"Like a Balcony": the philosophical text within the poetic metaphor.
Karaki, Balqis Al-
"Like a house's balcony, I overlook whatever I
desire." At first glance, this line by the late Palestinian poet
Mahmud Darwish may not seem to bear multiple or complex meanings. A
daring attempt at interpretation, however, can show that this simple
metaphor is capable of bearing and provoking various philosophical
ideas. To achieve this end, the interpretation invites the ideas of
several theorists of metaphor and imagery, including Bachelard, Derrida,
Heidegger, Ricoeur, Nietzsche, and Deleuze, in approaching Darwish.
I. Justifying the Imposition
"Metaphor is less in the philosophical text ... than the
philosophical text within metaphor" (Derrida 258). This bold,
intriguing statement by Derrida may be valid if we keep in mind that for
a philosophical text to exist within a metaphor, a certain type of
reading experience is required in order to find or create the
philosophical text. The subject of this article is Mahmud Darwish's
poem "'Ara shabahi qadiman min ba'id' (I see my
ghost coming from afar) (Limadha 11-15), which is widely referred to by
its first line: "'Utillu ka shurfati baytin 'ala ma
'uricT (Like a house's balcony, I overlook whatever I desire).
(1) Among the desirable things the subject of the poem looks out on are:
his friends holding the evening mail, a seagull, troop trucks, a
neighbor's dog, the name of the Arab poet al-Mutanabbi, a Persian
flower, trees, wind, ancient prophets, his image, words in the Arabic
dictionary, the Persians, the Romans, the Sumerians, the new refugees, a
crushed necklace of one of Tagore's poor women, a hoopoe, the
supernatural world, his language, his frightened body, and, finally, his
"ghost coming from afar." The poem is quite popular among
those interested in Arabic poetry, yet such admiration may have nothing
to do with potential philosophical dimensions that can be uncovered in
an analytic reading.
Darwish published this poem in 1995, and read it numerous times
across the world until his death in 2008. Several YouTube videos of
Darwish reciting the poem are available, with a total view count of
approximately 35,000. In the middle of this performance, Darwish
received a loud applause as he read:
I overlook the procession of the ancient prophets
As they climb barefoot to Jerusalem
And I ask: Is there a new prophet
For this new time? (13)
One can easily argue that the reason for this applause is simply
the political context. This may be true, but one must keep in mind that
no other Palestinian poet, no matter how politically oriented his poems
are, has received similar appreciation for his poetry. Thus there must
be something in Darwish's poetry--something besides the political
element--that draws this attention. As regards this poem, one can
endlessly go looking for aesthetic reasons to justify this appreciation.
One can claim, for example, that the poem's music is behind its
"beauty"; that the poem is appreciated because some of its
images are novel and unfamiliar; or that it is able to move the audience
because it touches upon some common human concerns. These and other
reasons which can be drawn from the wide literature of literary
criticism may be correct in part, but may also be "fantastic
creations" as well: "... where one did not know how to explain
one learned to create," Nietzsche reminds us (Daybreak 27). And as
it is probably impossible to come up with a prescription for writing a
poem that will be appreciated with such a degree of "subjective
universality" (to use Kant's terms) or
"transsubjectivity" (to use Bachelard's), the real,
complete set of reasons and causes behind this appreciation will remain
inaccessible, or at least very difficult to put together accurately
without serious reduction.
As in other artistic performances, no one among the members of the
audience seems to have brought a pen and paper to Darwish's
recital. This is because no one is there to interpret the poem, or to
attend a lesson in philosophy or a lecture in politics. They are there
to enjoy a certain aesthetic experience, and as to this poem, it is a
short event that takes less than five minutes. Whether the audience
members have read or heard this poem before is irrelevant: There is not
enough time anyway to turn this short experience into a careful act of
scholarly investigation. The closest description of this experience
seems to--still--be Kant's "pleasure without interest,"
or at least, the interest which Nietzsche admires in Stendhal's
description of the beautiful as "une promesse de Bonheur [a promise
of happiness]" (Genealogy 83).
Nonetheless, the two experiences--the short, seemingly effortless
encounter with the poem and the long effortful process of interpreting
it--are not entirely disconnected. For it often happens that the desire
for interpretation stems from a previous, short-lived experience of the
poem, i.e. reading or hearing it without a prior intention of
interpretation. It is because we briefly enjoyed a poem (or a piece of
music, or a painting) that we find ourselves desiring to work with it in
a non-passive fashion: either to try and find the reasons behind our
enjoyment, or to extract its possible meanings, or--as often happens--to
construct and impose the interpretation we prefer on the poem we liked
and enjoyed. Fortunately, we live in a time when being unfaithful to the
poet's intention is acceptable, and when an interpreter, unlike a
theological commentator, does not have to insist that his interpretation
is the original meaning of the text: The author is no God, not even
close.
But where does the desire to impose and exaggerate a poem's
meaning(s) come from? We know for example that the medieval theologians
had very good reasons for imposing a certain interpretation on their
holy texts. The Muslim theologians found it acceptable to read the words
"thing" and "be" in the Qur'an as bearing the
difficult philosophical problem of essence and existence. Christian
scholars who interpreted the occurrences of ladders, twigs, or rods in
the Old Testament as referring to Jesus's Cross did not consider
this an imposition. Nietzsche is known for attacking such
"dishonest," "impudent arbitrariness" and for
referring to such practice as "the art of reading badly"
(Daybreak 94). These may indeed be "bad readings" but not
because they are seemingly imposed from "outside" the text,
but because these interpreters did not know or admit that their
interpretation was not the original meaning of the text. In all cases,
they had serious wars to fight and which perhaps justified their need
for imposing a certain meaning. What is interesting is that such a
desire to impose, avowedly or not, does not require a persistent
theological need to exist. Does not Heidegger make Holderlin say what he
wants him to say? That is, he interprets Holderlin's poems in a way
that will make them helpful in explicating his own ideas about art and
history? In Holderlin's Hymn "The Ister," Heidegger even
denies that his reading is an "interpretation" in the
"strict sense of the word," but is only able to communicate
few "markers," or "remarks" on the poetry it has
selected, "signs that call our attention," and "pauses
for reflection" (2). For Heidegger, such remarks are "always
only" an "accompaniment," and are "simply imported
and are not even 'contained in' the poetry" (2). This
"accompaniment" for Heidegger is not an imposition, as the
poetry is still "present as what comes first" (2).
Deleuze and Guattari speak of the thinkers who are "'half
philosophers but also much more than philosophers" (Philosophy 67),
claiming that:
There is such force in those unhinged works of Holderlin,
Kleist, Rimbaud, Mallarme, Kafka, Michaux, Pessoa, Artaud,
and many English and American novelists, from Melville to
Lawrence or Miller, in which the reader discovers admiringly
that they have written the novel of Spinozism. (67)
In doing so, are they not imposing Spinozism--which Deleuze clearly
admires--on those literary works which they also admire? Is it not
possible to find or create traces of Plato, Descartes, or Nietzsche, for
example, in the works of those "half philosophers"? Will these
traces be "imported" from or "contained" in those
works of art?
Indeed, imposition and exaggeration seem to be much more inviting
than is faithfulness to the author's intention. In the case of
Darwish's poem, it would take a knowledgeable reader, one who is
interested in understanding the former's balcony poem within the
context of his entire poetic corpus, to craft a link between "I
overlook whatever I desire (or want) ['urid]" and, for
example: 1- Darwish's poem "Ruba'iyyai' (Quatrains)
where each stanza begins with "'Ara ma 'urid' (I see
what I want to see), and which is also the title of the entire
collection 'Ara ma 'urid (1990) (Diwan 377-86); 2-
Darwish's masterpiece Jidariyya (Mural), written in 1999, which
contains his famous line "sa-asiru yawman ma 'urid' (One
day I shall become what I want) (12-16); 3- Darwish's poem
"Lam yantazir ahadan" (He awaited no one), published in 2005,
where he writes: "And I escape an oppressive question: What do you
want. What do you want?" (Ka zahr allawz 33-35); 4- Outside the
sphere of Darwish's poetry, the devoted reader can add to his
intertextual reading Nizar Qabbani's poem "Rajul wahid'
(A Lonely Man) which famously begins: "Law kuntu a'rifu ma
'urid' (If I knew what I wanted) (n. pag.). The same reader
might also remember what Darwish said about the balcony in Dhakira
lil-nisyan (Memory for Forgetfulness): "The balcony is life's
attack on death. It is resisting the fear of war" (234). From this,
the faithful reader can move on to claim that the subject in
Darwish's poem wants to see or imagine certain things so as to
resist the fear of war, but he does not seem able to resist it
completely as he cannot escape seeing the trunks of the troops, and
wishing for a new prophet to come as savior, and so on.
The question is: Why does it not seem interesting, at least to some
readers such as the present author, to go along these somewhat safe and
riskless paths? It is probably due to something in those readers. Time,
some are happy to read or hear the poem, briefly share their experience
with others, praise the poet in passing, and move on. For others, the
desire to share their experience is far more persistent, and can
sometimes be governed by certain egoistic motives and feelings of envy
towards the poet. The stronger these desires, the harder it will be for
the interpreter to fulfill them, and perhaps becoming a "mere"
critic of, or a specialist in, the works of that particular poet may
also fail to do so. Such "ungratified" reader can go far and
try to find a role for himself, and mere enjoyment--something shared by
many--and mere commentary will not be sufficient to satisfy his pride.
And so after distancing himself from the original aesthetic experience,
he decides that he wants to become a creator himself rather than a mere
observer or faithful interpreter who is already in the worst of places:
right in the middle, neither a poet nor a philosopher. Therefore, when
this reader imposes an interpretation and it turns out to be good, it is
as if he is saying that he is no less brilliant than the poet. Indeed,
an interpreter can be credited for a good, post-performance
interpretation, but not for the capacity of the poem to be loved and
enjoyed at first reception. Thus "the reader's pride," as
Bachelard calls it (Space xxv), cannot be entirely satisfied if we agree
with Bachelard that the suggestive power of a poem--which allows for
multiple interpretations--is a credit to the poets, and because of this
"dynamism that belongs to suggestion," "the reader can go
farther, even too far" (53). In other words, if the interpreter
succeeds in forcefully extracting a good interpretation, it is not
because he has created it from scratch and later imposed it on a
metaphor or a poem, but rather because the metaphor has the
suggestiveness which allows him to construct that interpretation, or
simply because the "poem came first," to use Heidegger's
words. It is only if the interpretation proves to be somewhat better
than the poem to the extent that it can make a poem provoke a response
that it did not provoke before that interpretation, it is only then that
the reader's pride is fully justified and the interpretation can be
described as an instance of creation. If the poet's task is to
interpret the world poetically and create something astonishing from
normal and familiar words, the "proud" interpreter's task
becomes to create something even more astonishing with his raw material
being the poem itself.
Bachelard has a lot to say about the dynamism of an image which,
for him, can even exist in a single line (Space 11), and this seems to
apply to our line here: "Like a balcony, I overlook whatever I
desire." Bachelard encourages the reader to follow "the
positive impulse of exaggeration," because it has the benefit of
being interesting, free from the habits of reduction which is all too
"easy and commonplace": "The further one dares to go, the
more decent, the more personal, the more unique a life becomes"
(Space 219-20). Bachelard sees such daring reader as a
"phenomenologist":
He takes the image just as it is, just as the poet created it, and
tries to make it his own, to feed on this rare fruit. He brings the
image to the very limit of what he is able to imagine. However far from
being a poet he himself may be, he tries to repeat its creation for
himself and, if possible, continue its exaggeration. (Space 227)
The problem with Bachelard's characterization of the will to
exaggerate in The Poetics of Space is that it does not place the
"daring associations" at any conceptual level. It is true that
Bachelard insists that a poet can give us a "lesson in
philosophy" (185), that "we must listen to the poets"
(89), and even claims that philosophers themselves would learn much
"if they would consent to read the poets" (208). However,
Bachelard is not in favor of what he calls "intellectualizing the
experience" of reading, as he prefers not to attempt personal
interpretation but rather to experience poetry as a "daydream"
(see xvii, 17, and 218). He does not like the attempts that do not
indulge themselves enough with an image, i.e. those which translate what
is "believed to be" figurative language into reasonable
language (225). In other words, the exaggeration he calls for is an
exaggeration on the level of imagination, and the reduction he rejects
includes any attempt to interpret the image as a traditional lesson in
philosophy; i.e. a lesson which contains abstract concepts. An
interpreter looking for such lessons is for Bachelard "a reader
distorted by intellectualism who places abstract thoughts before
metaphor" and "who thinks that writing is looking for images
in order to illustrate thoughts" (Poetic Imagination 51). This is
because Bachelard's epistemology rejects the possibility of
synthesis or filiation between concept and image, and sees imagination
as a feminine "fog" and "smoke" which threatens the
"virility" of objective knowledge, while concepts which try to
give stability to an image "would stifle its existence" (5-7).
"I will not speak of my faithful love for images and then study
them with the help of a great array of concepts," he says, for
concepts and images should be loved "with two different
loves": one in daylight, the other at nighttime (6-7). For him,
poetic images should only be "lived," "experienced,"
"re-imagined," and allowed to "reverberate" in the
reader's consciousness (qtd. in Gaudin xli). Any commentary that is
not delicate enough threatens to "destroy the suggestive magic of
images" (lvii). In the poetic fold, Bachelard says, "reveries
replace thoughts and poems hide theorems" (4).
To be defending the possibility of translating a metaphor as
containing a philosophical text is to be in a position where one cannot
agree entirely--if at all--with Bachelard. However, it is still possible
to benefit from Bachelard's notion of exaggeration by widening its
field. Thus, one can argue that an exaggeration in interpreting the
image using an array of abstract concepts has the benefit of avoiding
the reduction of a faithful reading. It is also beneficial to keep in
mind Bachelard's idea that the dreamer is never passive, and that
dreams "reveal nothing to a lazy dreamer" (Gaudin xxvi,
xxviii). True, interpretation is a somewhat daylight activity, but one
can expand Bachelard's idea and argue that metaphor can reveal no
philosophical texts to a lazy, passive interpreter. Unlike daydreaming,
interpretation requires conceptual work as claimed by Ricoeur, whose
construal of interpretation may be added to Bachelard's to help
understand the philosophy of/within a metaphor. Ricoeur sees that
interpretation functions at the intersection of metaphorical and
speculative discourses: It "seeks the clarity of the concept"
but also "hopes to preserve the dynamism of meaning that the
concept holds and pins down" (303). He reads Kant's famous
claim that aesthetic ideas force our minds to "think more" as
meaning that the presentation of an idea by the imagination "forces
conceptual thought to think more" (303). And since he clearly
considers metaphor to be a form of such presentation, he states that
metaphor "introduces the spark of imagination into a 'thinking
more' at the conceptual level"; the "struggle to think
more" is the "soul of interpretation," Ricoeur adds
(303), which seems to encourage the intellectualization of the reading
practice rather than settling for a concept-free daydreaming experience.
But how exactly can the spark of imagination, in interpreting
metaphor, "think more" at the conceptual level? Analytical
philosophy, especially the famous thesis of Lakoff and Johnson,
Metaphors We Live By, has shown that through metaphors we
"think" because our conceptual systems are essentially
metaphorical. They regarded metaphors as part of "ordinary"
rather than "extraordinary" language only; i.e. they are not
confined to the realm of poetry and art. Since this article deals with a
poetic metaphor and argues that it can help us think more at a
conceptual level (a Kantian idea originally) leading to the formation of
a philosophical text (Derrida's phrasing), the focus on continental
philosophy appears to be justified. Through the applied part of this
article, I will argue that the philosophical lessons or texts available
within Darwish's balcony present themselves as dialogues between
philosophical lessons which we already know and the metaphor that can
bear them. In such dialogues, our minds will be forced to think more
about some philosophical ideas with the help of a new image. True, the
interpreter is not required to be a philosopher who creates concepts or
to prove that the poetry is similar or superior to philosophy, but, as
Deleuze and Guattari observe, philosophy, science, and art are all ways
of "thinking and creating" or "modes of ideation"
(Philosophy 8). Interpretation, then, can be seen as an interaction
between different modes of ideation. In this light, the poem, during the
process of interpretation, ceases to be merely a plane of "percepts
and affects," as Deleuze and Guattari see art (24), and as short
encounters with it may tell us. Rather, the poem becomes a plane where
percepts, affects, concepts, and even propositions come into the play of
forming associations. True, poetry and other arts do produce affects
which "surpass ordinary affections and perceptions, just as
concepts go beyond everyday opinion" (65), which is perhaps why the
desire for working more with the poem exists. However, just as Deleuze
and Guattari find both art and philosophy to be "Chaoids,"
i.e. modes of confronting chaos--art by creating affects and percepts
and throwing a plane of composition, and philosophy by creating concepts
and throwing a plane of immanence (197; 208)--we can say that
interpretation also tries to confront chaos though not only by
submitting to the affects of a poetic composition. Deleuze and Guattari
argue that chaos is not disorder as much as "the infinite speed
with which every form taking shape in it vanishes" (118).
And as the reader's first response to a poem is usually
characterized by an almost infinite speed with which any response or
quick interpretation that was produced soon vanishes, we can conjure
that the interpreter, like a philosopher and poet, also tries to fight
chaos. He fights the chaos of his own response to the poem, and through
interpretation, he tries to create some order to the way he receives a
poem, which requires establishing some degree of filiation between
concept and image, philosophy and poetry. Evidently, why the interpreter
would want to confront this particular chaos is due to a desire to
confront the greater chaos. He probably considers that the poem as
"chaoid' is too elastic and thus is in need of some
interpretive, philosophical work, one which can render the poem more
useful for such confrontation. It may be true that the artists are the
ones who, for Deleuze and Guattari, can be "hybrid geniuses"
in whose works the plane of immanence of philosophy and that of
composition of art can "slip into each other" to the degree
that "part of one may be occupied by entities of the other,"
and who can occupy a plane of immanence with instances other than
concepts, "poetic, novelistic, or even pictorial musical
entities" (66). But it is perhaps the task of the interpreter to
actualize the slipping of the philosophical plane into the poetic one,
and to help establish the status of poets as hybrid geniuses and
half-philosophers. Does not this apply, for example, to Heidegger's
disclosure of Holderlin's philosophical significance?
Certainly, rarely do readers of poetry get to become as important
as Heidegger. But at least they get to enjoy, during the process of
interpretation, a certain pleasure of forming associations, one that is
quite different from their first, almost passive, response to the poem.
The experience of interpretation involves a struggle to "think
more" within different "modes of ideation" where concepts
and images are not complete strangers, and where philosophy and poetry
are allowed to slip into one another. Perhaps this process can be richer
if the reader is allowed to slip in his own personal life as influenced
or re-interpreted by the poem and by his interpretation of the poem, but
this is something that is hardly--if ever-- acceptable in academic
writing.
To say that Darwish's balcony contains philosophical texts is
thus an attempt to show how an unorthodox interpretation of this
metaphor can enhance our ideas about philosophical lessons which we
already know. Although I will not argue that Darwish writes the poem of
Bachelardism, Heideggerism, Nietzscheism or Deleuzism, I will argue
that, as a "half philosopher," his metaphor allows the reader
to construct traces of some of the arguments of those thinkers. And
because it is in the end a metaphor and not an abstract concept, it can
both support and destabilize the lessons which we know, through a
dialogue that forces our minds to think more by trying to create new
correspondences between the metaphor and a possible philosophical idea.
The more accurate the correspondences, the more persuasive the
interpretation, and a new pleasure with interest can be born.
Darwish was not the first to use the balcony literally or
figuratively. Perhaps the most famous balcony in literature is
Juliet's balcony, and there is also Jean Genet's play Le
balcon; D. H. Lawrence's On the Balcony, Baudelaire's Le
balcon; Oscar Wilde's Under the Balcony; Lorca's
"Farewell" which begins: "If I die, leave the balcony
open"; Octavio Paz's El balcon; and al-Sayyab's simile in
"Hymn to the Rain": "Your eyes are two palm tree forests
in early light/Or two balconies from which the moonlight recedes"
as well as his poem "Shinashil ibnat al-Jalabi" (Enclosed
balcony of the nobleman's daughter). With Shakespeare's play,
the balcony became a symbol of love and of the anticipation of desire.
In Genet's play, the balcony is part of an artful house of
illusions, where secret theaters are formed for those who bring their
own scenarios and find satisfaction in mirrors and trickery.
Baudelaire's balcony is the "mother of memories" which
will remember the beauty of caresses, infinite kisses, perfumes, etc. In
Lorca's balcony, the subject can see the little boy eating oranges,
and the reaper harvesting the wheat, therefore it is dealt with
literally as a place from which one looks at things (and this is also
true for Lawrence's balcony). Wilde is "under the
balcony," speaking like Romeo of his love. The balcony of
al-Sayyab's Ibnat al-Jalabi is no longer there after thirty years,
and his desires to see her turn into "mere air, vanities, a plant
without fruit or flowers" (DeYoung 260). Paz's balcony is in
Delhi from which "he sees" things visible and invisible. The
latter can be regarded as a precursor to Darwish's balcony from
which he sees a crushed necklace of one of the poor women of the Indian
poet Tagore. Of course, each of these balconies deserves an independent
study and it is unfair to reduce their meanings to the summaries above.
What can be said, though, is that Darwish's "balcony"
is--at least as far as I know--the only balcony which is used as a
metaphor for a subject looking at things. He is not under a balcony, or
on a balcony, he is like a balcony. Because of this use, I find that the
metaphor contains a rich philosophical text that can be drawn from
distinctive features of the balcony, such as (1) its being immersed in
the "outside" although it is part of the "inside";
(2) its providing of a view of the world from a certain perspective; (3)
leading to the construction of certain desires. These three features
form the three philosophical subjects in Darwish's poem as will be
discussed in Part III, which is consequently divided into three
sections: Subject/Object Interaction, Perspectivism, and Desire. The
first section sets the metaphor in a dialogue with Bachelard and
Heidegger; the second with Nietzsche; and the third with Nietzcshe,
Deleuze, and Guattari.
Clearly, such interpretation is decontextual in nature and follows
the path of the theorists who welcomed some
"exaggeration"--imaginative and conceptual. And before going
forward with my reading of the metaphor, the next part of this article
(Part II) briefly explains how and why it clearly parts from most other
readings of the same poem or the same collection.
II. Darwish Criticism and The Need to Undress the Eye
In the acts of criticism and interpretation, it may be true that
one can never look at a text with a "naked eye." The poet is
never dead, neither is the geography and history of his text. And, as
has become all-too-known and generally accepted, the reader is
inevitably a participator in such text: in the construction of its
possible meanings and in its production of aesthetic and non-aesthetic
effects.
There is a problem of perspective, it seems, when it comes to
Darwish's criticism. As a general observation, it seems that this
criticism is not only unwilling to try and undress the critical eye, but
rather insists on overdressing it with Darwish's life and his
identity as a Palestinian. The titles of the works written on Darwish in
English often revolve around the following themes: "identity";
"resistance"; "Palestine"; "land" or
"homeland"; "exile"; "memory", and so on.
The quantity of such works is still incomparable to their counterparts
in the Arabic-writing worlds of academia and media, wherein Darwish has
been written about so extensively, and this "criticism" has
been ongoing in a ceaselessly reproductive fashion, especially after his
death in 2008. There is certainly much house-cleaning that needs to be
done in this regard before one can sketch a map for a so-called
"Darwish Criticism" in Arabic. Because of this, it may be
early to make confident claims regarding the viewpoints and value of
this criticism, even if certain observations seem to impose themselves
on a reader who tries to follow the increasing number of writings on
Darwish.
Among these observations, I will mention, with some caution, two
remarks that seem to apply to the criticism of Darwish's collection
Why Did You Leave the Horse Alone? which contains our balcony poem.
First, it seems that much of what has been written about this
collection, in Arabic and in English, departs from similar--if not
identical-standpoints. The latter can perhaps be summarized by what
Subhi Hadidi wrote on the back-cover of the collection published in
1995, where he stated that the Why Did You Leave the Horse Alone? is an
autobiography of Darwish's life and a biography of place as it
becomes "contained by geography so that history can spread in
it." The majority of articles contained in, for example, Mahmoud
Darwish: Exile's Poet that tackle the collection seem to depart
from the same perspective. Najat Rahman, for instance, discusses
Darwish's poem "'Ara ma 'urid'-a possible
intertext of our balcony poem-before moving on to his Why Did You Leave
the Horse Alone? She interprets the former as an attempt to
"create" a homeland by writing poetry which will become the
poet's "only guard" against the absence of his home (42).
She moves on to read Why Did You Leave the Horse Alone? through the lens
of home and history, and thus she chooses from the balcony poem the
lines which have strong political connotations (the same lines quoted
earlier on the need for a new prophet) (43). In her reading of both
texts, she relies on the idea that Darwish's poetry became "a
space for survival" after Beirut (42), which clearly shows that the
perspective of autobiography and biography of place, similar to
Hadidi's, is dressing (or perhaps overdressing) her reading. Fay
sal Darraj's reading of the collection is similarly contextual, and
he highlights the collection's difference from Darwish's
earlier works: "After thirty years of poetic experience, however,
Darwish's work came to depict truth, tragedy, and history. Tragedy
has remained, in the form of continued occupation, replacing the
certainty of liberation with its probability instead" (67).
This is not to say that such readings are incorrect or poor in
value. However, despite the fact that any attempt to understand each
poem in its proper context is definitely one interesting way of looking
at Darwish's poetry, it should not be the dominant approach to its
interpretation, let alone being the sole, almost exclusive, method.
Decontextualization, the approach of the present article, is an attempt
to free Darwish from seemingly overdressed critical eyes, and may thus
produce more interesting results, but only if it manages to render the
interpretation coherent and consistent--something which is perhaps
easier to achieve using contextual and intertextual approaches. Needless
to say, the two approaches can always enrich one another. For example,
Najat Rahman's notion of creating a homeland poetically may have
been richer, had she not restricted poetic creation to a quest for the
compensation of a lost land. For why would the subject in the balcony
poem "look over," in an attempt of creation as Rahman would
have it, "a woman basking in herself'? He looks at her
"ka shurfati bay tin," and "bayt" in Arabic means
both "house" and "hemistich"--a note which would
have enhanced Rahman's idea of creation and compensation, had it
been slightly freer from autobiography, for she would have certainly
found interest in other lines of the poem and examined other ways of
compensation through poetry at a more individual level as suggested by
the poem (the creation of a woman, friends, poetic ancestors). The
burden of context also seems to limit Darraj's reading which tries
to examine the transformation of the "self' throughout
Darwish's poetry, claiming that by the time the latter wrote
Limadha he had already departed from a "Romantic self' and
transformed into a non-Romantic, "poetic" one, thus Darraj
entitles the section where he discusses Limadha as "Homeland
Outside the Self' (67-74). The notion of "self' for
Darraj appears to be somewhat constrained in order to fit his political
perspective, and when this notion is applied to the balcony poem, it
will restrain, I think, the vast energy of the metaphor claimed in the
present article; i.e. its capacity to bear and problematize the
subject-object relation (including self-homeland interchange) at a
complex conceptual level. Still, when Darraj's reading is compared
to Hadidi's, especially in his use of "self," he will
seem far more thorough in his dealing with this concept and with
Darwish's text in general. From here, I will move to my second
remark on the criticism of Darwish's collection under question: the
problem of concept and of critical language.
Even more than twenty years after Hadidi's initial
identification of Limadha with autobiography (in "Dama 'ir
Mahmud Darwish")--an identification that is not as problematic as
the language of Arabic criticism mentioned above--some critics are still
reading the collection and its poems through the same eye using the same
writing style. Fakhri Salih, for instance, discusses Limadha in a
section entitled "Shibh sira dhatiyya" (A quasi-autobiography)
(139). He states that in this collection, Darwish "refurnishes his
poem with the primary elements using the child's memory to look
over the spatio-temporal sphere which witnessed the cry of the narrator
in the poem" (139). It is again the perspective of autobiography
and biography of place that shapes his reading twenty years after this
claim was first made. Like Hadidi, he writes that the title of the
balcony poem "emphasizes the element of birth observed through the
eye of the subject [dhat] in an imminent temporal sphere" (139).
Again, an overdressed critical eye is stubbornly shaping the criticism
of this collection in Arabic until this moment, and it is also evident
that Salih's writing style and use of concepts bear the same
problems of Hadidi's. The former's discussion of the balcony
poem begins by noting that the poet in the first lines of the poem uses
a simile that "implies stillness and a view of the surrounding
place. . . . The world is thus exposed in an explicit way [safira]
before the eye that observes, but this observed world soon transforms
into a scene looked at through the inner eye of the narrator-poet"
(140). And without discussing the particulars of the metaphor any
further, Salih decides to classify the looked-at elements in
past-present categories, in order to defend his interpretation of
"I see my ghost coming from afar" as "a journey of the
memory in the past of the self [dhat] and a recapturing of the details
of the absent time and place" (140).
It is surprising how the balcony of Darwish criticism in Arabic and
English fails, even after twenty years of the publication of Limadha, to
look out on newer things in this poem, and insists on rendering an
overdressed eye, and sometimes using difficult concepts inattentively,
which results in failure to evoke a new interest in the poem. My reading
of the balcony metaphor in "I see my ghost coming from
afar" in the following part (III) claims to both undress the
metaphor to explore its possible productiveness of philosophical ideas
such as (Subject/Object interaction, Perspectivism, and notions of
Desire) as well as treat each concept that converses with the metaphor
with the necessary caution in order to render the interpretation valid,
coherent, and insightful.
III. The Philosophical Text
III. A. Subject/Object Interaction
"Like a balcony, I overlook whatever I desire." The
subject is merely like a balcony, and so, from the very outset of
interpretation, any understanding of "subject" drawn from this
metaphor will be "charged with hesitation," as Bachelard would
say (Space 222). This is because "like" also signifies
"is not," but not "the same," as Ricoeur tells us
(7). Such "tension" between "identity and difference in
the interplay of resemblance" (247) reminds us that any meaning
concerning the subject that we can draw from the features of the balcony
will remain far from becoming a definition of "subject,"
because the balcony is an object that will never be the "same"
as the human subject.
Clive Cazeaux calls for an epistemological metaphor or family of
metaphors which can "articulate the relation between subject and
object in a way which does not repeat the internal-external
dichotomy" (150). He argues that such a metaphor is introduced by
Bachelard and Heidegger because "[t]hey configure the encounter
between subject and world as an opening, which is to say that the
subject and world meet each other not as two pre-formed components but
as entities who acquire their being through their mutual participation
in or as an opening" (150). The balcony metaphor also introduces
this relation in a nondichotomous manner. Like a balcony, the subject
looks out on the world. The balcony is already part of the inside and
also a way for the subject to be outside to some extent. In our daily
speech, we say that someone is "out on the balcony," but to be
"out" on the balcony one has to be "in" the house
first. Being "on" a balcony means being "in" and
"out" at once. This allows us to read the metaphor as
suggesting that the subject "overlooking" the world is not
detached from the world "outside," but is already
"immersed" and "engaged" with this world as
Heidegger would put it (Cazeaux 151). For Heidegger, this world, in
turn, does not have a mind-independent structure, but emerges before us
humans in a way that is not detached from our concerns, interests and
desires (Cazeaux 153-55). The balcony metaphor also bears this idea
because, despite its engagement with the outside, the balcony remains
part of the inside, a part that provides a limited view of the world
outside.
In the poem, the things that the subject-as-balcony overlooks also
support the idea of subject/object mutual disclosure. In the first line
of the poem, the speaker claims to see whatever he desires. True, he
sees things that are attached to some individual and cultural concerns,
which he projects upon the world, but these projections are all made
possible because of his being immersed and already located in the world.
To better understand this, we must remember that the state of
"overlooking" or "looking over" in the poem is
probably a mental state, as the subject looks at imaginable things
besides visual ones, and at times it is difficult to decide between the
two. What is clear, however, is that some of the things he looks at are
wishes, memories, and desires. Like a balcony, the speaker looks out on
the friends who bear the evening mail, wine, bread, novels, and records;
the seagull and troop trucks which change the trees of the place; the
dog of the neighbor who emigrated from Canada; a procession of ancient
prophets; a woman basking in herself; the trunk of an olive tree that
hid Zachariah; the Persians, Romans, Sumerians, and the new refugees.
These things can all be seen, imagined, or wished for because of the
necessarily biological, social, and political natures of the subject, or
because of his status of being "immersed" in the world: the
wide world of nature, and the smaller worlds of social and cultural
contexts. Being engaged in nature, he desires to "overlook" a
woman. Being in a part of the world where there is conflict, he looks
out over troops and a procession of new prophets. Being in a part of the
world where language is Arabic, he looks over the Arabic dictionary, and
the name of al-Mutanabbi. Nonetheless, it is impossible to claim that
every human being who is a Palestinian poet would necessarily see or
imagine the exact same things, and so it is not viable to say that the
individual is entirely subordinated to the forces of the worlds in which
he is immersed. Within the possibilities that the subject's
engagement with the world allows are possibilities which emerge due to a
subjective constitution that is not entirely passive. The balcony
metaphor strongly bears this idea: A balcony would not allow two
Palestinians to see what is behind the house, but within the space they
can both see, their attention would not be necessarily drawn to, or
focused upon, the same things. Each will see what he looks for, and his
personal interests will be reflected.
Thus, the metaphor destabilizes the subject/object dichotomy
because the balcony is part of a structure whose construction is
particular to humans, even if it is open to the world. What further
thickens the whole situation is that the speaker can see his frightened
body, and later his ghost approaching from afar. This makes it more
uncertain which things belong to the outside and which to the inside, or
to the subject and to the world (Cazeaux 174). The subject of the poem
is given the metaphor of the balcony--an object--and overlooks his body
and his ghost. Though these two are irremovable parts of the subject
reflecting, they are both "objects" of his reflection. In
other words, the subject is given the metaphor of an object to
experience itself as a subject encountering itself as an object. The
inside becomes a way of seeing the outside, which already contains and
mirrors this inside. "Poets are well acquainted with the existence
of this hesitation of being," write Bachelard (Space 214). As a
particular space of an opening, the balcony metaphor allows for the
complexity of this circuitous, hesitant interaction. Its unsettledness
lacks the sharp geometry which Bachelard criticizes in the dialectics of
inside and outside as presented by some philosophers. In this metaphor,
inside and outside can no longer be experienced by imagination--and
intellect--in their "simple reciprocity" (216).
Another philosophical idea is present in the approaching of the
subject's ghost from afar. The ghost brings to mind the unformed
spirit in the Cartesian mind-body dualism. But is it a way of saying
that this unformed spirit is already part of nature, rather than being
distinct from it as Descartes had it? Such interpretation is
problematic, because both body and spirit, which are opposed in
Descartes, approach the balcony separately as it overlooks them. But
although they are not united and not identical, they are not opposed to
one another either, and thus an anti-Cartesian interpretation is
invited. It is here that the body is frightened, not the spirit, which
is also anti-Cartesian since emotions are not linked to matter for
Descartes. Thus the "I" which overlooks both its body and soul
may not exactly be in our metaphor the Cartesian identification of the
self. Still, the fact that it can see both its soul and body as objects
can imply that it is indeed the Cartesian consciousness. Also, the fact
that all the subject-balcony does is imagine and reflect seems to invite
Descartes's cogito as the thinking being. True, the balcony is made
from "materials" in the world, but its construction and
function are particularly human. Therefore, within the metaphor,
Descartes's idea of the mind as immaterial is questioned at the
same time that the metaphor itself retains, though hesitantly, the
specificity of the human mind a la Descartes to some extent. Does not
this metaphor answer Bachelard's quest for a new image, one that is
"sufficiently new in its nuance of being," which can
"furnish a lesson in ontological amplification," and whose
newness can help us "reverberate above ... reasonable
certainties"? (Space 216)
Obviously, what has been forcing us thus far to "think
more" is the balcony's relation to space. It does not separate
neatly the inside from the outside. And so, in spite of its brevity, the
balcony metaphor is able to "disturb the common notions of
spatiality" (Space 219). Bachelard does not mention the balcony in
The Poetics of Space as bearing this disturbance. However, he discusses
a comparable image: the door, which seems to bear similar capacities as
those of the balcony. He finds that a poetic image of "door"
allows us to explore the being of man "as the being of a
surface," as a region where "the movements of opening and
closing are so numerous, that we could conclude on the following
formula: man is a half-open being" (222). The balcony resembles
Bachelard's door, and it might even be more suited to the
"half-open being" formula. Like a door, it seems to separate
man from world but it is only a delicate separation where no sharp
boundaries exist. For Bachelard, the door can give images of
"hesitation, temptation, desire, security, welcome and
respect" (224), and requires only a "slight push" (222)
for "our fate to become visible" (223). The balcony can also
give such images, and perhaps others, and it does not even need that
slight push in order to reverse the "ordinary common sense" of
the perspective of inside and outside (225). I am like a balcony, the
subject of the poem says: both outside and inside.
To express a Bachelardian enthusiasm towards the balcony image for
its elasticity and for placing us at the "very limit" of what
we are able to imagine (227) is not without problems. True, it can
perhaps place us at the crossroads between subjectivity and objectivity,
realism and rationalism, and other similar dichotomies. Indeed, our
thoughts of these are destabilized, and are given a new body--the
balcony metaphor--through which they can be thought and re-thought.
However, at the same time that the metaphor seems to encourage a
dichotomy-free reflection of subject and object, we still find some
dualisms to be unavoidable. The interpretation cannot do without the
concepts of "subject" and "object" even if it
challenges their dichotomy. This invites Derrida's construal into
the play of "thinking more": Within the metaphor,
"subject" and "object" play and differ in the
relation to one another, leaving only a trace. At the very end of the
poem, the "ghost" or "spirit" coming from afar may
be read as this trace. The subject is not completely dissolved in the
world: It is still as durable as a balcony, retaining some
"insideness" or a "trace" of identity.
III. B. Perspectivism
Other philosophical ideas may be drawn from another characteristic
of the balcony--apart from its relation to space as a delicate separator
of inside and outside--i.e. its perspectival nature. The balcony cannot
overlook what is behind the building of which it is part. It cannot
overlook other spaces. And thus as a metaphor for human subjects, it
discourages the God's-eye view of the enlightenment, and suggests
that all human knowledge is perspectival--an idea which Nietzsche is
most well-known for. Nietzsche rejects Kantian notions of "the
intelligible character of things," "absolute
spirituality," and "knowledge in itself':
for these always ask us to imagine an eye which is impossible to
imagine, an eye which supposedly looks out in no particular direction,
an eye which supposedly either restrains or altogether lacks the active
powers of interpretation which first make seeing into seeing something
(Genealogy 98).
Is it not also impossible to imagine a balcony that overlooks all
directions at once? Our poetic balcony is much like Nietzsche's
"eye" in his analogy, and so within the balcony metaphor,
knowing can only be perspectival. For Nietzsche, the only way that
conception and objectivity can be complete is by having "more
feelings about a matter," "more eyes, different eyes which are
able to view this matter" (98). Time, one balcony may provide a
better view of the outside world than another balcony, but never a
complete one. This contradicts sharply with the spirit of the first
line: "like a balcony, I overlook whatever I desire." The
subject will need to be "like" several balconies for this to
be possible. True, his desires and feelings will influence what he
overlooks according to Perspectivism, and his attention will be drawn to
what he desires within the space he can see, but this does not imply
that he cannot desire what the balcony does not overlook.
III. C. Desire
The philosophical problem of desire is not absent from the balcony
metaphor. The balcony per se can provoke images of desire and temptation
given the reference to Romeo and Juliet. However, like Bachelard's
door image, the balcony metaphor can be read as a symbol of both desire
and restriction of desire. Because the subject-as-balcony is immersed in
the world and can only see it from a certain perspective, his desires
are necessarily constructed. "Whatever I desire" in the poem
and also its previous intertext "'Ara ma 'urid' seem
to disbelieve the notions of construction and restriction of desire, but
the things which the subject-balcony desires to overlook imply
otherwise. The subject desires to look at conflict and troop trunks, and
these are related to realities which one cannot choose or easily neglect
or "overlook." The balcony already overlooks the absence of
independence and the lack of freedom and justice, which will all create
a desire for looking at the procession of ancient prophets and the
emergence of a new one.
As regards "lack" of independence and freedom, it is
known that Deleuze and Guattari argued in Anti-Oedipus against
understanding desire in terms of the categories of the Negative such as
limit and lack (25-26). But one has to wonder if any theory of desire
that dismisses these terms can convince a Palestinian that he does not
"lack" freedom and justice, but that what he thinks is lack is
actually the effect of desiring-machines in which the unconscious is a
factory (24). Deleuze and Guattari argue that "Desire is a machine,
and the object of desire is another machine connected to it," and
so there is no lack of object, but a lack of a fixed subject (26). In
the poem, the subject finds it enough that a woman's hand is held
in his for him to "embrace his freedom." He uses "I
desire" confidently, trying to dismiss the total dissolution of the
subject in the process of social production, even if the laws of
prohibiting national and sexual freedoms have a say in creating his
desires. The balcony he resembles is often part of a construction which
does not collapse easily under the effects of nature, unless these
effects are natural disasters, which are exceptions and do not happen
everyday. Thus, within the metaphor, we cannot easily agree that the
subject is lacking. However, the fact that the poem ends with the
speaker seeing his ghost provokes us to understand the "I" of
"I desire" as not bearing that confident a tone. The subject
is split between being like a balcony, conscious of his body and soul,
and being a separate body and a ghost (or soul) approaching this balcony
from afar.
The splitting of the subject challenges the previous interpretation
which is based on the durability of the balcony. The "I" of
"I desire" may be split between several unconscious
"drives" of which we are ignorant as Nietzsche believes
(Daybreak 64). He argues that the mind is "a blind instrument"
(65) for the vehement drive struggling against another, and thus our
notions of "purposes" and "wills" may be
"fantastic commentaries" on "an unknown, perhaps
unknowable, but felt text" (76). We do not act, we are "acted
upon," he says (76-77). And thus, he adds, there is
"perhaps" only one realm, that of "chance accidents"
and "cosmic stupidity" rather than the realm of purposes and
will, which are only imagined (80-81). In Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and
Guattari also encourage an "acted upon" theory, based on their
claim that: "Man and nature are not like two opposite terms
confronting each other--not even in the sense of bipolar opposites
within a relationship of causation, ideation, or expression (cause and
effect, subject and object, etc.); rather they are one and the same
essential reality, the producer-product" (4-5).
The balcony is immersed in the world and can thus bear the idea of
the subject being one with the forces of nature and society. But as it
retains some sort of space that keeps it from being entirely on the side
of the "outside," the metaphor succeeds in not rendering
desire entirely de-individualized. True, some of the goals of the
subject-as-balcony are seemingly constructed (women, independence,
justice, friendship, the refugees' right to return), which can all
be understood as connecting points within greater matrixes of social
production. Other desires, however, cannot. The desire to overlook the
name of al-Mutannabi and the Arabic dictionary may be an instrumental
desire through which the poet can achieve greatness. But to understand
this desire as merely a connecting point in some other greater machine
where, for example, great poets attract publishers who will profit from
such satisfaction of desire seems somewhat reductive. Conversely,
Deleuze and Guattari find that ego-based theories of desire, such as
Freud's Oedipus complex, are the ones which should be accused of
reduction. But does not an oedipal model of interpretation (such as
Bloom's anxiety of influence) seem very valid in understanding the
mention of the great Arabic poet al-Mutannabbi, a powerful precursor or
Freudian father?
Supposing that we agree with Deleuze and Guattari that there are
only "group fantasies" whose productions are real
(Anti-Oedipus 30), is there any way in which the desire to see
al-Mutanabbi's name can be understood in this framework? This
desire is seemingly individual, but if we understand its effects as
inspirations for writing a poem keeping in mind that many poets are
inspired by al-Mutanabbi, and if we consider the poem to be something
"real," then the interpretation can bear the claims of Deleuze
and Guattari. They propose that "If desire produces, its product is
real," as they are against the understanding of production as
production of representations and fantasies, and argue for the
"intrinsic power of desire to create its own object" (25-26).
This is perhaps clearer in the desire to overlook a procession of
ancient prophets, but as the "real" object created eventually
by this desire is "merely" a poem, this desire cannot be seen
as a connecting point for a social production in a time of conflict,
unless one exaggerates to the point of believing in an enormous effect
of poetry on its readers. The exaggeration will entail considering the
poem itself an instance of aesthetic "investment" in a wider
social unconscious (104), and which can be seen as part of a
"revolutionary machine" (293) that seeks to break other
mobilizing flows where the inhibition of revolt has become unconscious
(119).
But if this was possible, then why would the subject helplessly
desire the emergence of a new prophet? Is it not because the desires of
the latter-- who is not merely a poet--initiate action and can indeed be
connecting points in revolutionary desiring-machines that eventually can
produce something real, more real than poetry? Again, the balcony
metaphor can bear the theory of connecting points primarily because of
its status of being immersed in the world, a status which made prophets
come into the scene in the first place. It can thus bear Deleuze and
Guattari's view that "our 'object choice' itself
refers to conjunction of flows of life and of society that this body and
this person intercept, receive, and transmit, always within a
biological, social, and historical field where we are equally immersed
or with which we communicate" (293). Still, the metaphor's
bearing of this idea is not without instability and hesitation. The
title of the poem and its final fine contain a ghost approaching from
afar, which can be interpreted as the eventual return of the ego: It
approaches the subject of "I desire," refusing to be a mere
illusion. Adding to that the rough identity that the balcony retains
through being a small separating space, the metaphor leaves a small
possibility of human agency and free will. It is only a small
possibility because the immersion of the balcony in the world and its
perspectival nature cannot allow the subject-as-balcony to overlook
"whatever" he desires.
Conclusion
Heidegger, like Bachelard, was disinterested in interpretation in
the strict sense of the word, and preferred that his reading of
Holderlin be viewed as an "accompaniment" to the poetic text,
a "pause for reflection." Bachelard encouraged the reader to
go "too far" and follow his impulse of
"exaggeration," which he limits to the realm of imagination
and "daydreams." Ricoeur, however, following Kant, viewed
metaphor as an invitation to "think more" at a conceptual
level, and believed that interpretation functions at the intersection of
metaphorical and speculative discourses. Derrida went further to claim
the existence of more philosophical texts within metaphor than metaphors
within philosophical texts.
This article has relied on these theoretical encouragements
(outlined in Part I) to read Darwish's balcony metaphor differently
from most of Darwish criticism (reviewed in Part II). Part III attempted
a philosophical "accompaniment" to the poem, based on three
ideas linked to the balcony: inside/outside interaction, Perspectivism,
and desire. Doubtless, such "thinking more" has been made
possible by the "suggestiveness" of the metaphor (Bachelard)
and the poetic metaphor "came first" indeed (Heidegger). The
metaphor, however, has not created new concepts or become clearly
propositional thus maintaining a Deleuzian distinction between poetry
and philosophy. Still, it did not remain a plane of "affects and
percepts" (Deleuze and Guattari), but a plane of associations which
provoke a straggle to "think more," conceptually, in search
for a philosophical text underlying or accompanying the metaphor.
Notes
(1) For the most part of this article, I use "overlook"
as a translation of 'utill, i.e. in the sense of "looking over
or at something from a higher place," and not in the sense of
"ignoring" or "disregarding." Although
"overlook" is rarely used in English for humans to indicate
the first meaning, I believe it is here acceptable since, in
Darwish's poem, the human subject is given the balcony metaphor to
imply a state of looking at something in the same way that a balcony
looks out on something, and because it is difficult to find an exact
counterpart in English for 'utill which in Arabic is equally used
for both humans and non-humans. In Unfortunately, It Was Paradise, Amira
El-Zein uses "I gaze upon" as a translation for 'utill
(55-57), which I do not think is accurate because nothing in the word
'utill suggests gazing or staring, and because "gaze
upon" is not used for non-humans except metaphorically.
Darwish's metaphor intends to compare the human subject to the
balcony and not the other way around as would be implied if 'utill
is translated into "I gaze upon." Jeffrey Sacks in his 2006
translation of the collection uses "I look out on" for all the
lines of the poem beginning with 'utill, except for 'utillu
'alamawkibi al-anbiya'i al-qudamawahum yas'aduna hufatan
ila urshalim which he translates into "I look out over the
procession of ancient prophets climbing barefoot to Jerusalem" (Why
Did You Leave 2-6). Sacks's two choices--unlike "gaze
upon"--successfully maintain the figurative structure of the Arabic
original because, like 'utill, "look out on" and
"look out over" are used for objects. For this reason, I use
"overlook," "look over," "look out over,"
and "look out on" interchangeably in this article. My
preference for "overlook" stems from the fact that when used
as a noun, it means "an elevated place that affords an extensive
view" (The American Heritage Dictionary), a definition almost
identical to the Arabic 'itlala, verbal noun form of 'utillu.
All translations from this poem are mine.
Works Cited
Bachelard, Gaston. On Poetic Imagination and Reverie. Trans.
Colette Gaudin. Putnam: Spring Publications, 2005.
--. The Poetics of Space. Trans. Maria Jolas. Boston: Beacon P,
1994.
Cazeaux, Clive. Metaphor and Continental Philosophy. NY: Routledge,
2007.
Darraj, Faysal. 'Transfiguration in the Image of Palestine in
the Poetry of Mahmoud Darwish." Mahmoud Darwish, Exile's Poet:
Critical Essays. Eds. Hala Khamis Nassar and Najat Rahman. Northampton,
MA: Interlink books, 2008. 57-78.
Darwish, Mahmud. Dhakira lil-nisyan [A Memory for Forgetfulness].
Ramallah: Ministry of Culture, 1997.
--. Diwan Mahmud Darwish. Vol. 2. Beirut: Dar al-'Awda, 1994.
--. Jidariyya [Mural]. Beimt: El-Rayyis Books, 2000.
--. Ka zahral-lawz aw ab'ad [Like Almond Blossoms or Beyond].
Beimt: El-Rayyis Books, 2005.
--. Limadha tarakta al-hisan wahidan? [Why did you leave the horse
alone?] London: Riyad El-Rayyis Books, 1995.
--. Unfortunately, It was Paradise: Selected Poems. Trans, and Eds.
Munir Akash et al. Berkeley: U of California P, 2003.
--. Why Did You Leave the Horse Alone? Trans. Jeffrey Sacks. NY:
Archipelago Books, 2006.
Deleuze, Gillez and Felix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane. NY:
Penguin Classics, 2009.
--. What is Philosophy? Trans. H. Tomlinson and G. Burchell. NY:
Columbia UP, 1994.
Derrida, Jacques. Margins of Philosophy. Trans. Alan Bass.
Brighton: Harvester P, 1982.
DeYoung, Terri. Placing the Poet: Badr Shakir al-Sayyab and
Postcolonial Iraq. NY: State U of New York P, 1998.
Gaudin, Colette. Introduction. Gaston Bachelard On Poetic
Imagination and Reverie. Trans. Colette Gaudin. Putnam: Spring
Publications, 2005. xxxi-lix.
Hadd, Subhi. "Dama'ir MahmudDarwish [Mahmoud
Darwish's Pronouns]." al-Quds al-'Arabi. March 15, 2010.
20.
Heidegger, Martin. Holderlin's Hymn "The Ister."
Trans. William McNeill and Julia Davis. Bloomington: Indana UP, 1996.
Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: U
of Chicago P, 1980.
Nassar, Hala Khamis and Najat Rahman, eds. Mahmoud Darwish,
Exile's Poet: Critical Essays. Northampton, MA: Interlink books,
2008.
Nietzsche, Friedch. Daybreak: Thoughts on the prejudices of
morality. Eds. M. Clark and B. Leiter. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1997.
--.On the Genealogy of Morals: A Polemic. Trans. Douglas Smith. NY:
Oxford UP, 2008.
Qabbani, Nizar. "Rajul wahid [A Lonely Man]". Adab.
<http://www.adab.
com/modules.php?name=Sh3er&doWhat=shqas&qid=69203&r=&ic=6>.
Rahman, Najat. "Threatened Longing and Perpetual Search: The
Writing of Home in the Poetry of Mahmoud Darwish." Mahmoud Darwish,
Exile's Poet: Critical Essays. Eds. Hala Khamis Nassar and Najat
Rahman. Northampton, MA: Interlink books, 2008. 41-56.
Ricoeur, Paul. The Rule of Metaphor: Multi-Disciplinary Studies of
the Creation of Meaning in Language. Trans. R. Czerny, K. McLaughlin,
and J. Costello. London: Routledge andKegan Paul, 1978.
Salih, Fakhri. "Mahmud Darwish: Min shi'r al-muqawama ila
shi'r alinsaniyya [From the poetry of resistance to the poetiy of
humanity]." Hakadha takallama Mahmud Darwish: Dirasat ft dhikra
rahilih [Thus Spoke Mahmud Darwish: Studes in Memoriam]. Ed Abdelilah
Belkeziz. Beirut: Center for Arab Unity Studes, 2009. 127-57.