Language and Politics in the Sixteenth-Century History Play.
Lucas, Scott
Language and Politics in the Sixteenth-Century History Play, by
Dermot Cavanagh. New York: Palgrave, 2003. Pp. x + 197. Cloth, $65.00.
Dermot Cavanagh pursues two announced projects in Language and
Politics in the Sixteenth-Century History Play. First, Cavanagh seeks to
"resuscitate" and to reconfigure the concept of the
sixteenth-century history play as a critical category. Second, Cavanagh
argues that the six Tudor dramas he studies each presents critical
reflections upon the "topic" of "socially disruptive
speech" (6). Cavanagh's pursuit of the first of these projects
is successful and compelling; his pursuit of the second is often
fruitful but at times raises more questions about his thesis than his
relatively brief study can answer.
In the first of these endeavors, Cavanagh argues that critics
should come to think of the genre of the sixteenth-century history play
as "ideologically various, theatrically diverse, and as committed
to political enquiry as much as to sermonizing" (3). Scholars
should expand their sense of what counts as a history play beyond
familiar chronicle histories to encompass any Tudor drama set in an
English, Scottish, or early "British" past. The goal of this
reconception is to bring all sixteenth-century plays that are set
against British history into dialogue with one another, no matter if
such plays are usually treated as tragedies, romances, or as some other
generic form.
Following his own call, Cavanagh brings together several dramas not
always grouped with one another, namely Bale's King Johan,
Sackville's and Norton's Gorboduc, Greene's Scottish
History of James IV, and Shakespeare's King John, Richard II, and
Henry V. The chief element that links all of these works, Cavanagh
argues, is their authors' interest in "socially disruptive
speech," specific terms and modes of discourse that play key roles
in the political conflicts these dramas portray. In his readings of
these plays, Cavanagh shows how each playwright builds into his work
recognizable modes of controversial political (or politicized)
discourse. Such language, Cavanagh demonstrates, often plays key roles
in the development of the action of these works and creates important
tensions in and among the characters forced to confront such disruptive
speech. Cavanagh's attention to the shared employment of
"disruptive language" in these works persuasively bolsters his
call to juxtapose works such as these and to study them as a group.
Cavanagh's true test case for his realignment of the
history-play idea is Robert Greene's Scottish History of James IV.
Greene's play is usually not considered to be a history play, since
it has little other than its title of the actually
"historical" in it. While acknowledging that the play gives
itself over in great measure to comedy, jigging, and a
"romantic," melodramatic plot that has nothing to do with the
actual James IV's career, Cavanagh makes a strong case for its
consideration as a "history play," one Greene consciously
shapes to respond to the growing vogue for chronicle histories in the
late 1580s and 1590s. As Cavanagh notes, even among his other matter,
Greene incorporates much material into his play about the nature of
international conflict, dynastic difficulties, the danger of malicious
counsel, and the role of "monarchical speech in precipitating
political crisis," themes the play shares with chronicle history
plays (61). Greene counters the increasingly dominant chronicle-history
form, however, by shaping James IV to address these concerns in
specifically personal terms, embedding them in traditionally
"romantic" situations involving matters such as love, lust,
marriage, and the conflicts of the domestic sphere. With its strong
emphasis on "private" matters, Cavanagh shows, the play makes
its chief lesson that of the political importance of personal temperance and civility. In his study of the play, Cavanagh reveals how Greene
handles many of the same important political questions treated by
chronicle histories and thus convincingly shows why a
"romance" such as Greene's should be thought of as a
history play just as much as any of the chronicle histories of
Greene's contemporaries.
While Cavanagh's first project is thoroughly compelling, his
second critical endeavor is mixed in its success. Moving beyond
identifying the presence of socially disruptive modes of discourse as a
formal hallmark of the newly reconceived history play genre, Cavanagh
argues that such language is present in many historically based works
because the authors of these plays use their dramas as spaces for
"critical reflection" on the very nature of such language (6).
In his introduction, Cavanagh argues that each of the dramas he studies
in Language and Politics in the Sixteenth-Century History Play treat
"disruptive speech" as a "topic" to be considered in
a critical and often meditative manner in order to present to audiences
truths about the very nature of the discourses the works portray (6).
Cavanagh's assertion of such a reflective dimension to the
plays he examines seems convincing in his studies of Shakespeare's
King John, Richard II, and Henry V. In the fourth chapter of his study,
Cavanagh shows how Shakespeare's King John is marked by the
scandalous subject matter and disruptive language associated in the
early modern period with popular rumor. In King John, Shakespeare makes
the sorts of unsubstantiated assertions, scandalous accusations, and
wild, disruptive language that Tudor officers so often identified as
producing disorder and discontent in the realm the very matter of high
politics. The claims to the English crown advanced in this play are
often asserted and contested through exchanges of libelous accusations
and harsh invective, types of speech whose language, like that of
popular rumors, can be deplored but whose charges cannot fully be
refuted. Rumor swirls around all the events of the play, and even King
John gains information about his own concerns through irregular,
unconventional means. Cavanagh shows how Shakespeare employs facets of
"disruptive" and often demonized speech in his drama and how,
by placing such demonized patterns of speech at the very heart of power
in England, provides audiences with a "searching account of how
multiple forms of social, political, and religious authority are claimed
and contested" (102).
In chapter 5, Cavanagh traces Shakespeare's employment of the
language of treason and loyalty in Richard II to show the dramatic
impact of the competing demands for loyalty between the erring and,
later, deposed King Richard and the newly crowned King Henry. Noting
that "there was no more devastating instance of injurious speech in
early modem English than to be condemned as a 'traitor' and no
clearer demonstration of the relationship between language and power
than the ability to ascribe this term successfully," Cavanagh
highlights the stakes of successfully imposing one's own definition
of treason on others in the play (103). In portraying the competition
over the definition of treason in Richard II, Shakespeare, Cavanagh
asserts, presents viewers with important food for thought about the very
notion of "treason" in itself. From the beginning of Richard
II, Cavanagh shows, the nature of political betrayal is uncertain: is it
a more general violation of "honour and fealty" or is it an
offense specifically against the "king's person and
will"? (105). The struggle later in the play becomes one over the
ability to charge treason and, thereby, to constitute one's
authority, as the new Henry IV must transfer the idea of loyalty due to
a king from Richard II to himself, a man who earlier bore the stigma of
being called a traitor. Throughout this work, Cavanagh convincingly
suggests, Shakespeare does not define a controlling viewpoint, but lets
audiences question the true definition of treason and to whom loyalty is
properly owed.
Chapter 6 turns attention to Shakespeare's Henry V. Here,
Cavanagh focuses on Shakespeare's interest in attempts to
"reform" demotic and turbulent language. Shakespeare portrays
the language of Henry V as an agent of reform for those under him, and
presents in the play the spectacle of "the King's English triumphing over foreign or irresponsible speakers" (128). Yet
Shakespeare builds into his work persistent ambiguities surrounding this
triumph, as the speech of Henry's subjects throughout the drama
serve to limit the authority of the monarch's dominant discourse.
It is Henry's inspiring, elevated words, Cavanagh argues, that
tempers the often excessive, "turbulent" impulses of the other
characters and shapes them into proper subjects of their monarch. Yet
the "disruptive" speech of such figures never quite leaves the
play but persists as a reminder of the sometimes less-than-ethical
events the king's discourse seeks to hide. Williams's portrait
of the savagery of war and the often doubtful nature of a king's
claims, for instance, continues to limit Henry's attempt fully to
overwhelm the persistently questioning and even accusatory language of
those under him. The demotic speech Shakespeare builds into his play
offers an ethical critique of the privileged rhetoric of the
"King's English" even as the play acknowledges the power
of that language to dominate and to a great extent shape those who exist
under the monarch who employs it.
While Cavanagh's readings of Shakespeare are often compelling,
his studies of Bale's King Johan and Sackville's and
Norton's Gorboduc are more problematic. Neither of these texts--nor
Greene's James IV for that matter--presents itself on its face as
particularly meditative or ambiguous in its treatment of the discourses
it incorporates. Further, the "insights" Cavanagh suggests
these works are meant to reveal to viewers do not always seem either
insightful or revelatory, given the audiences to which they were
directed.
In his chapter on Bale, Cavanagh sets out to examine what he calls
the "paradox of sedition" in King Johan (16). Cavanagh argues
that the Elizabethan text of King Johan (the revised version of
Bale's original Henrician drama) reveals its author's
"complex form of historical awareness," specifically
Bale's "bitter understanding that the category of sedition can
be used to incriminate godly speech" (17). Because of this
knowledge, Cavanagh declares, "King Johan's polemical assurance is offset by Bale's insistent recognition of the power of
catholicism" to demonize the godly in the eyes of others (30).
Further, the chief antagonist Sedition's habit of revealing the
"sinful and partisan" nature of the Catholic (or even
Anglo-Catholic) Church conveys "an unsettling proximity between
Bale's polemical intentions and the Vice's effects,"
since Sedition, a Catholic character, makes Bale's anti-Catholic
points for him through his revelation of the malice and sins of the
Church (20). By naming his character Sedition and having Sedition make
the charges of evangelicals against Catholics for him, Bale, Cavanagh
suggests, exposes "the ambivalent potential" of the concept of
sedition itself and thus unsettles audiences even as he seeks to win
them to his anti-Catholic side (38).
To be fully persuasive, both Cavanagh's suggestion that
Bale's text presents the "ambivalent potential of
sedition" and his assertion that Bale's polemic is undercut by
having Sedition as one of its spokesmen need more support than Cavanagh
provides. First, the power of the Catholic Church (or even the
Anglo-Catholic Church) to demonize evangelicals as "seditious"
would not seem to trouble the polemical assurance of Bale's play
but instead would seem to reinforce it. It is precisely Bale's
fervent belief in the ability of lying Catholics to seduce English kings
into both undermining their own authority and into persecuting
Christ's truly faithful (i.e., evangelicals) that leads Bale so
fervently to seek to expose in King Johan the seditious depredations of
the Church. Charges of sedition against the godly would not lead Bale to
reflect upon the very concept of sedition, since for the supremely
confident and remarkably unreflective Bale such charges are simply
devilish lies, falsehoods that, even when endorsed by the monarch
himself, have no relation to the true meaning of "sedition."
Nor does the fact that Sedition reveals his own crimes seem to add
ambiguity to Bale's play or work to unsettle Bale's intended
audiences. Anti-Catholic literature of the time is full of Roman
Catholic characters openly admitting their sins, a habit granted to them
not only as a means to reveal secret crimes but also to suggest the
brazen and even boastingly sinful nature of the "minions of the
Pope." Finally, even if there were compelling evidence that Bale
wishes audiences to muse on the "the ambivalent potential of
sedition," one must simply wonder at what point in viewing this
angry, insistent, and self-righteous work Bale thought audiences might
stop to meditate upon such ambiguities. Throughout the play, Bale pulls
out all the stops in creating his polemical attack on the Church and its
alleged depredations. There seems to be little space for viewers to rest
and to reflect in the endless hurly-burly, slander, accusations, and
(toward the end) pathos his play provides.
Similarly problematic is Cavanagh's treatment of
Sackville's and Norton's Gorboduc as a work designed to offer
a deliberative exploration of the problems of counsel. Cavanagh begins
his study of this tragedy by arguing against the idea of Gorboduc as a
didactic work. Instead, Cavanagh insists, the play is a meditative
exploration of the "topic" of "destructive political
language" in the discourses of political counsel. In his reading of
the play, Cavanagh correctly notes that much of Gorboduc is given over
to lengthy speeches of advice by various characters, all of which seem
entirely persuasive and well supported even as they contradict one
another. The fact that each of the several different advisors who weigh
in on the question of Gorboduc's succession plans seems to offer a
compelling argument for his views highlights the difficulty faced by any
ruler to distinguish between good political advice and bad or obtuse counsel. The problem is compounded, Cavanagh also notes, by the fact
that unfolding political events can transform what was good counsel in
an earlier set of circumstances into ill advice. Cavanagh argues that
Sackville and Norton wrote Gorboduc to reveal to viewers such truths and
to guide their audience to meditate upon them.
Once again, one must entertain questions about Cavanagh's
assertions. First, one wonders for whom Sackville and Norton might have
thought the "insights" Cavanagh ascribes to their play would
be either new or revelatory. The authors' original audiences were
composed of Inns of Court men, English magistrates, and Queen Elizabeth herself. Each audience member was highly trained in rhetoric and thus
well aware of the ability of rhetoric to make contradictory views seem
equally appealing. Further, those viewing the play had lived through the
astonishing and often rapid ideological upheavals of the past decade,
the wrenching changes England endured through the successive reigns of
King Edward, Queen Jane, Queen Mary, and Queen Elizabeth. Which of the
audience members would have needed Sackville and Norton to reveal to him
or her the notion that changing historical circumstances can render what
seemed good counsel in one set of circumstances suddenly bad? Finally,
and most surprisingly, Cavanagh is able to mount his argument that
Gorboduc is a meditative rather than a didactic or persuasive text only
by ignoring the words of the Chorus, a figure who quite openly describes
Gorboduc as seeking to teach a specific political lesson. It is
difficult to read the Chorus's declaration in act 1 that "this
great king, that doth divide his land / ... / A mirror shall become to
princes all / To learn to shun the cause of such a fall" without
concluding that Gorboduc seeks to teach its viewers proper courses of
action through the negative exemplum of its erring king.
Indeed, if each of Gorboduc's advisors couches his advice
about the succession in equally persuasive terms, as Cavanagh suggests,
the play nevertheless provides a guide for choosing a course of action,
namely, that when in doubt, a monarch should stick with the customary
form of rule and succession. It is Gorboduc's abandonment of the
traditional ideas of living out his reign and passing on his kingdom to
a single heir that causes all of the problems that follow in the play
and makes him an admonitory "mirror" to others. Remarkably,
Cavanagh never confronts these words of the Chorus in his study; rather,
in a three-sentence paragraph, he simply dismisses the messages of the
Chorus and dumb shows alike as unimportant to viewers' reception of
the deliberative process dramatized in the play (41). In his reading of
Gorboduc, Cavanagh does offer a compelling description of how Sackville
and Norton use the language of counsel to develop the tension and
dramatic action of their play. However, his assertion that the play is
best understood as a meditation upon the nature of counsel itself
remains in need of more argument to become persuasive.
Cavanagh's book should be read for its call for a new
understanding of the sixteenth-century history play and for its shrewd
recognition of the centrality of modes of "socially disruptive
speech" as a formal element in many plays incorporating historical
material. While his assertion of critical reflection in several of the
texts he studies in Language and Politics in the Sixteenth-Century
History Play is more problematic, his studies of Shakespeare's
reflections upon recognizable modes of disruptive discourse will provide
readers with valuable insight both into Shakespeare's plays and
Shakespeare's thoughts upon language.
Reviewer: SCOTT LUCAS