of history, but origins of the
process are most obvious in myths. Careful analysis of a myth will
reveal that it is the story of a murder told from the self-exonerating
perspective of the murderers.
Purely human history, therefore, occurs in cycles sealed within an
intelligibility that is powered by murder. A murderous intelligibility
lacks the conceptual resources for standing outside itself and
"objectively" judging the processes of murderous
intelligibility. This is true because purely human language crystallizes
around a first word that designates a murder, and all subsequent words
have a genealogy that can be traced back to that first word. At the
heart of all purely human culture is a sensibility founded on a
rationality that justifies bloodshed. One specific murderous
intelligibility might insightfully condemn and argue for the
"murder" of another, but that perspective could not escape
itself and find a place of neutrality for offering a general
condemnation of the murderous mechanisms of desire.
But is not a primary attraction of postmodernism precisely its
ability to unmask the scapegoating oppressions of power (e.g., Castelli,
1991)? And if Girard is correct, how is that even possible? In a
cyclical history theoretically sealed within the thought structures of
murderous intelligibility, what events socially constructed our ability
to condemn the mechanisms of murderous intelligibility? In the third and
final element of his thought, Girard (1978) identifies the
Judeo-Christian Scriptures as the source of these "postmodern"
abilities. God enters human history and begins the process of replacing
dark and murderous human words based on blood with the Word of God based
on light and love (John 1: 1-5). In part, the goal of this Word is to
explain "what has been hidden since the foundation of the
world" (Matthew 13: 35). Murderous mimetic desire has been hidden
since the foundation of the world, and humanity should use the Word to
socially construct a very different world with a very different
language.
In the Christian Old Testament, for example, God uses the story of
an oppressed people to narrate the injustice and ultimate futility of
all sacrificial violence (e.g., Micah 6: 6-8). The truth of these
victims supplies the hermeneutical key that unlocks all ancient and
contemporary mythological lies. These texts specifically reveal that
murderous intelligibility originates in misdirected mimetic desire.
Humanity was tempted away from an external mediation of the only model
capable of preventing violence and was led instead to believe that being
"god" was an appropriate object of desire (Genesis 3: 1-7).
This desire to be "god" guaranteed a fall of human
relationships into the destruction of internal mediation. With that
fall, each person would act like a "god" with the power to
define good and evil for all others. Conflict would become inevitable.
Even a brother would kill a brother (Genesis 4: 1-8).
Then in the New Testament, Christ incarnates the metanarrative of
God's Truth that explains all other narratives and metanarratives.
The crucifixion shows how the scapegoating process is the power used and
justified by regimes of murderous intelligibility, even when employed
against the only completely innocent victim who ever lived. With the
resurrection, Truth for the first and only time in history returns from
death to falsify the mythological lies of social solidarity. In this
resurrection, Truth sets humanity free and establishes a new foundation
for understanding. A loving intelligibility enters history and begins
the long, slow, and often torturous process of overcoming the power of
murderous intelligibilities.
This Love speaks Truth to power in two most fundamental ways. A
loving intelligibility first emphasizes that our mimetic gaze should
never miss the mark of seeing and following the external mediation of
Truth. Warnings are offered about the consequences of failing to do so,
for the "wages" of misdirected desire "is death"
(Romans 6:23). Then with a metaperspective that only Truth makes
possible, this loving intelligibility unmasks the violent exclusions of
murderous intelligibilities and teaches a concern for all potential
victims. A loving intelligibility, in other words, says, "You shall
love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and
with all your mind" (Matthew 22: 37). Then it adds, "You shall
love your neighbor as yourself" (Matthew 22:39). This loving should
also occur without concern for the socially constructed communal
affiliations of the self or of the neighbor (Luke 10: 29-37).
Skepticism about Girard's approach to Scripture could rest
upon its apparent innovativeness. How could so apparently novel and
"discontinuous" an interpretation of the Bible be part of a
continuous metanarrative of loving intelligibility? But Girard's
perspective is not wholly unique. Others have seen elements of what he
has seen. Nietzsche did, for example (Girard, 1996). In Christianity,
Nietzsche "recognized that a new perspective on the world and a new
kind of religious personality were born in the traditions and Scriptures
of the Jewish people and came to fruition in the teachings of Jesus and
the way in which followers perceived his death" (Williams, 2001, p.
xxi). "Rome versus Judea; Judea versus Rome" was how Nietzsche
(1887/1967, p. 52) described the fundamental choice available to
humanity for understanding good and evil. Nietzsche rejected the
"new perspective" of Judea and essentially embraced
"Rome." Though not an advocate of literal sacrifice, he
nevertheless affirmed a pagan desire for the godlikeness of an Overman,
that was to be achieved, if necessary, "by sweeping aside the weak
who were unable to contribute to creating new traditions and
institutions and waging war" (Williams, p. xxii).
Contemporary followers of the (surreptitious) postmodern
metanarrative have learned from Nietzsche how to see the scapegoating
exclusions that stand behind the social solidarity of the crowd. As
interpreted within a Girardian perspective, however, they have not seen
that Nietzsche learned this from Christianity (Girard, 1996), nor have
they embraced his aristocratic rejection of the weak. Indeed, when they
use Nietzsche to defend victims, they fail to see that they are looking
down on cyclical pagan history from the linear Christian history of the
Cross. This location supplies a metaperspective from which a Christian
movement beyond postmodernism might begin. From this metaperspective,
postmodernism (and also modernism) will look very different. Postmodern
(and also modern) intellectuals may demythologize the Bible, but it is
the Bible that demythologizes the world and makes their work possible:
By an astonishing reversal, it is texts that are twenty or twenty-five
centuries old--initially revered blindly but today rejected with
contempt--that will reveal themselves to be the only means of furthering
all that is good and true in the anti-Christian endeavors of modern
times: the as-yet-ineffectual determination to rid the world of the
sacred cult of violence. (Girard, 1978, pp. 177-178)
In short, postmodernism articulates a (surreptitious) metanarrative
that unmasks the scapegoating oppressions associated with the
metanarratives of all purely human forms of intelligibility. According
to the postmodern argument, such metanarratives and all other aspects of
culture are the socially constructed products of power. But if all
history is sealed within the power arrangements of social construction,
what liberating perspectives stood outside those power arrangements and
made it possible for the postmodernist to see the abuses of socially
constructed power? The answer to that question, according to Girard, is
found in the Judeo-Christian scriptures. God entered history to help
humanity see with a loving intelligibility what it was doing through the
murderous intelligibilities of its social constructions. When Nietzsche
sees perspectives seeing, he is seeing from the (surreptitious)
metaperspective of the Cross. This claim will scandalize non-Christians
and will seem like an act of violent Christian internal mediation. From
a Girardian metaperspective, however, Christians will see that all
abilities to see and unmask the words of power will be based upon the
powers of the Word.
AFTER SCAPEGOATING: THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF LOVE
If the commandment is to "love the Lord your God ... with all
your mind," then a Christian movement beyond postmodernism must
have epistemological implications (Girard, 1978, p. 127). A loving
intelligibility presumably must grow in knowledge through an
epistemology of love:
But love certainly is not a renunciation of any form of rationality or
an abandonment to the forces of ignorance. Love is at one and the same
time the divine being and the basis of any real knowledge. The New
Testament contains what amounts to a genuine epistemology of love, the
principle of which is clearly formulated in the first Epistle of John:
'He who loves his brother abides in the light, and in it there is no
cause for stumbling. But he who hates his brother is in the darkness and
walks in the darkness, and does not know where he is going, because the
darkness has blinded his eyes'. (1 John 2: 10-11; Girard, 1978, p. 277,
emphasis added)
A Christian movement beyond postmodernism would accept
Nietzsche's emphasis on seeing, but would see all seeing from the
metaperspective of love. This love would not be just another affect. The
positive affects of social life often appear when subjects and models
enjoy relationships of external mediation. Positive affects devolve into
negative affects as externally mediated relationships move toward
internal mediation. Christian love would be no mere social affect, but
instead would be "the divine being and the basis of any real
knowledge" and would rest instead upon a unique and definitive act
(John 3: 16). In this act, the Word was crucified by the words of
communities trapped within the "darkness" of murderous
intelligibilities. This crucifixion supplied the "light" of a
definitive "rationality" that makes it possible to see the
Truth about the sacrificial dynamics underlying all purely human affects
and desires.
The eyes of this Christian love, for example, might see how to
build upon a potentially cryptic statement once made by Jesus,
"What then is this that is written: 'The very stone which the
builders rejected has become the head of the corner'" (Luke
20: 17). At least in Girardian terms, this mimetic echo of Psalm 118 can
mean that perspectives maintain intellectual and social solidarity
through the rejection of "stones" that then create and
strengthen other perspectives.
The process can be usefully oversimplified. In a time of growing
internal discord and disarray, a religious perspective attempts to
maintain its social and intellectual solidarity by rejecting Galileo. A
modernist perspective then is built upon this rejected stone (and
others) and increasingly (over centuries) develops solidarity through
scapegoating rejections of religion. Scapegoating rejections of religion
by modernism serve as models for religion to scapegoat modernism and
vice versa in a seemingly endless cycle. Nietzsche (1887/1967) then sees
how both religion and modernism maintain solidarity through an ascetic
scapegoating of those free spirits who artistically express their lives
through a passionate will to power. Upon this rejected stone is built a
postmodern perspective that enters into relationships of rivalry and
rejection with religion and modernism. And, of course, the list of
perspectives can seem endless: Marxist (with the proletariat as the
rejected stone), feminist (with women as the rejected stone),
psychoanalytic (with sexuality as the rejected stone), various forms of
fundamentalism (with religious texts as the rejected stones), gay and
lesbian (with the homosexual as the rejected stone), and so on and so
on.
A Christian movement beyond postmodernism would see an influence of
the Bible in what appears to be an accelerating proliferation of
perspectives. The Bible helps create a process of seeing potential myths
about "rejected stones" in terms of the Truth of victims
instead of the lies of murderers. In this, the Bible demythologizes the
world and promotes the differentiation of humanity. Indeed, Christ in
his crucifixion incarnated this process "with the aim of showing
that this stone has always formed a concealed foundation. And now the
stone is revealed and can no longer form a foundation, or rather it will
found something that is radically different" (Girard, 1978, p.
178). But how would this "something that is radically
different" operate epistemologically?
First, an epistemology of love would be non-authoritarian. No
perspective, either inside or outside the socially constructed
manifestations of the church or any other cultural institution, could
serve as the final, definitive mediator for identifying which objects of
knowledge should be desired. Any perspective attempting to do that would
become an oppressive internal mediator and the source of destructive
conflict. An epistemology of love would instead require Truth as the
Infinitely external final mediator. This "future objectivity"
would require an attempt first to see and love God and then an attempt
to see how God in Truth sees and loves all "neighbors." In
pointing us to the needs of our neighbors, God would direct our
knowledge to the appropriate objects of our desire. The seeing of God
would thus become the metaperspective of Truth. This metaperspective
would "hover" above all other perspectives, and would serve as
the standard against which they all would be evaluated. For each
community of understanding, the task would be to socially construct
arguments and evidence that moved its necessarily finite perspective
relatively closer to but always still far away from the Infinite Truth
of God. Progress presumably would be obvious in the ability of a
community to show greater and greater love for neighbors.
Second, an epistemology of love would be critical and appropriately
practice a hermeneutics of suspicion (Ricoeur, 1970). Seeing Truth
occurs "through a glass darkly" (I Corinthians 13:12), and any
claim to have a perfect ability to see Truth without ever missing the
mark would be self-deceptive (1 John 1:8). Truth also would make it
possible to understand how perspectives maintain their own solidarity
through "rituals" of epistemological scapegoating. In other
words, the foundations of all socially constructed perspectives
presumably rest upon rejected stones, but these perspectives then build
and maintain themselves through their own scapegoating rejections. At
least some of these rejections could produce a blindness that caused a
perspective to stumble over the rejected stones of other perspectives.
The task would be to develop methodologies for shining Light on the
darkness produced by our own inadequacies in seeing and by our own
epistemological scapegoating wherever it might occur.
Finally, an epistemology of love would be integrative. Like
communities generally, all perspectives presumably use epistemological
scapegoating to produce periods of peaceful solidarity during which
meaningful discoveries and innovations can occur. Different communities
of understanding may have made the same or similar discoveries and not
know it. And each perspective may have developed unique insights that
need to be tested and made available to other communities. An
epistemology of love would be open to closer approximations of Truth
wherever they might occur. The task would be to develop methodologies
for uniting perspectives through their tested and warranted insights
into Truth.
In short, an epistemology of love would be non-authoritarian,
critical, and integrative. Or to say the same thing differently, an
epistemology of love would be nonviolent. An authoritarian perspective
would promote power arrangements of internal mediation that led
inexorably to violence. A non-critical perspective would be complicit with the violence of scapegoating. And a non-integrative perspective
would tacitly reinforce boundaries between communities that would
encourage scapegoating and rivalries of violent internal mediation.
Again, in agreement with Nietzsche, an epistemology of love would be all
about seeing, but seeing with a mimetic gaze focused on the Prince of
Peace. This would be the stable foundation for socially constructing a
linear history of loving intelligibility that could understand the rise
and fall of all the rejected stones of cyclical history. Upon this Rock,
rejected stones that sought to approach Truth could be joined in the
construction of a Church of Understanding. Or to say the same thing in
more explicitly Christian terms, an epistemology of love would
"love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your
soul, and with all your mind" (by first seeking "to see
Truth") and then would "love your neighbor as yourself"
(by building a "Church of Understanding").
PSYCHOLOGY AND RELIGION WITHIN AN IDEOLOGICAL SURROUND
Any claim that an epistemology of love can develop in only one way
would be authoritarian and self-refuting. An example may nevertheless
appear in the ideological surround model of psychology and religion
(Watson, 1993, 1994), Central to this model is the acceptance of
perspectivism as an accurate description of life in pluralistic
societies. In such societies, conflicts among perspectives can justify
the use of power to maintain order by some regime of understanding.
Order maintained by power ultimately rests upon a foundation of violence
and scapegoating (John 11: 49-50) and represents a temptation that is
incompatible with order maintained by Love (Matthew 4: 8-10). A Church
of Understanding would in Truth love all perspectives and would attempt
to reform all forms of understanding based upon power. The practical
problem, however, will be that none of the available perspectives will
"see" everything and so will make observations based upon a
limited view. But any particular perspective also might have a unique
line of sight for making otherwise unavailable discoveries. Legitimate
discoveries invariably will be framed within a surround of limitations.
For the findings of all perspectives, the task will be to determine what
is wheat and what is chaff (Jeremiah 23:28). Some progress toward that
goal may be possible by framing all perspectives within an ideological
surround.
As defined by MacIntyre (1978), an ideology has three elements. It
first "attempts to delineate certain general characteristics of
nature or society or both, characteristics which do not belong only to
particular features of the changing world which can be investigated only
by empirical inquiry" (MacIntyre, p. 5). Christianity is
ideological in that "the God-created and God-maintained character
of the world is just such a characteristic" (pp. 5-6). Such claims
cannot be falsified, yet countless empirical observations can be
assimilated within the ideology. Second, an ideology has normative
elements that explain "the relationship between what is the case
and how we ought to act, between the nature of the world and that of
morals, politics, and other guides of conduct" (p. 6). As read by
Girard, for example, the Bible tells us "what is the case"
about human desire and how we should respond to that reality. Finally,
an ideology "is not merely believed by the members of a given
social group, but believed in such a way that it at least partially
defines for them their social existence" (p. 6). There is "a
Christian account of why Christians are Christians and the heathens are
not" (p. 6). In short, the ideological surround model assumes that
all psychological knowledge about religion (and all religious knowledge
about psychology) is sociological, normative, and somewhat
(non)empirical. These assumptions have three most important practical
implications.
First, within an ideological surround, no perspective can justify
the arbitrary use of power to exert a dominating control over the
creation of knowledge about psychology and religion. Nietzsche's
critiques have made it possible to see that all perspectives are
limited. For Christians working in this area, this means liberation from
the domination of modernism. A modernist therapeutic perspective, for
instance, may only see pathology in religious beliefs about sin. Within
a Christian ideological surround, however, it may be possible to see and
to begin describing empirically a dialectic between sin and grace that
promotes self-synthesis and well-being (e.g., Watson, Morris, &
Hood, 1988a, 1988b). In this and countless other sociological,
normative, and somewhat (non)empirical concerns, all relevant insights
and methodologies can be used to socially construct a Christian
psychology for use in Christian communities (Roberts, 2000).
Second, research within an ideological surround requires
methodologies that can unmask the limitations in what a perspective can
see, including those limitations associated with epistemological
scapegoating. Diverse techniques for accomplishing that purpose have
been developed (Watson, 1993, 1994). Within an existential ideological
surround, for example, authentic selfhood can seem to demand a rejection
of traditional religion. Researchers working within that surround
created a 36-item scale for measuring personal tendencies to avoid
existential concerns, and correlations confirmed that religious
commitments predicted a refusal to confront the difficult existential
realities of life. A rational analysis of the scale, nevertheless,
revealed that three items expressed this avoidance in explicitly
religious terms ("God exists," "there is much certainty
about the existence of God," and "it is quite certain what
happens after death"). A separate analysis of just those three
items demonstrated that they fully explained the relationship between
religious commitment and an avoidance of existential concerns. Results
for the full scale therefore had yielded the misleading tautological finding that religion correlated with religion. In this, an existential
perspective had stumbled over the rejected stone of religion (Watson,
Hood, & Morris, 1988).
Finally, research within an ideological surround would work from
the assumption that perspectives share and also have unique insights
that can be combined in broader systems of understanding. Standard
psychological frameworks and methodologies might be used to explore
commonalities between perspectives, even those that seem separated by
conflict (e.g., Ghorbani, Watson, Ghramaleki, Morris, & Hood, 2002;
Hood et al., 2001; Watson & Ghorbani, 1998). And special methods
also might be devised for promoting integration. Beliefs expressed in
the language of modernist psychology, for example, might be usefully
translated into the language of religion and vice versa (Dueck, 1995, p.
146; 2002). Empirical procedures for accomplishing that purpose have
been developed and used with Christian samples (e.g., Watson, Milliron,
Morris, & Hood, 1995). Such data document that translation is a real
possibility not limited to mere speculation.
In short, a metaperspective that saw psychology and religion within
an ideological surround would be non-authoritarian, critical, and
integrative. This model was developed with Christians, but would work
within any ideological surround. Any perspective could use methodologies
of self-articulation to bring itself closer to Truth. Any perspective
could unmask the scapegoating exclusions of its own and other
perspectives. And any perspective could explore opportunities for
integration. This is an "ideological surround" model, not a
"Christian" model. To call it "Christian" would for
non-Christians be authoritarian and self-refuting. Indeed, such a label
would be a stumbling stone over which many would trip, especially in
light of the historical scandals of "Christian" scapegoating
(for example, in pogroms, crusades, inquisitions, witch burnings, and
ethnic cleansings).
The ideological surround model, nevertheless, remains faithful to
premodern Christian traditions that have unmasked scapegoating and have
made a nonviolent perspectivism possible. The model also would conserve
the clear achievements of modernist scientific methodologies. Those
methodologies would not be used to defend the implicit internal
mediation of an objectivist epistemology, but instead would serve as a
safeguard against authoritarianism. Any community could use the Truth of
reliable and valid modernist methods to defend itself against the
oppressive use of power by other perspectives. Science in this way would
promote a democratization of perspectives and thus would respond to the
realities of postmodern pluralism. The ideological surround model, in
other words, would meet the "postpostmodern" integrative
challenge of articulating a new position that attempts to be faithful to
premodern Christian traditions, that preserves widely appreciated
modernist achievements, and that remains appropriately sensitive to the
realities of postmodern pluralism. The model would be Christian in its
origins, and this could be a stone over which much stumbling is
inevitable (Romans 9: 30-33). Still, the ultimate hope would be to
socially construct the loving intelligibility of a Church of
Understanding.
PSYCHOLOGY, HELL, AND SATAN
Because of its rejection of Enlightenment interpretations of
rationality, the ideological surround model has been described as a
postmodern approach to psychology and religion (Wulff, 1997, pp. 11-12).
Carrette (2001), nevertheless, argues that the model is insufficiently
responsive to the post-structuralist insights of a "critical
psychology" that unmask the role of power in social life (e.g.,
Foucault, 1980). A failure to be critical "maintains the oppressive
and prejudicial models inherent within psychological theory"
(Carrette, p. 113). The "task is to recognize that the future of
the psychology of religion will be found in the history of its
omissions, its denials, in the forgotten and the feared, in the return
to hell" (Carrette, p. 123).
But any meaningful return to hell should take hell seriously.
"Dionysus versus the Crucified" was another way that Nietzsche
explained his perspective (Girard, 1996). In attempting to become
Overmen, humanity should reject the Crucified Jesus and should instead
follow the pagan god Dionysus. But as Girard (2001) warns, "Before
placing too much confidence in Nietzsche, our era should have meditated
on one of the most sharp and brilliant sayings of Heraclitus:
'Dionysus is the same thing as Hades'" (p. 120). A
critical psychology that returns to hell with only a Nietzschean
understanding of power can only bring more hell into hell.
At least, this is one possible reading of a centrally important
question: "How can Satan cast out Satan?" Jesus asks this
question in response to an accusation that he has the power to cast out
demons because he himself is possessed by a demon. Jesus then adds,
"If a kingdom is divided against itself, that kingdom cannot
stand" (Mark 3: 23-24). From the perspective of his accusers, this
apparently was a successful defense. Jesus could not be possessed. Satan
would never cast out Satan because his kingdom could not stand.
A Girardian reading of this situation suggests something strikingly
different (Girard, 2001, pp. 34-43), and begins with a realization that
the word "Satan" in its Hebrew origins refers to "the
accuser." A cyclical history of Satan casting out Satan is
precisely how Satan's kingdom stands. With its mimetic gaze missing
the mark of Truth, a community at peace will fall into frustration and
rivalry. The situation will become increasingly "satanic" as
social solidarity collapses into escalating accusations, especially
against the power that serves as the mediator of the group. The
community then will be trapped in a mimetically-driven, self-reinforcing
spiral of violence. In some instances, the controlling power will
finally protect itself by using an effective gesture of accusation that
models a discharge of violence against a convenient scapegoat. Caiaphas
suggested the process when he said that "it is expedient ... that
one man die for the people, and that the whole nation should not
perish" (John 11:50). Sometimes, however, the finally successful
gesture will be directed against the controlling power itself. "But
no one can enter a strong man's house and plunder his goods, unless
he first binds the strong man; then indeed he may plunder his
house" (Mark 3:27). In other words, the power arrangements of one
murderous regime of understanding can bind up and plunder the power
arrangements of another. Satan can replace Satan.
So when Jesus is accused of being possessed by a demon, why does he
not speak more clearly? Why does he not say to his accusers that in
their accusations they are being satanic? But Jesus knows that his
accusers are not in submission to Truth. From their perspective, Jesus
is not a model of Infinitely external Truth. In such circumstances,
difficult Truth is often best expressed in a parabolic way. Relative to
his accusers, Jesus is a subject in rivalry to their own socially
constructed model of good and evil. Jesus cannot speak obviously to them
without taking his eyes off Truth, seeing truth from their perspective,
and becoming ensnared in a trap of internal mediation. Or to say the
same thing differently, to resist evil is to take evil as a model
(Matthew 5: 39). To accuse an accuser of accusing is in fact an
accusation that takes the accuser as a model. To call someone Satan in a
spirit of condemnation is to participate in the life of Satan.
And now, a critical psychology that returns to hell needs to answer
some questions. Will there not be as many critical psychologies as there
are perspectives? Given the inevitable absence of a perfect vision of
Truth, will not the limitations of each perspective serve as the
legitimate object of accusation by other perspectives? Will not a
critical psychology therefore collapse into the very thing it critiques?
Will not the dominating power of one critical psychological regime of
understanding merely replace the dominating power of another, and so on
without end? Each question will be followed by an affirmative response
within at least some ideological surrounds and will also lead to one
more question. How can a critical psychology cast out a critical
psychology? If an epistemology is divided against itself, that
epistemology cannot stand. But, of course, that epistemology can stand,
but will be trapped in the cyclical dynamics of a "return to
hell." The task instead will be to see and to return to hell from
the metaperspective of heaven.
From the metaperspective of heaven, any criticism of critical
psychology could not be made in a spirit of condemning accusation, but
would find it necessary to explain the "foundations" of
critical psychology. The sincere (and surreptitious) prayer of critical
psychology is to ensure that psychology does not ignore "the
forgotten and the feared" in attempting to maintain its
"disciplinary and political amnesia about foundational
questions" (Carrette, p. 123, p. 113). Behind this attempt to see
"things hidden since the foundation of the world" is a desire
for the liberation of humanity from oppression. But where in the social
construction of this epistemology was the founding model that pointed
toward this object of desire? A Girardian answer to that question is
found in the Holy Spirit, or parakletos of the Greek Bible. "The
principal meaning of parakletos is 'lawyer for the defense,'
'defender of the accused'" (Girard, 2001, pp. 189-190).
Against the accusations of Satan, Truth sent the Holy Spirit as a
defender. Within the linear history of human liberation, it is the
Defender that speaks Truth to the powers of accusation and attempts to
bring heaven into hell.
In other words, critical psychology has inherited the
demythologizing metaperspective of the Bible. Again, in Girardian terms,
a myth is the story of a murder told from the self-exonerating
perspective of the murderers. "Myth" is based on the Greek
word meaning "to close" or "to keep secret":
In the New Testament, mythos is juxtaposed to ... aletheia ... the Greek
word for truth. Aletheia comes from the root letho, which is the verb
'to forget.' The prefix a is negative. The literal meaning, then of the
Greek word for truth, aletheia, is 'to stop forgetting.' It is
etymologically the opposite of myth. (Bailie, 1995, p. 33)
Where critical psychology seeks to unmask "the forgotten and
the feared" and to overcome a "disciplinary and political
amnesia about foundational questions," the task is to overcome myth
with Truth. And how is this possible? Truth sends the Defender to
introduce evidence that makes it impossible to forget.
Only through the Defender, therefore, will a critical psychology be
able to avoid bringing more hell into hell. Sometimes the accusations of
cyclical human history will be hidden in closed regimes of understanding
that cannot see the secrets of their own sacrificial systems of
self-protection. Sometimes the accusations will be stated in more
explicit indictments like "only we are good and they are
evil." But the Defender will always find ways to cross-examine all
accusers: "In your own socially constructed language, you see the
defendant as evil. But do you not see how the defendant uses his own
socially constructed language to explain how he is truly good in many
important ways?" A second line of questioning will begin, "Of
course, it is True that the defendant falls short of Infinite Truth and
is good in only some ways. Some evil undoubtedly can be seen there. But,
is it possible that the log in your own eye has blinded you to the evils
that you share with all defendants?" And a third and final line of
evidence will begin, "Do you not see that the defendant's
socially constructed understanding of good expresses many of the same
goods that have been socially constructed within your own regime of
understanding?" The Defender, in other words, will be
non-authoritarian, critical, and integrative.
DISCIPLES OF TRUTH AFTER POSTMODERNISM
"Future objectivities" after postmodernism presumably
will be trapped within great conflicts. From one perspective, the task
will be to prove that modernism has already solved the problems of good
and evil. Through modernist reason, humanity has reached an "end of
history" in the sense that it is now impossible to discover any
fundamental cultural innovations that can improve social life. Reason
affords modernist societies with insurmountable economic and military
advantages, and modernist democratic reforms have at long last satisfied
the basic human desire to be desired (Fukuyama, 1992). Marxist,
feminist, fundamentalist, and countless other perspectives will
undoubtedly join the coming conflicts over the mediation of human
desire.
Within a Christian ideological surround, the situation after
postmodernism may be like stories we have heard before. Actually, these
stories can and should be remembered and retold in countless ways (e.g.,
Roberts, 2000). Only a reflective, reassertion of Truthful stories can
avoid an irrelevant or potentially dangerous "ghettoization"
of thought. Each retelling of these stories will, of course, be from a
particular perspective and as a consequence will be incomplete and
limited. Moreover, any story of Truth that even implicitly sought to
mediate all others stories would be authoritarian and self-refuting.
Within that context, a Girardian retelling of stories might be useful.
After postmodernism, everyone freed by the Defender will repeatedly
share a banquet honoring Truth. The table will be increasingly large and
around it will be seated all kinds of self-professed disciples of truth,
even those whose (surreptitious) Truth is that there is no truth. These
disciples will never really be like gods, fully knowing good and evil.
The Truth will always be Infinitely above them and difficult to see.
Because of this difficulty, Truth will encourage all disciples to
practice non-sacrificial methodologies of liberation. These
"rituals" should help all disciples to see and to remember
Truth.
But disciples will be seated around an increasingly crowded table.
The growing crowd plus the distance from Truth will make it easier for
the mimetic gaze of all to drift toward other disciples. From their own
perspective, all disciples will begin to make comparisons that lead them
to the (often surreptitious) accusation that they alone are closest to
Infinite Truth. Each will be trapped in a scandal of escalating
accusations. Each will assert with increasing anger and frustration
against all others, "They are guilty. I alone am good."
Everyone will begin to behave as if they were freed from prison in order
to throw everyone else into prison. All will forget that there are many
rooms with many perspectives in the house of Truth.
Betrayals of Truth will necessarily follow. Out of the conflict,
Truth will be dragged before dominant powers and demands will be made
for answers to a question, "What is truth?" The answer will be
incarnated in a crucifixion in which Truth looks down on a cyclical
history of lies. From this metaperspective, there will be no
condemnation. No accusations will be made, just the prayer of a
passionate will to loving forgiveness. After this crucifixion, Truth
will be resurrected so that lies will not be remembered and disciples
will stop forgetting. This will happen again and again.
The Defender will shepherd this process across time in a linear
history of loving intelligibility that frees humanity from prisons of
murderous intelligibility. Through the dynamics of liberation, the
banquet will get larger and larger. In the growing crowd, disciples
increasingly will be distracted in their mimetic gaze. Betrayals of
Truth will come with more frequent and depressing regularity. Even in
this dangerous situation, Truth will refuse to tell lies. The Defender
will work without rest. Witnesses to Truth will be called to testify.
Murderous mechanisms of social solidarity will be unmasked. Previously
scapegoated models of desire will be released. Social life will expand
in a confusion of models. The mimetic gaze of all will increasingly miss
the mark. Desires will be inflamed. Rivalries, accusations,
frustrations, and violence will spread. Lost in a blinding hate of
accusations, disciples will stumble toward a war of all against all in a
spirit of anti-Truth.
Crisis after crisis will recur. "Crisis" in its Greek
origins refers to "a separating" and "a decision."
Turning-point after turning-point will come in separating decisions, as
between sheep and goats. But because of the unmasking sacrifice of the
Scapegoat, the pattern will increasingly be too obvious to be effective.
No longer will it be possible to resolve any more crises through the
sacrifice of any more goats (Girard, 1986; cf. Girard, 1972, pp. 39-67).
History will proceed toward the logical conclusions of anti-Truth. The
blindness of hate will stumble toward apocalyptic discharge.
Cycles of lies will eventually culminate in the violent crisis of a
Final Trial. A death penalty for all could be the final sentence. The
hand of Truth will then be upon faithful disciples and will lead them
into the middle of a valley. The valley will be full of dry bones. Free
to really see for the first time, each in amazement will say, "I
had not thought death had undone so many" (Eliot, 1922/1952, p.
39). Truth will respond, "Prophesy to these bones and say to them,
O dry bones hear the word of the Lord ... Behold I will cause breath to
enter you and you shall live" (Ezekiel 37:4, 5; cf. Girard, 1978,
446-447). And the Word of the Lord will literally be the only Way out of
the blindness of hate into the seeing that is possible only in the Light
of Love. No secret knowledge, no socially constructed rationality will
ever substitute for a mimetic gaze that sees the only Truth that is
capable of showing how each must take the well-being of all as the
object of desire. Under the influence of the Defender, a "not
guilty" verdict will at long last come back in a decision that
separates history from its own past. At the Grace of the True end of
history, all of the psychologies of hell will be transformed into the
psychology of a new heaven and a new earth.
REFERENCES
Bailie, G. (1995). Violence unveiled. New York: Crossroad.
Carrette, J. R. (2001). Post-structuralism and the psychology of
religion: The challenge of critical psychology. In D. Jonte-Pace &
W.B. Parsons (Eds.), Psychology and religion: Mapping the terrain (pp.
110-126). London: Routledge.
Castelli, E. A. (1991). Imitating Paul. Louisville, KY:
Westminster/John Knox Press.
Clark, M. (1990). Nietzsche on truth and philosophy. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Dueck, A. C. (1995). Between Jerusalem and Athens. Grand Rapids,
MI: Baker Books.
Eliot, T. S. (1952). The wasteland. In T.S. Eliot, The complete
poems and plays: 1909-1950 (pp. 37-55). New York: Harcourt, Brace, and
World. (Original work published 1922)
Erickson, M. J. (2001). Truth or consequences. Downers Grove, IL:
InterVarsity Press.
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge. New York: Pantheon Books.
Fukuyama, F. (1992). The end of history and the last man. New York:
Avon Books.
Girard, R. (1965). Deceit, desire, and the novel. Baltimore, MD:
The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Girard, R. (1972). Violence and the sacred. Baltimore, MD: The
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Girard, R. (1978). Things hidden since the foundation of the world.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Girard, R. (1986). The scapegoat, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Girard, R. (1996). Nietzsche versus the crucified. In J.G. Williams
(Ed.), The Girard reader (pp. 243-261). New York: Crossroad Publishing.
Girard, R. (2001). I see Satan fall like lightening. Maryknoll, NY:
Orbis Books.
Ghorbani, N., Watson, P. J., Ghramaleki, A. F., Morris, R. J.,
& Hood, R. W., Jr. (2002). Muslim-Christian Religious Orientation Scales: Distinctions, correlations, and cross-cultural analysis in Iran
and the United States. The International Journal for the Psychology of
Religion, 12, 73-95.
Hood, R. W., Jr., Ghorbani, G., Watson, P. J., Ghramaleki, A. F.,
Bing, M. N., Davison, H. K., et al. (2001). Dimensions of the Mysticism Scale: Confirming the three-factor structure in the United States and
Iran. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 40, 691-705.
Johnson, E. L., & Jones, S. L. (2000). Finding one truth in
four views. In E. L. Johnson & S. L. Jones (Eds.), Psychology and
Christianity (pp. 243-265). Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Kvale, S. (1992). Postmodern psychology: A contradiction in terms?
In S. Kvale (Ed.), Psychology and postmodernism (pp. 31-57). London:
Sage.
MacIntyre, A. (1978). Against the self-images of the age. Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality? Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1992). The communist manifesto. New
York: Bantam Books. (Original work published in 1848)
Middleton, J. R., & Walsh, B. J. (1995). Truth is stranger than
it used to be. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1967). On the genealogy of morals. In W. Kaufman
(Ed.) On the genealogy of morals and ecce homo (pp. 15-163). New York:
Vintage Books. (Original work published in 1887)
O'Connor, K. V. (2001). What is our present? An antipodean perspective on the relationship between "psychology" and
"religion." In D. Jonte-Pace & W.B. Parsons (Eds.),
Psychology and religion: Mapping the terrain (pp. 75-93). London:
Routledge.
Oden, T. C. (1995a). The death of modernity and postmodern
evangelical spirituality. In D.D. Dockery (Ed.), The challenge of
postmodernism (pp. 19-33). Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books.
Oden, T. C. (1995b). So what happens after modernity? A postmodern
agenda for evangelical theology. In D. D. Dockery (Ed.), The challenge
of postmodernism (pp. 392-406). Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books.
Ricoeur, P. (1970). Freud and philosophy. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Roberts, R. C. (2000). A Christian psychology view. In E.L. Johnson
& S.L. Jones (Eds.), Psychology and Christianity (pp. 148-177).
Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
Rosenau, P. M. (1992). Post-modernism and the social sciences.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Stout, J. (1988). Ethics after Babel. Boston: Beacon Press.
Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis. New York: Free Press.
Watson, P. J. (1993). Apologetics and ethnocentrism: Psychology and
religion within an ideological surround. The International Journal for
the Psychology of Religion, 3, 1-20.
Watson, P. J. (1994). Changing the religious self and the problem
of rationality. In T. M. Brinthaupt & R. P. Lipka (Eds.), Changing
the self. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Watson, P. J. (1998). Girard and integration: Desire, violence, and
the mimesis of Christ as foundation for postmodernity. Journal of
Psychology and Theology, 26, 311-321.
Watson, P. J., & Ghorbani, N. (1998). Ravanshenasi din dar
javame Moslemin. [Psychology of religion in Muslim society.] Qabasat, 3
(2,3), 52-71. (In Persian)
Watson, P. J., Hood, R. W., Jr., & Morris, R. J. (1988).
Existential confrontation and religiosity. Counseling and Values, 33,
47-54.
Watson, P. J., Milliron, J. T., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W.,
Jr. (1995). Religion and the self as text: Toward a Christian
translation of self-actualization. Journal of Psychology and Theology,
23, 180-189.
Watson, P. J., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W., Jr. (1988a). Sin
and self-functioning, Part 1: Grace guilt, and self-consciousness.
Journal of Psychology and Theology, 16, 254-269.
Watson, P. J., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W., Jr. (1988b). Sin
and self-functioning, Part 2: Grace, guilt, and psychological
adjustment. Journal of Psychology and Theology, 16, 370-381.
Webber, R. E. (1999). Ancient-future faith. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker
Books.
Williams, J. G. (2001). Forward. In R. Girard, I see Satan fall
like lightening (pp. ix-xxiii). Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books.
Wulff, D. (1997). Psychology of religion: Classic and contemporary.
Second Edition. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
P.J. WATSON
University of Tennessee at Chattanooga
AUTHOR
WATSON, P.J. Address: Psychology/Department #2803, 350 Holt
Hall-615 McCallie Avenue, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga,
Chattanooga, TN 37403 Title: University of Chattanooga Foundation
Professor of Psychology. Degrees: BA, University of Texas at El Paso;
PhD, University of Texas at Arlington. Specializations: Psychology and
religion; personality theory; and cross-cultural psychology.
Correspondence concerning this article may be sent to P.J. Watson,
Psychology/Department #2803, 350 Holt Hall-615 McCallie Avenue,
University of Tennessee at Chattanooga, Chattanooga, TN 37403. Email:
paul-watson@utc.edu