"Titles are jests": the challenge to generic dialectic in A King and No King.
Byrne, Peter
RECENT criticism of Fletcherian tragicomedy has focused on its
political commentary. Such criticism is reasonable; tragicomedy appears
particularly well-suited to courtly criticism, inasmuch as it can
combine the lofty characters and high emotional and political stakes of
tragedy, while avoiding that genre's necessarily cataclysmic
conclusion, which might easily give offense to the courtiers observing
their doppelgangers' demise. Instead, tragicomedy provides "a
form which expresse[s] in theatrical fiction the belief that in spite of
potentially dangerous circumstances harmony and order [will] prevail in
the end," (1) and so enables an appropriate means for the artistic
community to comment on the conduct of their social superiors. By
incorporating instead comedy's resolution of harmony, the rhetoric
of exhortation can replace that of condemnation. Such generic
opportunity was unlikely to be neglected by the politically-minded
Fletcher. Gordon McMullan has demonstrated thoroughly the political
agenda of Fletcher's canon in The Politics of Unease in the Plays
of John Fletcher, and the combination of such an author and such a genre
yields the reasonably decisive conclusion that we are secure in reading
his works for their political content.
But there is a problem with applying this rubric too broadly,
particularly with regard to A King and No King, generally regarded as
the most successful tragicomedy in the Fletcherian canon: political
commentary, like all forms of rhetoric, requires a relatively stable
genre to inform and sustain its argument. This need is particularly
acute in those genres in which the commentary is implicit within the
mimesis of art, and which therefore demands the interpretation of the
audience in order to sway its opinion. Genre is a powerful device for
easing this interpretation, as Alastair Fowler explains: "In
literary communication, genres are functional: they actively form the
experience of each work of literature." (2) For the playwright, the
tropes of dramatic genre function as Aristotelian
enthymeme--familiarities that prompt concession without requiring proof
or digressive justifications: "The generic markers ... of a work
have a strategic role in guiding the reader. They help to establish, as
soon as possible, an appropriate mental 'set' that allows the
work's generic codes to be read." (3) The wide assortment of
generic hallmarks available to playwrights (character types, plot
devices, commonplaces of imagery or action) serve to enable
comprehension of the grounds upon which an argument is formed, and act
as an illustration of that argument's movement from premise to
telos. An audience familiar with watching a comedy or a tragedy is
familiar with the meanings of the hallmarks of those genres, and by
recognizing them, can more successfully be led to the playwright's
desired concordance of opinion. Such rhetorical use of a genre's
predictability can be problematic, however, in two ways. First, if the
genre, like tragicomedy, is less rigorously defined and understood by
author and audience, its ability to construct an argument based on
accepted indices can be compromised. Second, overfamiliarity with any
genre can lead to an ossification of the audience's judgment;
elements that appear to be the hallmarks of a genre may be received
contrary to the author's intent, and an audience preconditioned to
see generic meaning can, with little or no prompting, see nothing else.
For the generically-minded playwright, there must be concern that
the enabling of comprehension offered by genre can tip over into an
occlusion of comprehension when familiarity of generic tropes replaces
the ability to interpret objects that do not, in fact, embody those
tropes. This problem is particularly acute for those working in
tragicomedy, which must render its composers self-conscious about its
generic elements. Tragicomedy, which assembles its arsenal of tropes
from both comedy and tragedy, as well as many that are sui generis, must
confront the rhetorically-minded author with the challenge of
constructing an argument based on tropes that may lead an audience to
anticipate (as the audience for The Faithful Shepherdess did) a play and
an argument far from the author's intent. And there is an
additional, related challenge for the tragicomic playwright: the loss of
the emotional coherence provided by comedy and tragedy. Can the mixed
mode achieve a momentum of pathos sufficient to carry an argument? John
T. Shawcross obliquely diagnoses this concern in his definition of
tragicomedy: "The conclusion is comedic, but there is no
necessarily lasting spiritual rebirth or vision ... exhibited by the
characters. The reversal is for the present only; there is more surface
than depth, particularly in the moral dimension." (4) These are the
concerns that dominate the argument of A King and No King, which
addresses both the validity of a generically framed dramatic argument
and the questionable emotional impact of a tragicomedy's
denouement.
Both issues were clearly on Fletcher's mind well before the
composition of A King and No King. In his address 'To The
Reader' of The Faithful Shepherdess, Fletcher offers a famously
acerbic account of the play's aforementioned failure: "It is a
pastorall Tragie-comedie, which the people seeing when it was plaid,
having ever had a singuler guift in defining, concluded to be a play of
country hired Shepheards in gray cloakes, with curtaild dogs in strings,
sometimes laughing together, and sometimes killing one another: And
missing whitsun ales, creame, wassel, and morris-dances, began to be
angry." (5) Though his conclusion may be compromised by his anger,
Fletcher's disdain for his audience is significant in that he
stresses the degree to which popular opinion (rather than classical
precedent or artistic convention) had become a means of defining
dramatic genres, a trend with potent implications for the popular artist
whose income depended largely on satisfying that opinion.
For Fletcher, the poor reception of Shepherdess was not due to an
audience unprepared to view a tragicomedy, but one that was too firmly
prepared for its version of a pastoral to accept any elements extraneous
to that anticipated theatrical experience. Such expectations invariably
lead away from the notion of drama as a mode of philosophical or moral
portrait, examination, and encouragement, and towards an "assembly
line" approach in which the ingredients of the genre themselves
become the genre itself.
Curiously, Fletcher seems to confirm this approach in his own
definition of tragicomedy. While his dismissal of his audience's
inadequacy would seem to be based on a dismissal of their means of
evaluation, his description is not as distinct from theirs as it might
be: "A tragie-comedie is not so called in respect of mirth and
killing, but in respect it wants deaths, which is inough to make it no
tragedie, yet brings some neere it, which is inough to make it no
comedie: which must be a representation of familiar people, with such
kinde of trouble as no life be questiond, so that a God is as lawfull in
this as in a tragedie, and meane people as in a comedie." (6) Like
his despised audience, Fletcher depicts tragicomedy as a genre defined
by its hallmarks (or their absence) rather than for any coherent telos
the genre sustains. (7)
Moreover, his description reinforces the easy notion of tragicomedy
as a genre defined by other genres. Defined exclusively by the elements
of tragedy and comedy, tragicomedy remains "neither fish nor
fowl," and thus encourages the presumption that tragedy and comedy
are instances of coherent genres, with elements appropriate to both.
This definition has been the grounds for the critical dismissal of
tragicomedy as an inherently inferior genre, since it cannot sustain a
generic unity of tenor and vehicle. (8) Under this rubric, tragicomedy
becomes simply an admixture of disparate elements, rather than an
independent mode, capable of articulating a moral or emotional
perspective that is something other than tragedy or comedy in a minor
key. (9)
But as canonical critics of Fletcher like Eugene Waith and Philip
Finkelpearl have demonstrated, the Fletcherian canon does achieve an
artistic consistency that transcends the notion of tragicomedy as a
generic gallimaufry. Fletcher's frustrated counterassertion to his
audience's definitions appears to be the first step toward
recognizing that the mode is more than the sum of its parts, and it is
significant that the three works he produces in his collaboration with
Beaumont immediately after Shepherdess are his most substantial
contributions as a dramatist: Philaster, The Maid's Tragedy, and A
King and No King. Recalling his recently expressed self-awareness of the
problematic nature of generic tropes and their overfamiliarity, Fletcher
moves towards an artistic assertion of the possibility of a dramatic
mode that corrects the faults of generic overdependence.
Examined with this intent in mind, A King and No King offers a
dramatic form in which the exceptional, rather than the categorical, is
the constitutive. In this sense, it is a peculiar fulfillment of the
modes of comedy and tragedy, which address the dramatic consequences of
an exceptional perspective. But the play's portrait of exceptional
perspective operates as a rejection of, rather than an altered version
of these genres. The play argues that, abstracted from the specifics of
plot and character, neither tragedy nor comedy can portray true
exceptionality, since both genres operate according to a systematic
concept of drama as dialectic, which excludes the exceptional in favor
of the categorical. Each genre is a conflict of values, desires, and
perspective, which in tragedy achieves the elimination of one side, and
in comedy achieves a corrective detente. (10) But A King and No King
strongly criticizes the exclusionary process of dialectic, suspending
the conclusive nature of tragedy and comedy, and focusing instead on
those theatrical elements of action and character that comedy and
tragedy exclude, while acknowledging the pull towards commitment to one
of the "pure" dramatic genres.
This rejection of a designated telos is reflected in
tragicomedy's tendency to portray suspended action; within generic
composition, action decisively commits the drama to one of the two
generic outcomes. Waith has identified this structural suspension as a
particular quality of Fletcher's tragicomic work: the use of
narrative stasis as an occasion for rhetorical discovery and examination
of a thematic topic. Of the characters of The Faithful Shepherdess, he
writes: "In speeches as formal as the movements of the dancer they
exhibit their diverse natures and establish the themes of the play....
The plot, like the story of a ballet, is less important than the
component situations in which an idea, a relationship, or an emotion is
given a brief, vivid actuality." (11) Like tragedy or comedy,
tragicomedy is an exhibit of the agon between represented ideas, but
unlike them, it is not predetermined in the conclusion of that agon.
On the contrary, its lack of narrative necessity enables its
encounters to be profitably indecisive, achieving mutual agreement
rather than the enforced capitulation of one perspective. It is the
privileging of discourse in Fletcherian tragicomedy that has yielded
much of traditional criticism's disdain for what seems like an
indecisive mode. Waith answers this criticism (in the form of
Eliot's famous dismissal of the collaborators' canon as
"hollow" and "a clever appeal to emotions and
associations which they have not grasped" (12)), by arguing that it
is the very artifice of tragicomedy that enables a more substantial
intellectual grappling with its subject: "The verse of Beaumont and
Fletcher ... is exactly what it appears to be and exactly what the
situations demand.... The poetry of every major scene is a brilliant
solution to a rhetorical problem." (13) Waith regards this dramatic
method as one primarily used to attempt emotional expression rather than
more cerebral analysis, but he also notes that these emotional
"high points" of tragicomedies like A King and No King are
achieved by a "vitality ... given to them by declamatory
rhetoric." (14)
It is the use of such rhetoric, used to examine as well as
persuade, to identify and define as well as to move, that denotes
Fletcherian tragicomedy. The authors assert their right to include gods
as well as mean persons because such figures are capable of perspectives
and speech that those occupying the middle grounds of humanity cannot
articulate, and while tragedy or comedy would exclude one of these two
extremities, tragicomedy enables a fuller view of its topic. Their
tragicomedies enable a competitive but inclusive discourse between rival
perspectives, and with this is in mind, we might regard A King and No
King as, in part, a dramatized discourse between the perspectives and
presumptions of each genre. This approach returns us to the notion of
genre both as a rhetorical mode for making a particular argument about
human character and experience, and as a means of popular and critical
consumption. Both functions are foregrounded in A King and No King,
which portrays a set of characters insistent on a generically coherent
experience, reflecting both the audience demanding its usual generic
tropes and the critic demanding a traditional generic telos.
Based on his earlier definition of a tragicomedy's licensed
ingredients, Fletcher appears to favor the audience's demands. But
A King and No King reveals a developed perspective that recognizes the
need to examine both sets of expectations, and criticize the flaws in
both. As such, A King and No King evokes generic conventions for
evaluating character and action, in order to criticize the degree to
which such conventions--and the convention of genre itself--are adequate
to present and evaluation the heterogeneous nature of context and
character.
Here my focus on the generic criticism in and of the play aligns
with the political focus of other critics. For to be sure,
Fletcher's plays are political in their aims. McMullan baldly
states that "The Faithful Shepherdess is a political play,"
elaborating "the political effect of the transfer of power is ...
highly charged, since figures representative of both spiritual and
secular power in the play defer to a virgin for an appropriate solution
to the country's ills, a thoroughly Jacobean literary strategy
recalling the mythologized norms of the reign of Elizabeth." (15)
The implication here is not simply that Fletcher's work is
politically motivated, but that his use of familiar hallmarks of
character and action show a lively sense of the power of such hallmarks
to attain rhetorical ends. But the political goals of Fletcher's
art are what must motivate him, as a conscientious artist, to render his
plays capable of presenting and his audiences capable of receiving his
intended argument. The failure of The Faithful Shepherdess, as well as
his collaboration with Beaumont, appear to have given him pause in his
political agenda, resulting in one work, at least, that questions the
stability (and thus the efficacy) of generically-situated rhetoric.
Unless an audience can read a play correctly, they cannot be expected to
read the message conveyed within that play. The critical consensus on
the political dimension of Fletcher's plays must make allowance for
a self-awareness on Fletcher's part as a rhetorician. My reading of
A King and No King as a play primarily concerned with the efficacy of
genre as a means of interpretive engagement with both art and the world
is therefore a supplement, rather than an alternative to, the political
readings of his works.
The need for suppleness of interpretive approach in art and in life
is of course a timely subject for Beaumont and Fletcher. Montaignean
skepticism's intrusion into the theatrical realm creates a
disruptive opportunity to question precedence as a means of evaluation,
and Michael Neill has noted that the ethos of A King and No King derives
substantially from such skepticism: "The protean qualities of this
drama, the violent switches of attitude and behavior, are not simply
resources of theatrical expediency: they reveal the dramatists'
sense of a world knit up of contraries, inherently unstable and liable
to sudden alteration and peripety." (16) Neill's reading
correctly represents the experience of both the characters of the play
and its audience, but as I will show, he overlooks a significant aspect
of its plot which reveals that experience to be considerably less
arbitrary, and which renders the experience of arbitrariness to be a
misreading of the homogenous. Nevertheless, Montaigne's influence
is unquestionable; the play's criticism of the insistence on
conventional consistency resonates decisively with the Montaignean
criticism of the same subject: "Given the natural inconstancy of
our behavior and our opinions it has often occurred to me that even
sound authors are wrong in stubbornly trying to weave us into one
invariable and solid fabric." (17) While Montaigne may not have
intended his words to be understood as references to dramatic poets, the
sentiment is entirely applicable to their work, as Verna Foster has
noted in identifying "one of the hallmarks of Fletcherian
tragicomedy, the predictably unexpected quality of mundane human
experience." (18)
The tragicomedy of A King and No King is framed within an
unsustainable ethos that demands consistency, and rejects anything less
as a sign of inadequacy. This is of course the problem of tragicomedy
itself, which frustrates the expectations of critics who demand generic
coherence. In their generically pliant mode, and its implied rejection
of the authority of those critics (like Sidney) who demand rigidity,
Beaumont and Fletcher appear to align themselves with the position of
Puttenham, who prescribes a revised approach to composition and
reception in terms that themselves owe much to Montaigne:
But since the actions of man with their circumstances be infinite,
and the world likewise replenished with many judgments, it may be a
question who shall have the determination of such a controversy as
may arise whether this or that action or speech be decent or
indecent. And verily, it seems to go all by discretion, not
perchance of everyone, but by a learned and experienced discretion.
For otherwise seems the decorum to a weak and ignorant judgment
than it doth to one of better knowledge and experience, who showeth
that it resteth in the discerning part of the mind, so as he who
can make the best and most differences of things by reasonable and
witty distinction is to be the fittest judge or sentencer of
decency. Such generally is the discreetest man, particularly in any
art the most skillful and discreetest, and in all other things for
the more part those that be of much observation and greatest
experience. (19)
Puttenham later stresses that decency as is virtue is "to be
observed in every man's action and behavior as well as in his
speech and writing," (20) thus tying his analysis to the
interpretation of performance as much as text, and giving a distinct air
of the theatrical to the decorum he advocates. Of key importance in
Puttenham's argument is the recognition that a flawed perspective
on the part of the poetic critic or dramatic audience is as severe as a
misguided author. In addressing the flaws of the critic and audience,
however, Puttenham elides what Montaigne flatly states: that
"learning" and "experience" often conflict, and that
humanity has a tendency to rely too much on the former, and to forget
that the latter is highly subjective. (21) Adopting the issue of genre
precedent as an inadequate means of composing and receiving drama,
Beaumont and Fletcher offer a deeper skepticism than Puttenham's,
but do so in a fashion that attempts to unite his values of
"learning" and "experience" by questioning the
perspective that shapes both.
With Fletcher's description of his audience's
inadequacies in mind, the crowd scene in II.ii of the play demonstrates
his criticism of popular authority in generic evaluation. Beaumont had
already mocked the sophomoric pretensions of the popular audience in The
Knight of the Burning Pestle, and the scene in A King and No King
strongly resembles that earlier work in its scathing portrait of the
common spectator. Arbaces, King of Iberia, has ended his country's
lengthy war with Armenia by besting its monarch, Tigranes, in single
combat. With characteristic excess, he has announced to his court his
plans to forgive all hostilities, forgo all ransom, and to unite the
kingdoms with the marriage of his captive to Panthea, Arbaces's
sister. (22) Arbaces has therefore assembled the populace not only to
meet them in triumph, but to present to them a reconciled Tigranes. But
here he meets with an unexpected response: a chorus of disapproval.
In what reads like an artist's retort against those who
rejected his Shepherdess, Fletcher's prelude to Arbaces's
entrance establishes the crowd as a surly, ignorant lot, as much
concerned with the sale of conveniences and refreshments as they are by
the appearance of their king after his long absence. A jostling fight
breaks out and an adulterous assignation is contemplated; such is the
moral and intellectual makeup of the crowd to whom Arbaces speaks. The
king's agenda is not a complex one: to present Tigranes as the
prospective husband of their princess, and the foundation of a lasting
peace. Their reaction, however, does not follow his intentions;
rejecting his bid to "sing songs of gladness and deliverance,"
the crowd quickly becomes a lynch mob: "Out upon him! How he looks!
Hang him, hang him, hang him!" (23) His lieutenant Mardonius is
appalled, Tigranes is humiliated, and Arbaces can only placate the crowd
by giving them what they clearly want: a vision of Tigranes as a
monstrously hubristic hero brought low. "The terror of his name has
stretched itself / Wherever there is sun. And yet for you / I fought
with him and won him too; /I made his valour stoop and brought that
name, / Soared to so unbelieved a height, to fall beneath mine"
(III.ii. 118-23). At this new representation of the war's
conclusion as the consummation of a tragic career, the crowd subsides
once again into happy celebration. It is the sacrificial catharsis of a
tragic downfall that they have come to see, not the pleasantries of a
comic reconciliation. Like the audience for Shepherdess, they have come
with expectations, and nothing else offered them, no matter how
pleasantly beneficial, will satisfy.
Tigranes blames Arbaces for this "speech in commendations of
himself," calling him "vainglorious" (III.ii. 127-29)--a
diagnosis shared by virtually all of the court--but it is worth
remembering that such had not been Arbaces's intention: "It
was far from me to mean it so" (III.ii. 112-13). Here the
drama's depicted pull toward generic commitment is revealed. Swayed
by the crowd and their expectations, Arbaces succumbs to their demands,
and stumbles into a display of hubris that, even as it paints Tigranes
as a tragic hero overthrown by nemesis, equally marks Arbaces himself as
a tragic figure inviting his own peripeteia. Simply put, Arbaces wishes
to offer his audience a comedy's ending, but his audience demands a
tragedy's pride and fall, and gets it. For one who is marked as
perversely self-determining throughout the play, Arbaces here displays
the contrary fault in his unwillingness to remain firm in the face of a
mob of ignoramuses; he would rather be popular with the people than
maintain his own interpretive agenda. And lest we think that commoners
are in the right, the authors are careful to mock them in departing, as
the Citizens' Wives happily anticipate the "peas"--rather
than "peace"--they believe Arbaces has brought home with him
(III.ii. 155-63).
The scene argues that, within a theatrical perspective, action is
interpreted by an often unsoundly biased perspective. This concern
permeates the play, in which identity is too often determined by
external denomination, and action judged accordingly. A King and No King
opens with the comic exchange between Mardonius and Bessus, reviewing
the latter's inadvertent success in the climactic battle of the
war. Bessus, beaten by Mardonius as a coward during the battle, has
allowed his fright to misdirect him, and engaged upon an unintentional
surprise charge against the enemy, winning the Iberians their victory.
But Mardonius will not allow any virtue in the action, arising as it did
from cowardice and error. Bessus is pragmatic: "But came not I up
when the day was gone and redeemed all?" Mardonius rebuts:
"Thou knowst, and so do I, thou meanst to fly, and, thy fear making
thee mistake, thou ranst upon the enemy" (I.i.67-71). Mardonius is
correct, of course; the act was a mistake. But it was a mistake that led
to triumph, which even Mardonius grudgingly concedes: "I think we
owe thy fear for our victory" (I.i.72-73). But he will not allow
that a man's action can be in contradiction to his character;
Bessus is a coward, and thus his act is cowardly, and is judged
accordingly.
A central problem of the play is established: the degree to which
actions are deemed erroneous not by their consequences, but by the
publically designated character of their performers. That Mardonius is
right is this case does not mean that he will be right in every case,
particularly with this interpretive approach. But the authors invite us
to give Mardonius that credibility here; Bessus is such an identifiable
type, the miles gloriosus, that we are encouraged not only to share
Mardonius's certainty about him, but to approach subsequent
characters with a similar means of typological evaluation, and a similar
certainty as to their type. This invitation to confirmation bias is
aided by the fact that Mardonius, in his moralizing chastisement,
reveals himself to be a dramatic type as well: the raisonneur of comedy.
If the first two characters we encounter appear to encourage generic
typology, such typology is the suggested reading of subsequent
introductions.
Upon this established point, Arbaces enters. And here the authors
reveal that without such a sound understanding of character, readings
that fall back on typology will attempt to make the exceptional and
incongruous fit within the stereotypical. For just as Mardonius
correctly reads Bessus as a generic type, so he reads Arbaces, but this
time incorrectly. His chastisement of his king is the criticism of a
perspective that demands consistency of character: "He is
vainglorious and humble, and angry and patient, and merry and dull, and
joyful and sorrowful, in extremities in an hour" (I.i.84-86). Here
he resembles nothing so much as those figures mocked by Montaigne, who
"select one universal character, then, following that model ...
classify and interpret all the actions of a great man; if they cannot
twist them the way they want they accuse the man of insincerity."
(24) The notion that circumstances may, even within a short space of
time, provoke Arbaces to entirely appropriate yet divergent responses,
does not occur to him.
Mardonius's complaint regarding the brief space of time
between these swings of mood and action pointedly resembles the demands
of generically minded critics of tragicomedy. A play's brevity, for
such readers, requires consistency of character in order to produce a
harmonious whole in enacting the genre's emotional and moral telos.
This critical perspective aligns Mardonius with Sidney, who demands just
such consistency from his heroes: "If the poet do his part aright,
he will show you in Tantalus, Atreus, and such like, nothing that is not
to be shunned; in Cyrus, Aeneas, Ulysses each thing to be
followed." (25) It does not strike Mardonius that, as a subject to
a king, his reading of inconsistency might be the result of a flaw in a
subject's perspective rather than a monarch's conduct. (In the
absolutist terms of seventeenth-century kingship, derived from texts
like Baslikon Down, such ought to be Mardonius's response.)
But Mardonius does not interpret Arbaces as he would a true king;
he interprets him as he would a generic, and specifically, a tragic
king. His advice to Arbaces addresses the king as an insufficiently
committed dramatic type, not as an individual independent of generically
conventional restrictions:
Were you no king and free from these wild moods, should I choose a
companion for wit and pleasure, it should be you; or for honesty to
interchange my bosom with, it would be you; or wisdom to give me
counsel, I would pick out you; or valour to defend my reputation to
defend my reputation, still would I find you out; for you are fit
to fight for all the world, if it should come in question
(I.i.373-80).
Arbaces's status as 'a king' demands consistency
before Mardonius can ascribe any virtue to him; without this
consistency, he must be read as an inadequate figure. And it is equally
telling that Mardonius portrays inconsistency not as a quality that
divides Arbaces between a tragic identity and a comic one, but instead
casts it as a disposition of character that leads to the tragic
hero's role. "Truth will offend you" (I.i.276), he tells
Arbaces, and a monarchical hero in opposition to a universal truth is
the hallmark of tragedy's destructive arc.
This pattern of forcing Arbaces into a suitably generic role is
perpetuated throughout the play. Following the debacle of the crowd
scene, Arbaces is chastised for his capitulation to the mob by Tigranes
and Mardonius. Tigranes is motivated by an understandable self-interest,
but Mardonius's disapproval, motivated as he claims by his devotion
to Arbaces and supported by his role as raisonneur, appears
comparatively objective, and thus more a more significant contextual
evaluation of his character. Maurice Hunt, for instance, deems Mardonius
to be the "authoritative auditor" of Arbaces's
self-expression, whose ridicule is supported by Beaumont and Fletcher:
"By depicting temperamentally mixed Arbaces as two persons and then
wishing the passionate fellow away, Mardonius predicts the possible
reformation of his character." (26)
But I contend that this apparent support is an invitation by
Beaumont and Fletcher to share the error, rather than confirm the
opinion, of Mardonius. We cannot view his as the course of
self-evaluation and conduct that Arbaces ought to follow, since
Mardonius suffers from the same analytical distortion as Arbaces
himself. Though he believes that he speaks from a perspective of
critical objectivity, his perspective is fundamentally flawed in its
premise. For, like everyone else at the Iberian court, and like the
audience itself, he believes Arbaces to be what he is not: the rightful
king and Panthea's brother.
The interpretive cipher to the action and argument of A King and No
King, hidden until the final moments of the play, is the secret plot
between Gobrius, Lord Protector of Iberia and Arbaces's true
father, and the Iberian Queen Mother, Arane. Faced with the failure of
her royal marriage to produce an heir, Arane enters into a conspiracy
with Gobrius to feign her pregnancy, and to substitute Gobrius's
newborn son as the designated heir to the throne. The plan succeeds, but
to the chagrin of both, Arane subsequently conceives a true heir: her
daughter, Panthea. Locked into the artifice of Arbaces's feigned
parentage, the two continue the ruse as he assumes the throne. Arane
repeatedly attempts to murder her supposed son in order to secure the
throne for Panthea, only to be frustrated by failure and Arbaces's
forgiveness.
But Gobrius has a more ornate scheme to resolve the crisis: he will
encourage the supposed siblings to fall into an incestuous passion for
one another, in order to facilitate their eventual marriage and the
restoration of right and stability to the throne. All goes according to
plan, but the suddenness of the plot's discovery and the
instantaneously harmonious marriage of the dethroned Arbaces and the
newly elevated Panthea has struck many readers as an unduly artificial
conclusion to the drama. That Gobrius and Arane have been such minor
figures in the drama, either off-stage or, in Gobrius's case,
colorless, exacerbates this impression; they appear to have been
included solely to provide the denouement of happy discovery.
By withholding the existence of the conspiracy throughout the play,
the authors have done more than engage its characters in an artificial
scenario; they have also forced the audience to rely upon its own
generic preconceptions in reading the characters, and given their
multiple cues to read Arbaces and Panthea as tragic figures, we will
almost certainly do so. It is on this point that Neill's reading of
the play as a portrait of "a heraclitan world" (27) appears
misguided; while its characters and audience experience the apparent
confusion of contradictory promptings and impulses, the play's many
reversals are in fact the result of a carefully sustained composition by
Gobrius, whose manipulations render what seems random to be in fact
predestined. Far from the chaos of profitable uncertainty propounded by
Montaigne, the world of the play is the result of a single absolute
truth (Arbaces's true parentage) disguised by a single lie, easily
revealed and, in being revealed, resolving all conflict between the
perspectives of its characters. That the lie encourages a conventionally
tragic consequence (Arbaces enters the final scene of the play intent on
murder, rape, and suicide), while the truth provides a comic one is part
of the play's generic criticism. Gobrius has constructed a plot of
deceptive identity that results in comedic consummation, but his pawns
are prompted by their conventional biases to read their situation as
tragic, and nearly achieve the destructive end of that genre. Neither
Gobrius's comic manipulations (which we must not forget are rooted
in treasonous deception) nor the tragic predispositions of the other
characters are offered as salutary perspectives.
Instead, the highly orchestrated scenario and the response of its
players, first to the tragic deception, and then to the comic
resolution, serve to remind us of the inadequacy of any response within
such artifice. Thanks to the generic cues of Mardonius and others, and
the revelation of Gobrius's elaborate scheme, we are perpetually
reminded of the theatrical nature of our engagement with the text.
Foster has noted this element in the play: "As spectators we share
in the theatrical self-consciousness of Fletcher's plays. But where
such self-conscious artistic design in Shakespearean tragicomedy evokes
providential design, the more attenuated form of metatheater in
Fletcher's tragicomedies points only to the author-ity of the
dramatist himself." (28) But where Foster reads this authorial
self-indication as a flaw of the play, I contend that this pointed
reminder is an essential element of its argument. The orchestrated
nature of the plot is confirmed by Arthur Mizener: "It is
impossible not to admire the ingenuity of [the play's]
construction; yet most readers will probably feel that it is more
ingenious than satisfying." (29) But given the degree to which the
play foregrounds the artifice of its generic circumstances, it may be
wondered whether it can be aesthetically or emotionally satisfying, and
whether this frustration is not, perhaps, the intended response of the
play's critical portrait of a generic basis for drama.
Many readers will, I suspect, regard the emotional elements of the
play as engaging, particularly the sufferings of Arbaces and Panthea.
The plot's artifice does not negate the subjective experience of
its characters, who do not regard their situation as artificial, and
whose passions are real enough to them, and to us if we do not know the
play's great secret. Yet given that secret--given the overarching
artifice that casts the lovers and their supporters in such false senses
of identity--can we regard their subjective reactions as objectively
meaningful? Beaumont and Fletcher do not make this question easy to
answer. William C. Woodson has noted that Gorbrius's scheme reduces
Arbaces and Panthea as pawns in a situation of artificial plot "in
which the young innocents are ... jeopardized by an alien and unwanted
desire." (30) But we ought to apply that situation not merely to
the hero and heroine, but to all the other characters of the play who
are not directly involved in the conspiracy. The entire Iberian court
and its foreign captives and visitors are under the same false
impression, and their contributions to the unfolding of the play are no
less maneuvered by an artificial reading of their situation.
While Woodson examines this false set of readings and responses in
terms of contemporary morality, I would argue that an equally valid
argument is being made in opposition to generic evaluation, inasmuch as
the characters who articulate the judgments of this situation and those
enmeshed in it are guided by principles that derive from the generic
indices of character. Woodson is correct in that the characters are
morally tested within what they believe to be a genuinely tragic
dilemma. The authors have not simply presented a play in which comedy is
disguised as tragedy, but one in which we are made to realize that if we
accept generic dictates as absolute, we are led inevitably to insist
upon those dictates, rather than seeking some other meaning in what we
experience.
Under this generic belief, for instance, Mardonius reads Arbaces
through the demands of appropriately kingly and brotherly behavior, and
condemns him for the erratic conduct that contradicts such demands. Such
condemnation is regularly expressed in a typology of character that
resembles the distinction demanded by a binary view of genre: "Thy
valour and thy passion severed would have made two excellent fellows in
their kinds. I know not whether I should be sorry thou art so valiant or
so passionate. Would one of 'em were away" (I.i. 171-76).
Mardonius believes Arbaces has the makings of a fine typological
specimen, either of boldness or of sentiment, but the king's
insistence on enacting a mixed mode of conduct corrupts the virtues of
both.
This condemnation of Arbaces's erratic behavior, by his
onstage companions and by subsequent critics of the play, begins with a
simple premise: an evaluation of character that privileges consistency
as its means of preferment. Arbaces cannot reconcile his desires and
impulses to his expected persona, but this inability appears, given the
untenably artificial demands of that persona, to render him the kind of
man idealized by Montaigne: "The most beautiful of souls are those
universal ones which are open and ready for anything, untaught perhaps
but not unteachable" (741). Unaware of his true nature, and limited
by the absolute expectations of others, he nevertheless strives
throughout to be genuine in his conduct, only to be represented as a
monster of inconstancy. Such is how he and the play must appear to those
whose doctrinal adherence cannot value the assertion of self in the face
of circumstances, however artificial. Since Arbaces is magnificent and
ludicrous, an evaluation that demands exclusivity must read one of these
two qualities as false, artificial, or erroneous, whether that
evaluation is Mardonius's or Thomas Rymer's: "And far
from decorum is it, that we find the King drolling and quibling with
Bessus and his Buffoons, and worse, that they should presume to break
their jests upon him." (31) It is significant that Rymer's
disdain for the character of Arbaces, the first major critical reaction
after Dryden (who approved of the play), is based on a similar premise,
echoing the criticism of Sidney--that Arbaces does not act as a king
ought to: "Kings of Tragedy are all Kings by the Poets Election,
and if such as these must be elected, certainly no Polish Diet would
ever suffer Poet to have a voice in choosing a King for them" (42).
Rymer's insistence on referring to the play as a tragedy largely
explains his displeasure, and from that critical perspective, he is
correct in his assessment of Arbaces, who refuses to display that
consistently heightened state of conduct and expression that tragedy
demands of its kingly heroes.
But we may reflect Rymer's criticism back onto the text to
recognize that Mardonius's reading of Arbaces is itself tragic in
nature. By demanding absolute consistency of conduct, Mardonius cannot
help but read Arbaces's behavior as erratic, and to read such
erraticism as a self-destructive flaw of character. Thus,
Mardonius's expectations and assessment of Arbaces's
character--that it should be a pure instance of his role as
king--resembles a criticism of Fletcher's portrait of Arbaces, as
Rymer's reaction confirms.
Arbaces's response to this judgment, seen within this
genetically insistent context, suggests less erratic self-indulgence and
more a sympathetic desire to assert his own identity independently of
generic restrictions: "Will you confine my words? By heaven and
earth, /I were much better be a king of beasts than such a people"
(I.233-35). (32) There is an obvious political context to the speech; a
king who is subject to the judgment of his inferiors is no true king,
and among beasts, who lack context to render judgment, he can be more
himself. (In his invocation of beasts, there is also a suggestion of
Adamic identity, in which Arbaces, as the solely human arbiter of
meaning, is one who bestows it, rather than receives it.) His perverse
determination suggests a tragic hero's hubris, but also the
instinct of a man who, as the plot reveals, is often instinctively in
the right, only to be perpetually told that he is in the wrong.
And his present submission proves to be as much a failure as his
earlier inconsistency; after this attempt at self-assertion, his
response to Mardonius's complaint is total capitulation. Falling
into a lower register, Arbaces submits himself to his subordinate's
assessment: "Thou has spoken truth, and boldly, such a truth / As
might offend another. I have been / Too passionate and idle; thou shalt
see / A swift amendment" (I.i.385-88). But this capitulation, too,
is further evidence of his erraticism; by refusing to maintain his right
to be as prideful as he pleases, he veers from hubris to abjection.
Within the confines of an order that demands consistency, Arbaces cannot
succeed even by repentant reversal. Having been established as one who
is an inappropriate mixture of qualities, he cannot be consistently
himself without confirming this diagnosis; only a different frame of
meaning can sustain his identity as something other than inadequate.
Such is the equivalent predicament of tragicomedy under the generic
rubric, its portrait of an inconsistently provocative cosmos rendering
it faulty, no matter how substantial the contradictory provocations may
be rendered.
Hunt correctly notes that "gradually the viewer realizes
during the performance of act I that Arbaces contains within himself the
fundamental conflict of the play." (33) I contend that this
conflict is between the insistence on a categorically generic
understanding of character, and an alternative insistence on a pliable
freedom from generic categorization, in recognition of the multiplicity
of experience. (34) Thus Arbaces's submission is carefully phrased
to show that he is aware of its artifice. While he succumbs to the terms
in which Mardonius would frame him, his conscientiousness cannot
entirely erase his conviction that he is not the character he is forced
to enact: "I want those parts / You praise me for"
(I.i.388-89). Arbaces's sense of self is perversely resistant to
the attempts of others to tell him what he is, and what he must be.
Within a generic structure of identity, he knows himself not to be his
own man, a conviction Fletcher quickly confirms by the crowd scene, in
which the king is diverted from his course by a collection of his
meanest subjects.
Arbaces identifies the flaw, both in Mardonius's criticism,
and in generic criticism in general, when he asserts that "Where
there is no difference in men's worths / Titles are jests"
(I.i.332-33). The concept of "worth," like that of value, is
based on the occupation of an identity. Unless rank is substantiated in
character, titles and the expectations that attend them are an occasion
for absurdity, and in Arbaces's case, both title and identity are
distinctly unsound. But this point is ignored consistently throughout A
King and No King, not simply by Mardonius, but by all those who reject
Arbaces's conduct as heterogenous, and attempt to steer him
squarely in a generically distinct type of character.
The subsequent colloquy between Arbaces and Panthea, isolated
momentarily from all those who attempt to shape their identities, is the
play's frankest confrontation with the failure of designation to
account for character. The two characterize their dilemma as one that
renders not their desire, but the designation of that desire, as
erroneous:
Arbaces: Is there no stop
To our full happiness but these mere sounds,
'Brother' and 'sister'?
Panthea: There is nothing else,
But these, alas, will separate us more
Than twenty worlds betwixt us.
Arbaces: I have lived
To conquer men and now am overthrown
Only by words, 'brother' and 'sister'. Where
Have these words dwelling? I will find 'em out
And utterly destroy them; but they are not to be grasped.
Let 'em be anything but merely voice.
Panthea: But 'tis not in the power of any force
Or policy to conquer them
(IV.iv. 112-28).
Intuitively, the two innocents are in the right, both in reading
their situation and in their instinctive rejection of its artifice.
Their colloquy here yields temporary but unsustainable refusal of their
instinctive desires, but their capitulation to nebulous authority will
drive Arbaces into tragic madness; when he next appears, it is with
sword in hand, determined to assert his character in the face of a
contrary designation--though even here, he continues to designate it and
himself in tragic terms.
His embrace of his tragic identity is the fulfillment of the choice
offered him by his two counselors in this matter: Mardonius and Bessus,
who, one after another, offer a reading of the situation. Mardonius,
predictably, designates the sexual desire as a tragic hamartia. Though
he initially gives the nod to political subservience ("You must
understand, nothing that you can utter can remove my love and service
from my prince"), he immediately undercuts this statement by
pressing his own, absolutist agenda: "But otherwise, I think I
shall not love you more; for you are sinful, and if you do this crime,
you ought to have no laws, for after this it will be great injustice in
you to punish any offender for any crime ... I feel I have not patience
to look on whilst you run these forbidden courses"
(III.iii.96-103). This course lays the pathway to despair;
Arbaces's instinctive reading of his relation to Panthea is too
powerful (and too accurate) to subside, even in the face of this
terrible condemnation. Although he is perpetually conceding
Mardonius's tragic characterization of the act, Beaumont and
Fletcher have him unable to resist his natural passion for Panthea.
But Fletcher is careful not to offer a comic reading of the
situation as a preferable one, as the subsequent scene with Bessus
reveals. Where Mardonius condemns the supposedly incestuous desire,
Bessus indulges it, reminding us that if the predetermination of tragedy
is bad, the predetermination of comedy is no better. The corrupt
casuistry of Bessus is decidedly nauseating; told of Arbaces's
desire, he readily encourages its fulfillment: "O, you would have a
bout with her? I'll do it, I'll do't, i'faith,"
adding, "And when this is dispatch'd, if you have a mind to
your mother, tell me, and you shall see I'll set it hard"
(III.iii. 150-72). Small wonder that Arbaces recoils from this
enablement: "Hast thou no greater sense of such a sin? / Thou art
too wicked for my company, / Though I have hell within me, and mayst yet
/ Corrupt me further ... Thou hast eyes / Like flames of sulphur, which,
methinks, do dart / Infection on me, and thou hast a mouth / Enough to
take me in, where they do stand / Four rows of iron teeth"
(III.iii. 156-64).
The hyperbole of this response is reflective of the degree to which
Arbaces has already begun, under Mardonius's influence, to read his
situation as irretrievably tragic, and his sense of Bessus as one who
would "corrupt" and "infect" him is entirely
reasonable under this assumption. But Bessus's advice, while
monstrous, is not that of a villain, but of an individual who is
fundamentally comic in his understanding of consequences. When Arbaces
challenges him with "Dost make no more on't?", Bessus
freely answers "More? No" (III.iii. 152-53). Bessus responds
with a comic character's unwitting sense of action as essentially
inconsequential. Taking a page from Restoration comedy rather than Greek
tragedy, he regards sexual transgression, even in extremity, as a light
matter, an attitude is keeping with his role as an undeniably comic
character. In his world, vice is met with kicks and insults rather than
death; his sense of consequence operates on the ameliorative scale of
comic punishment, rather than tragic devastation. Yet Arbaces is
undoubtedly right to be repulsed by Bessus; the suspension of generic
identity within the play and his own growing sense of himself as a
tragic figure would lead inexorably to his destruction, and a comic
resolution here is portrayed as fundamentally insensitive to the
severity of the action he contemplates.
The play thus rejects both tragic and comic characterizations of
its reading as inadequate; the former is moral judgment on a false
premise, the latter permissive regardless of circumstance. Neither will
achieve an honest and salutary solution to the dilemma. The play thus
argues, in the form of two generically minded and equally incompetent
advisers, that the ability to inform authority of its duties cannot
derive too much from, nor express itself in generic typology; again, we
are reminded that Fletcher's larger goal is a drama and an audience
healthy enough to offer and comprehend political commentary. And as bad
as Bessus is, Mardonius, the 'virtuous' adviser, is worse, for
it is his virtue that leads Arbaces astray. The more Mardonius reads
Arbaces as tragic, and the more he expresses this opinion to Arbaces,
the more he confines Arbaces's responses within a tragic framework
of self-interpretation.
The result of this 'help' appears in Arbaces's final
entrance, in which he declares his self-designation as finally, utterly
tragic:
It is resolved. I bore it whilst I could;
I can no more. Hell, open all thy gates,
And I will thorough them; if they be shut,
I'll batter 'em but I will find the place
Where the most damned have dwelling. Ere I end,
Amongst them all they shall not have a sin
But I may call it mine. I must begin
With murder of my friend, and so go on
To an incestuous ravishing, and end
My life and sin with a forbidden blow
Upon myself
(V.iv.1-11)
This Senecan pronouncement, which by this point reads like a
hysterical surrender to the tragic telos, has the hyperbole of satire,
and its critical nature is confirmed as Mardonius enters with "What
tragedy is near?" (V.iv.12), a line that reads as cruelly witty,
given that this outcome is precisely the one he has striven so hard to
achieve.
But Fletcher once again subverts the emotional momentum of the
action, since this apocalyptic sentiment is immediately dispersed by
Gobrius's lengthy confession, and is quickly followed by universal
rejoicing, Arbaces finally answering the riddle of the play's title
by declaring "Come every one / That takes delight in goodness; help
me sing / Loud thanks for me, that I am proved no king"
(V.iv.356-57). As noted by the play's critics, the cleverness of
the conclusion does little to mask its artifice, and this problem is
exacerbated by the unreflective nature of the characters' reaction
to their new circumstances, and to the errors that all of them have been
engaged in. Only Arbaces, significantly, admits his wrongdoing.
This conclusion infuriated Rymer because, according to the laws of
ancient tragedy, Arbaces (and perhaps Panthea) ought to have died for
entertaining the sin of incestuous desire. (35) But his reading insists
that their sin, even if represented under false pretenses (they are,
after all, not siblings) must follow the prescribed course of its
presentation as 'true' incest. But the play rebuts this
assertion; what seems like casuistry between the frustrated lovers in
justifying their passion is the desired result of Gobrius's
plot--they have, therefore, behaved correctly in achieving a harmonious
conclusion. But Rymer's frustration is understandable, inasmuch as
the degree to which the characters receive the news contains no
resentment or criticism of Gobrius's manipulations. The Protector
goes so far as to declare, in his confession, "Sir, I hate a lie /
As I love God and honesty" (V.iv.100-101)--an absurd statement,
given that the entirety of the action is based on his deception. Yet no
one questions the moral or political correctness of his fraud. Instead,
with universal rejoicing, all the characters embrace the artificial
solution of comedy with an emotional readiness that understandably rings
false. And such, I contend, is the point. Fleeing from a tragic
denouement, they embrace a comic one, but the revolting premises of
treason, violence, planned rape, and incest render this conclusion
equally repulsive. A comic conclusion may be emotionally preferable--joy
is invariably preferable to misery--but it is as artificial as the
tragic conclusion, based on a lie, would have been.
In the hollow but vociferous rejoicing that results from the
revelation of Arbaces's true parentage, the authors present their
final argument against generic prescription. And this rejection of the
generic telos suggests that, rather than a tragicomedy in the vein of
Philaster, A King and No King may be something else: a play that rejects
the significance of generic assignment. For if the play argues that
genre inevitably leads to a popular and critical prejudice against what
may or may not be done and said, and against characters who are anything
more than the fulfillment of those prejudices of consistency, then to
call the play even something as loosely categorical as a tragicomedy is
to ignore its argument. Rather, the authors appear to offer a play
without genre, a dramatic mode in which inconsistency is not evidence of
a lack of disciplined perspective, but of the artistic assertion that
such discipline invariably leads to an inorganic confirmation of
prejudice. A King and No King argues that only through unrestricted
self-knowledge can action that is truly representative of character be
taken. But generic unity corrupts this process, as illustrated by
Arbaces's victimized mischaracterization throughout the action.
The play reveals, then, the false necessity of generic absolutism,
and its hero, simultaneously but not unnaturally ridiculous and
terrifying, comic and heroic, is an embodiment of an attempt to achieve
an exceptional path towards the virtue of self-consciousness. Arbaces
fails, of course, as this reading has shown. He is subsumed into comedy
by the conclusion, one which gratifyingly ignores his seemingly
monstrous determination to defy moral order, and simply ushers him into
a happy marriage and a more securely-worn crown. Genre is offered here
as an influence that, once introduced, inescapably confines the
understanding of character and action.
The implications of this argument for the political commentary
within drama are profound. If an over-reliance on genre eliminates the
personal from the categorical, then a generically-based political
argument must ignore the human factor within political discourse. But if
the specificity of circumstance may--and usually does--demand a
recognition of the individual (whether that individual be author,
audience, or event), then an over-reliance on the generic as a means of
present or understanding the political is an unquestionably corrupting
influence. I do not believe that Fletcher--a professional artist, after
all--advocated the total rejection of precedent or intended the
abolition of genre, though this play may stray towards the polemic in
order to act as a corrective to a weighty opponent of tradition and
familiarity. Rather, A King and No King serves, as all good drama
should, as a medicinal reminder of the consequences of a limited
perspective.
Notes
(1.) William Proctor Williams, "Not Hornpipes and Funerals:
Fletcherian Tragicomedy" in Renaissance Tragicomedy: Explorations
in Genre and Politics ed. Nancy Klein Maguire (New York: AMS Press,
1987), 146.
(2.) Alastair Fowler, Kinds of Literature: An Introduction to the
Theory of Genres and Modes (Cambridge; MA: Harvard University Press,
1982), 38.
(3.) Fowler, Kinds of Literature, 88.
(4.) John T. Shawcross, "Tragicomedy as Genre, Past and
Present" in Renaissance Tragicomedy, 24.
(5.) The Faithful Shepherdess in The Dramatic Works in the Beaumont
and Fletcher Canon, ed. Fredson Bowers (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1966), III, 497.
(6.) Ibid.
(7.) The concept of genre defined by popular expectation and
reception is further confirmed by the commentary of clergyman Samuel
Harsnett, identified and discussed by Herbert Barry. See Barry,
"Italian Definitions of Tragedy and Comedy" SEL 14:2, 179-87.
(8.) Una Ellis-Fermor's condemnation of the
collaborator's canon exemplifies the older tradition of criticism
in this vein. See The Jacobean Drama: An Interpretation (London: Methuen
& Co. Ltd., 1947), 25-27. Subsequent criticism has, of course, led
to a more appreciative approach the works Ellis-Fermor so derides, but
the tradition has been slow to yield its interpretive grip. Even later
critics like Danby, who attempt to mollify this disdain, acknowledge
that they are swimming upstream against the deficiencies of the plays.
See Poets on Fortune's Hill (Port Washington NY: Kennikat Press,
1966), 181-3.
(9.) His audience's approach appears more ecumenical; let the
play be what it will in terms of argument or narrative architecture,
they will be content so long as it contains those performative hallmarks
they expect and enjoy.
(10.) We might characterize the difference of tragedy and comedy as
a choice between Platonic or Ciceronian dialectic.
(11.) Eugene Waith, The Pattern of Tragicomedy in Beaumont and
Fletcher (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1952), 5.
(12.) T. S. Eliot, Elizabethan Essays (London: Faber & Faber
Ltd., 1934), 78.
(13.) Waith, Pattern of Tragicomedy, 40.
(14.) Waith, 41.
(15.) Gordon McMullan, The Politics of Unease in the Plays of John
Fletcher (Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press, 1994), 65-67.
(16.) Michael Neill, "The Defense of Contraries: Skeptical
Paradox in A King and No King," SEL 21 (1981), 321.
(17.) Michel de Montaigne, The Complete Essays trans. M. A. Screech
(London: Penguin Books, 1987), 373.
(18.) Verna Foster, "Ford's Experiments in Tragicomedy:
Shakespearean and Fletcherian Dramaturgies" in Waith, Renaissance
Tragicomedy, 100.
(19.) George Puttenham, The Art of English Poesy ed. Frank Whigham
and Wayne A. Rebhom (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2007),
348-89.
(20.) Ibid, 360.
(21.) Bacon follows this train of criticism in identifying his
Idols of Tribe, Cave, Market-place and Theatre, noting that the
precedent not simply of learning but of personal experience often leads
the judgment astray from the true nature of die object of examination.
See Novum Organum, trans. and ed. Peter Urbach and John Gibson (Chicago,
II: Open Court, 1994), 60-67.
(22.) It should be added that Tigranes, previously sworn to his
countrywoman, Spaconia, is far from pleased at being recast in the role
of Panthea's intended. In enforcing the comic requirements of
castigation, reconciliation, and marriage onto the uncomfortably
individual Tigranes, Arbaces is already illustrating the inadequacy of a
generic approach to the personal, reminiscent of the Duke's
assignment of mercy and Mariana to the self-condemning Angelo in Measure
for Measure.
(23.) A King and No King ed. Lee Bliss (Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 2004) II.ii. 106-8. All references to the play will be
to this edition, identified parenthetically by act, scene, and line
number. I have elected to use this edition, rather than the Bowers,
because it is the most recent critical edition and therefore reflects
additional scholarship.
(24.) Montaigne, Complete Essays, 374.
(25.) Philip Sidney, A Defense of Poetry ed. J. A. Van Dorsten
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1966), 36. Subsequent references will
be to this edition, identified by page number.
(26.) Maurice Hunt, "Conquering Words in 'A King and No
King'" South Central Review 7:4 (Winter 1990), 25.
(27.) Neill, "Defesus of Conltaries," 321.
(28.) Vema A. Foster, "Sex Averted or Converted: Sexuality and
Tragicomic Genre in the Plays of Fletcher," SEL 32:2, 320-1.
(29.) Arthur Mizener, "The High Design of A King and No
King," Modern Philology 38:2, 139.
(30.) William C. Woodson, "The Casuistry of Innocence in A
King and No King," ELR 8 (1978), 314.
(31.) Thomas Rymer, "The Tragedies of the Last Age" in
The Critical Works of Thomas Rymer ed. Curt A. Zimansky (New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1956), 44. All references to Rymer will be to
this edition. In fairness to Rymer, he urges that Arbaces ought have
been given a duality of character: "Arbaces should have been
consider'd in a double capacity; he should have been endu'd
with all the greatness of mind, and generosity of a King, and also with
the modesty of a Subject." (43-44) But even here Rymer is insisting
on a decorum of character based on generic typology; he insists on
calling the play a tragedy, and his scathing evaluation is guided
largely by what he perceives as its many failures to sustain the
typological demands of that genre.
(32.) The first Quarto's version of the line reads
"While," rather than "Will," resulting in a
statement rather than a sentence: "While you confine my words, by
heaven and earth, / I were much better be a king of beasts / Than such a
people." Quartos 2-8, however, amend the line as presented here,
and I agree with this editorial correction. In either case, the
sentiment of the line--Arbaces's resentment at limits to his
self-expression placed on him by his inferiors--is unchanged.
(33.) Hunt, "Conquering Words," 25.
(34.) Again, Neill's identification of the play's
Montaignean elements is validated.
(35.) Rymer, "Traegdis of the Lost Age," 48-50.