Presidential power and national security.
Sofaer, Abraham D.
This issue of Presidential Studies Quarterly examines the powers of
the president of the United States to deal with issues of national
security. The attacks on the United States of September 11, 2001 led to
claims and actions concerning presidential power that reignited this
enduring debate. Participants in this symposium have been asked to
answer the following questions:
1. Did the Framers adopt the British war model theory (Blackstone,
Locke)?
2. Does the theory of executive prerogative operate without limits
from the legislative and judicial branches?
3. What role did the Framers anticipate for the courts in matters
of war and national security?
4. What role did the Framers anticipate for Congress in matters of
war and national security?
5. What is the scope of the president's power as commander in
chief? That title provides unity of command and also assures civilian
supremacy over the military. What else? What are the limits, if any?
These are good questions. But abstract questions about the powers
allocated by the Constitution to the president, or to the other branches
of government, are by their nature inadequate vehicles for understanding
the meaning of the powers at issue. Abstract questions lead to abstract
answers, and to the unproductive tradition of cutting and pasting parts
of the Constitution and quotes from other sources while ignoring others,
to prove one position regarding presidential power or another. As
Justice Robert H. Jackson wrote in his famous concurring opinion in the
Steel Seizure case (Youngstown): "A century and a half of partisan
debate and scholarly speculation [concerning the Constitution's
separation of powers] yields no net result but only supplies more or
less apt quotations from respected resources on each side of any
question." (1) Attempts to explain executive power without at the
same time seeking to understand it in the context of legislative and
judicial power is an inherently flawed method for understanding how the
U.S. government works and was intended to work.
The Framers did not adopt any specific model of executive power in
shaping the presidency. They created an office with many though not all
the powers considered "executive" in the Blackstone model,
including the powers to interpret and execute laws and treaties, handle
the country's international relations, and act as commander in
chief. They gave other "executive" powers to Congress,
however, including the powers to declare war, issue letters of marque
and reprisal, confirm executive appointments, and suspend the writ of
habeas corpus. At the same time, the Framers gave the president the
legislative power to veto laws, and they gave powers to both the
Congress and (less explicitly) to the courts which enable those branches
as well to approve, disapprove, or check the exercise of executive
authority over national security issues.
The resulting overlap of authority in the Constitution stems from
the Framers' acceptance of the British view that liberty can only
be effectively preserved by having not only separate branches (as
recommended by Montesquieu, Locke, and Blackstone, among others) but
also by mixing in each branch aspects of all the forms of
power--legislative, executive, and judicial (Bailyn 1968, 20-23). What
this meant in terms of British constitutional history is that the king
could be criticized or impeached for conduct that fell within the Royal
Prerogative, because Parliament had its own, independent powers over the
same subjects on which the king had power to act. On the other hand, it
also meant that the king could act unilaterally in areas of his
authority, despite the fact that Parliament had the power to prevent his
action but had flailed to do so.
The Framers explicitly relied on the mixing of powers in the
Constitution as a substitute for what James Madison in Federalist nos.
48 and 51 cited as the inadequate "parchment barriers" of
constitutional prohibitions or enumerations. As opposed to
"exterior" means, an effective or "interior
structure" could be created in several ways, he noted, but the
"great security" was to give each branch the constitutional
means and the personal motives to resist encroachments on its functions
by the others. It is in making this point--the need for overlapping
authority to enhance the capacity in each branch to resist the
others--that Madison wrote: "Ambition must be made to counteract
ambition. The interests of the man must be connected to the rights of
the place." The Framers deliberately used conflicting grants of
authority as a supplement to their use of prohibitions and limitations
in the Constitution in order to create separate branches that would be
capable of defending their respective roles (Sofaer 1976, 41-43).
The system that resulted cannot effectively be described through
abstract pronouncements about the powers of particular branches over
particular functions. The powers at issue are properly understood as
they relate to each other, as part of a system of deliberately mixed
authorities.
The principal advantage in understanding executive power within its
intended constitutional context is that it undermines the extravagant
claims that abstract definitions of the powers of any particular branch
facilitate. Claims that the Framers intended to create a
"unitary" executive underlie the recent wave of assertions
that the president has all the inherent and exclusive powers he and his
lawyers consider necessary to win the War on Terror. These claims have
often been baseless. But the practice of advancing claims of inherent
and "exclusive" executive powers should be no surprise given
the durability of equally baseless arguments that favor legislative
power. Among these is the assertion that the president can only engage
in military actions with the prior approval of Congress expressed in the
particular form of a declaration of war or in the specific form required
by the War Powers Resolution. The situations are highly analogous. Both
sets of claims are based on abstract definitions of powers assigned to
one branch or the other. Both disregard the mixed nature of the
constitutional system. Both ignore authoritative precedents established
and repeatedly reaffirmed over two hundred years. Both would unravel the
Framers' scheme to prevent absolute control by any one branch over
the others. Thankfully, neither has been taken seriously enough to pose
a threat to the constitutional system.
The mixed system of government intended by the Framers is
instructively reflected in the handling of a national security crisis
during the earliest times of our constitutional government, when
President George Washington declared and attempted to enforce neutrality
in 1793. Some 160 years later, Justice Jackson explained how this scheme
is best applied in evaluating the exercise of executive authority. These
precedents explain how the Constitution assigns all three branches
powers that can lawfully be exercised in a manner that affects the
exercise by the other branches of all their assigned powers, even
exclusive ones.
George Washington's Proclamation
The proclamation issued by President Washington in 1793, commonly
known as the "neutrality" proclamation, demonstrated that
overlapping powers were assigned by the Constitution to all the branches
that bear upon war-related matters. It is rich in issues that remain
relevant, and its participants were among the principal Framers of the
Constitution. (2)
President Washington learned by April 12, 1793 that France had
declared war on England and other states. He left Mt. Vernon immediately
for Philadelphia, then the nation's capital, to deal with the
crisis this situation created. The United States had treaties with
France that could be construed to require actions that would give
England grounds for declaring war. The Treaty of Amity and Commerce provided for the reciprocal use by the parties of each other's
ports to carry in prizes, and each party was to deny this privilege to
an enemy of the other. In addition, the parties agreed to disallow the
use by an enemy of either party of its ports for fitting out privateers,
selling prizes, or routine purchase of food. Many Americans had already
begun to help France by getting their vessels designated as French
privateers or by preparing French vessels for naval action.
The United States had several options, including siding with France
or England, remaining neutral, or doing nothing. The president wanted to
keep the United States out of the war. When he arrived in Philadelphia,
he sent a list of questions to his cabinet, including whether a
proclamation of neutrality should issue, the meaning and applicability
of the French-American treaties, and whether to call Congress back into
special session. At the same time, he instructed Secretary of State
Thomas Jefferson and Secretary of the Treasury Alexander Hamilton to
prepare measures to keep American citizens from embroiling the United
States with either France or England.
Jefferson urged the president not to declare
"neutrality," as such an act could be considered legislation
and therefore in violation of the lawmaking power exclusively assigned
to Congress. At a cabinet meeting on April 19, the president decided
with the unanimous support of his cabinet to issue a proclamation
establishing neutrality as national policy, but without using the word
"neutrality" in it. This nuanced action reflected the fact
that the word "neutrality" had specific meaning in
international law, and therefore that its inclusion would have more
clearly resembled lawmaking. The cabinet also voted unanimously against
calling Congress back early; Jefferson concurred despite having earlier
written to James Madison, then in the House of Representatives, that he
supposed "Congress would be called, because it [complying with
prohibitions against supplying the French] is a justifiable cause of war
& as the Executive cannot ... decide the question of war on the
affirmative side, neither ought it to do so on the negative side, by
preventing the competent body from deliberating on the question"
(Ford 1895, 6: 192). All members of the cabinet supported the
president's exercise of discretion in deciding not to call Congress
into special session, despite the fact that Congress could exercise its
assigned powers only after it returned.
The president issued "A Proclamation" on April 22, 1793.
It did not use the word "neutrality," but it declared that it
was the "duty and interest" of the United States to
"pursue a conduct friendly and impartial toward the belligerent
Powers." In addition, the proclamation warned Americans to refrain
from conduct that violated the national policy that had been declared
and specified two remedial measures. First, those who rendered
themselves "liable to punishment under the law of nations" for
violating duties associated with U.S. policy "will not receive the
protection of the United States, against such punishment or
forfeiture." This remedy went unchallenged as being within the
president's power to implement. The proclamation also stated that
the president had authorized criminal prosecutions against those who
violated "the laws of nations": "I have given
instructions to those officers to whom it belongs, to cause prosecutions
to be instituted against all persons, who shall, within the cognizance of the Courts of the United States, violate the laws of nations, with
respect to the powers at war, or any of them" (Fitzpatrick 1939,
32: 430-31). This remedy rested on the claimed power to prosecute
individuals in the federal courts for crimes not created by legislation.
The president possessed the exclusive power to receive ambassadors
and Hamilton proposed that France's new ambassador, Edmund Charles
Genet, be received with a warning that the U.S.-French treaties might be
temporarily or provisionally suspended, in order to avoid suggesting to
England that the United States regarded France as an ally. Jefferson
urged, however, that receiving Genet only meant that his government was
recognized and that the treaties could be interpreted in a manner
consistent with neutrality. To withhold compliance with the treaties
without just cause or compensation, he argued, would "give to
France a cause of war, and so become associated in it on the other
side." Washington accepted Jefferson's position, ordering that
neither England nor France was to fit out privateers in U.S. ports.
Particularly difficult issues in enforcing the proclamation
concerned an English merchant vessel, Little Sarah, which was seized in
early May 1793 by a French privateer outfitted in Charleston, South
Carolina in violation of neutrality, brought into Philadelphia, fitted
out as a privateer, and renamed Little Democrat. England demanded that
the vessel be returned. Hamilton favored restitution, but Jefferson
urged that an apology should suffice. If the commission given the
commander of the privateer that seized the vessel was illegal, Jefferson
argued, then the courts would order restitution; and if the case were
important enough to require reprisal, "Congress must be called on
to take it; the right of reprisal being expressly lodged with them by
the constitution, not with the executive." Washington agreed not to
order restitution, but ordered that all illegally equipped privateers
"should depart from the ports of the United States" (Ford
1895, 6: 257-59, 282). Minister Genet ignored this order, and the Little
Democrat was transformed into a fourteen-gun warship, with equipment
purchased in the United States and a partially U.S. crew.
On July 8, Hamilton and Secretary of War Henry Knox voted at a
cabinet meeting at which Washington was absent to establish a battery at
a point between Philadelphia and the sea, in order to stop Little
Democrat if it should attempt to depart before the president's
return. Jefferson opposed the use of force without the president's
approval, though he agreed the U.S. attorney for the district should be
informed that Americans might be serving on the vessel so he could
"take measures for apprehending and bringing them to trial"
(Ford 1895, 6: 340-44). Washington was angered at Genet's defiance
of the administration's orders and disappointed that Jefferson had
not taken action. Jefferson at that point agreed the vessel should be
stopped in order to remove improperly installed armaments, but by then
it was beyond effective detention. Jefferson later claimed that, in
authorizing the use of force to stop vessels from arming in or entering
U.S. ports, Washington had not contemplated major uses of force, but
rather early detection and occasional use of small parties of militia.
On July 18, the administration turned to the Supreme Court for
guidance with regard to the duties of neutrality and the meaning of the
French-American treaties. A list of twenty-nine questions was submitted
to the justices, who declined to answer. The Court would soon play an
active role on issues of international law and the use of force, but the
Court's guidance would only be available when cases or
controversies arose. On August 3, the cabinet issued a set of
"Rules Governing Belligerents," after considering whether such
actions were "within the competence of the President to
prohibit." "An administrative law of neutrality had been
forged" (Freeman 1957, 7:111).
Washington and his cabinet were soon made aware, however, that
serious uncertainties existed with regard to the orders they had issued.
On May 22, 1793, Chief Justice John Jay instructed a grand jury in
Richmond that they could properly indict Gideon Henfield for violating
neutrality, based on the proclamation, on the theory that the federal
courts had jurisdiction at common law to try individuals for violating
international law. At the urging of Attorney General Edmund Randolph,
Justices James Wilson, James Iredell, and District Judge Richard Peters
issued the same instruction in July 1793 to the jury that tried Henfield
for serving on a French privateer. The jury, however, refused to
convict. The administration realized that prosecutions based on a
presidential proclamation were likely to end in acquittals and decided
against bringing any further prosecutions on the theory that the federal
courts had jurisdiction over crimes not adopted by law (which the
Supreme Court rejected in 1812). (3) When Congress reconvened in
December, the president called on them "to extend the legal code
and the jurisdiction of the Courts of the United States to many cases
which, though dependent on principles already recognized, demand some
further provisions." (4) The statute he proposed incorporated the
"Rules Governing Belligerents" drawn up after the Henfield
prosecution (Hamilton 1850, 4: 455-62).
The president also realized he lacked authority unilaterally to
effectuate Jefferson's proposal that it would be better to pay
England compensation for vessels that the United States was obliged by
neutrality to return than to attempt to seize them from the French. The
Constitution assigns to Congress exclusively the power to raise and
spend funds. The president therefore insisted that the decision to pay
compensation be communicated to the French and British ambassadors in a
manner "so guarded as to convey nothing more than an opinion of the
executive." When Congress reconvened, the president sent a message
advising that "rather than employ force for the restitution of
certain vessels, which I deemed the United States bound to restore, I
thought it more advisable to satisfy the parties by avowing it to be my
opinion, that, if restitution were not made, it would be incumbent on
the United States to make compensation" (Ford 1891, 12: 357). The
president felt empowered to decide against seizing vessels from the
French and to opine that the United States was obliged to pay, but not
to make a promise to do so. Seeking to increase the likelihood that
compensation would in fact be paid, Hamilton (with the president's
knowledge) urged Jay to make the issue of compensation part of the Jay
Treaty with England, then under negotiation, because it could be
ratified without approval by the pro-French, Republican-controlled House
of Representatives (Sofaer 1976, 110-11).
The Pacificus-Helvidius Exchange
During this crisis, while Congress was still out of session, the
proclamation and related issues were debated in print by Hamilton and
Madison, the joint authors of the Federalist Papers that pertain most
directly to the purposes of the Framers in separating and mixing the
powers of the branches of government. On June 13, 1793, after the
proclamation was issued, Madison wrote to Jefferson expressing his
chagrin that the president had gone beyond declaring that the United
States was at peace and enjoining Americans to behave accordingly.
"The right to decide the question whether the duty & interest
of the U.S. require war or peace under any given circumstances, and
whether their disposition be towards the one or the other seems to be
essentially & exclusively involved in the right vested in the
Legislature, of declaring war in time of peace; and in the P. & S.
[President and Senate] of making peace in time of war. Did no such view
present itself in the discussions of the Cabinet?" (Hunt 1906, 6:
131-32). In responding on June 23, Jefferson took credit for having
succeeded in deleting the word "neutrality" from the
proclamation, but he explained that he did not want to oppose it
altogether for fear that he would then be ineffective at ensuring that
the French minister was received (Ford 1895, 6: 315-16).
Hamilton publicly defended the administration in an article under
the pseudonym "Pacificus" on June 29, 1793. A proclamation of
neutrality was, he wrote, the usual and proper manner for a state to
make its position known to other states at war with each other, and the
executive is the proper branch to make such a declaration, being
"the organ of intercourse between the nation and foreign
nations," the "interpreter of the national treaties," the
branch charged with enforcing the laws, including treaties, and the
official "in command and disposition of the public force." He
advanced two theories of "executive" power to support this
position: one encompassing all the powers normally considered executive
except those specifically withheld; and one limited to the duty to
"take care that the laws be faithfully executed." Under his
narrow theory, Hamilton argued the proclamation was not a
"law," but merely the statement of a "fact" with
regard to the state of the nation. Under his broad theory, Hamilton
assumed that Congress's power to declare war "includes the
right of judging, whether the nation is or is not under obligations to
make war." But he believed the president could also act, because
the Constitution often gives the branches concurrent authority over the
same functions. The executive had the authority in the exercise of his
powers to judge the nation's obligations, even "though it may,
in its consequences, affect the exercise of the power of the legislature
to declare war." Significantly, however, even under his expansive
view of executive power, Hamilton acknowledged that "the
legislature is still free to perform its duties, according to its own
sense of them" (Hamilton 1851, 7: 76-83).
Jefferson sent the Pacificus article to Madison, identifying the
author as Hamilton and complaining that no one had answered
Hamilton's "heresies." He later sent Madison two more
articles by Pacificus, urging him to "take up your pen, select the
most striking heresies, and cut him to pieces in the face of the
public" (Ford 1895, 6: 38). Madison obliged, responding as
Helvidius in articles appearing between August 24 and September 14. He
claimed that the powers to make treaties and declare war are not
properly considered by their nature "executive." But the gist
of his attack was on Hamilton's claim of concurrent power. If, as
Hamilton assumed, the power to declare war includes the power to judge
whether the nation is under an obligation to make war, then all
judgments concerning war were necessarily and exclusively part of the
legislative function. Whenever the issue arises whether war should be
declared or was required by a treaty, Madison wrote, "the question
necessarily belongs to the department to which those functions
belong--and no other department can be in the execution of its proper
functions, if it should undertake to decide such a question." He
rejected the notion that two branches could both have the power to judge
the state of the nation; the executive was bound to enforce neutrality
only because it was duty bound to preserve the peace in all cases, until
war is declared. He insisted on "a rigid adherence to the simple,
the received, and the fundamental doctrine of the constitution, that the
power to declare war, including the power of judging of the causes of
war, is fully and exclusively vested in the legislature." Madison
dismissed the concern that war might result if the president could not
act in Congress's absence, stating that the president was "not
responsible for the consequences" (Hunt 1906, 6: 134-82).
Congressional Reaction
The president explained his actions to Congress on December 3,
1793. When war erupted, he said, it became "my duty to admonish our
citizens against hostile acts," and to obtain "by a
declaration of the existing legal state of things, an easier admission
of our right to the immunities belonging to our situation." Now, he
said, "it rests with the wisdom of Congress to correct, improve, or
enforce the plan he had announced to preserve neutrality," noting
especially the need to confer jurisdiction on the courts to interpret
and enforce the rules (Ford 1891, 12: 352). Jefferson later wrote that
the president "never had an idea that he could bind Congress
against declaring war, or that anything contained in his proclamation
could look beyond the first day of their meeting" (Washington
1853-1854, 9: 179).
Both houses of Congress adopted resolutions praising the president
for his handling of the crisis. (5) No support for Madison's views
was expressed in the resolutions or discussion. After considerable
debate, on June 5, 1794, Congress provided financing and other authority
for enforcing neutrality, including the power to use force to seize or
expel offending vessels. (6)
The issues raised by Washington's proclamation demonstrate
that the process of decision making under the Constitution from the very
beginning has involved the exercise by all three branches of concurrent
powers over foreign and military affairs. The incident illustrates how
the conduct and claims of officials who were responsible for drafting
the Constitution, in exercising various powers, took into account other
related and potentially conflicting powers. In this sense, the process
generated by overlapping powers was even more instructive than the
specific acts and statements, in that the participants might have
expressed other views or taken other measures, but the dynamic created
by a divided but mixed government would nevertheless have presented
itself at every significant point. The existence of powers in one branch
that could support a given action or statement led neither branch to
treat those powers as exclusive, nor to treat them as insignificant
because of the existence of other, countervailing powers in another
branch. The president had strong arguments to support issuing and
enforcing a proclamation aimed at keeping the United States out of a
war, and Congress approved his having done so. Congress's powers
did not prevent the president from performing his functions. At the same
time, both Washington and Hamilton acknowledged that Congress could
authoritatively establish the national policy by accepting, rejecting,
or modifying the president's positions, and only Congress could
provide for full enforcement (though even those decisions were subject
to the president's veto). By inviting Congress to "correct,
improve, or enforce" his proclamation, Washington recognized that
he was operating, not on the basis of independent or exclusive powers,
but rather as one branch involved in a process with another branch
possessing its own concurrent powers.
It also became clear during that period that the powers of both
branches were subject to possible judicial review, by courts that were
themselves dependent on Congress and the president for funds,
jurisdictional allocations, appointments, and the means to enforce their
judgments. While the Supreme Court justices refused to answer abstract
questions posed by the president, they addressed (even if incorrectly)
the power of federal courts to prosecute crimes not legislatively
approved by Congress. After neutrality with France became impossible to
maintain, the Court passed on several legal issues that established
important principles regarding power over national security. It upheld
Congress's power to authorize and control a "Quasi War"
based on legislation rather than a declaration of war. (7) It also ruled
that, although the president as commander in chief normally may seize
any enemy vessel in an authorized war, Congress may limit this authority
by specifying the circumstances in which ships can be seized. (8)
The events surrounding the neutrality proclamation make clear that
the meaning of executive power cannot accurately be described without at
the same time taking into account that every power vested in any branch
(even "exclusive" powers) is limited by the existence of
other, related powers, vested in the other branches. The ambiguities
created by this complex and dynamic system are nowhere dealt with more
effectively than in Justice Jackson's concurring opinion in
Youngstown. Jackson's opinion has received widespread attention and
respect, not because he succeeded in defining the meaning of executive
power. He did not even attempt to do so. Rather, he succeeded in
providing instead a practical method for reviewing the exercise of
executive power within a system of predominantly concurrent rather than
exclusive authorities.
The Youngstown Method
In its 1952 decision in Youngstown, the Supreme Court invalidated
President Harry Truman's seizure of steel mills in order to prevent
them from being shut down in a labor dispute during the Korean War.
Justice Hugo Black's opinion for the Court characterized as
"legislative" the issue of whether the government ought to
seize steel mills and therefore beyond the president's
"executive" power. "In the framework of our
Constitution," Justice Black wrote, "the President's
power to see that the laws are faithfully executed refutes the idea that
he is to be a lawmaker. The Constitution limits his functions in the
law-making process to the recommending of laws he thinks wise and the
vetoing of laws he thinks bad." (9)
Justices Felix Frankfurter and Jackson, among other justices,
rejected this "formal" approach to separation of powers
decisions, based on the nature of the power of each branch. Justice
Jackson doubted that Justice Black's attempted bifurcation of
authority between what is "legislative" and what is
"executive" could be successfully applied. Justice Frankfurter
made the same point, quoting Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes in Springer
v. Government of Philippine Islands: "The great ordinances of the
Constitution do not establish and divide fields of black and
white." (10) Both Frankfurter and Jackson espoused a more
functional view. Jackson wrote:
The actual art of governing under our Constitution does not and
cannot conform to judicial definitions of the power of any of its
branches based on isolated clauses or even single Articles torn
from context. While the Constitution diffuses power the better to
secure liberty, it also contemplates that practice will integrate
the dispersed powers into a workable government. It enjoins upon its
branches separateness but interdependence, autonomy but reciprocity.
Presidential powers are not fixed but fluctuate, depending upon
their disjunction or conjunction with those of Congress. (11)
Frankfurter and Jackson agreed that acts of the president may
sometimes violate specifically assigned powers or prohibitions in the
Constitution. Absent a sufficiently clear prohibition on certain
conduct, however, they regarded the president's powers as
potentially extending to actions that could be considered
"legislative" or that otherwise fall within the scope of
powers of the other branches. Jackson concluded, therefore, that the
most effective way to evaluate the legality of executive conduct that
did not violate specific provisions in the Constitution was to determine
whether Congress had approved or disapproved that conduct. Thus, Justice
Jackson wrote: "When the President acts pursuant to an express or
implied authorization of Congress, his authority is at its maximum, for
it includes all that he possesses in his own right plus all that
Congress can delegate." (12) On the other hand: "When the
President takes measures incompatible with the expressed or implied will
of Congress, his power is at its lowest ebb, for then he can rely only
upon his own constitutional powers minus any constitutional powers of
Congress over the matter." (13) Under this view, Congress's
approval or disapproval of an executive action is a controlling factor
in determining the action's legality, absent some independent and
overriding executive authority. Both Jackson and Frankfurter found the
seizure in Youngstown invalid, because even if not unconstitutional by
its nature, it was inconsistent with Congress's decision against
conferring such authority, which they found on the facts implied its
disapproval.
Jackson also suggested an approach, not a rule, where Congress
fails to express its support or opposition to an executive action not
clearly precluded by the Constitution. In such situations, the
president's conduct is in a "zone of twilight," he wrote,
in which both branches may have concurrent authority, and legislative
inaction will not preclude determinations upholding the executive action
at issue:
When the President acts in absence of either a congressional grant
or denial of authority, he can only rely upon his own independent
powers, but there is a zone of twilight in which he and Congress may
have concurrent authority, or in which its distribution is
uncertain. Therefore, congressional inertia, indifference or
quiescence may sometimes, at least as a practical matter, enable, if
not invite, measures on independent presidential responsibility. In
this area, any actual test of power is likely to depend on the
imperatives of events and contemporary imponderables rather than on
abstract theories of law. (14)
The categories in Jackson's opinion provide a roadmap for
dealing with the legality of executive actions. Applying those
categories to contemporary issues illustrates the parameters of
presidential power and its relationship to the powers of Congress and of
the courts.
Actions that Violate Constitutional Limitations
The principle that executive actions may violate specific
provisions in the Constitution, though seldom controlling in actual
controversies, is a fundamental aspect of the constitutional plan which
the Supreme Court regards its duty to maintain. The Court has found
unconstitutional legislative schemes, executive actions, and judicial
assertions of power because they were inconsistent with limitations
expressed in or implied from constitutional language or may represent or
allow aggrandizement or encroachment of one branch's authority by
another. The Court ruled, for example, that Congress may not authorize
one-House vetoes of decisions of the attorney general to suspend the
deportation of aliens. One-House vetoes are legislative actions, the
Court found, in a form inconsistent with the unambiguous presentment and
bicameral requirements of the Constitution: "Explicit and
unambiguous provisions of the Constitution prescribe and define the
respective functions of the Congress and of the Executive in the
legislative process." (15) The two-House vetoes in the Federal
Trade Commission Improvements Act of 1980 met a similar fate, (16) as
did an effort to move the nation toward a balanced budget through cuts
in spending supervised by the comptroller general, an officer removable
by Congress. Even the dissenters to the latter decision agreed that
"the constitutional scheme of separated powers does prevent
Congress from reserving an executive role for itself or for its
'agents,'" but argued that it had done neither in that
particular case. (17) The line item veto was invalidated, because it was
inconsistent with the specific plan of the Constitution for the passage
of legislation. (18)
The Court enforces the language and structure of the Constitution,
(19) recognizing that the Framers' overarching purpose was to
achieve a balance of power between the political branches, even though
that objective may be inconsistent with efficiency or other claims of
improved government. (20) On the other hand, the Court has upheld novel
provisions or practices not clearly proscribed, where they pose no
threat of "aggrandizement" or "encroachment" by one
branch upon another. (21)
Some executive powers are so specific and exclusive that Congress
may not regulate their exercise. The pardon power, for example, may not
be limited or otherwise restricted by legislation. How far this
principle goes is uncertain. It certainly does not extend to the point
that it would interfere with specifically assigned legislative powers,
but rather seems to restrict Congress's use of the general power to
pass "necessary and proper" laws. It is inapplicable to
Congress's power over spending, so Congress could probably
influence as a practical matter the exercise even of exclusively held
executive powers (Prakash 2005, 91: 215).
The Constitution also by its terms precludes some forms of
executive conduct as inconsistent with powers assigned to Congress.
Congress has the exclusive power to raise funds for all purposes under
the Constitution. This is a major restraint on executive power, so long
as Congress has not provided funds that are within the president's
discretion to spend. The scheme by some officials in the Reagan
administration to sell arms owned by the United States for a profit in
order to raise money to support the Contras in Nicaragua violated this
principle. (22) President Abraham Lincoln's suspension of habeas
corpus was also illegal, because the Constitution is understood to
assign the power to suspend habeas corpus in emergencies to Congress.
(23) Lincoln claimed his unconstitutional act was necessary to save the
Constitution and expected Congress to approve the suspension (Cox 1984,
218).
Another category of restraints based on constitutional provisions
is less predictable but important. The Court has often refused to uphold
civil liberties claims in the face of executive decisions during times
of crisis. It has in general accepted executive branch positions in
emergencies without careful scrutiny. Even though, for example, the
Court requires a clear and present danger to justify the prohibition of
protected speech, it applied that test during World War I in a highly
deferential manner. This tendency may be altered to some extent, due to
the widespread recognition that executive claims in support of civil
liberty deprivations are often unsubstantiated in retrospect (Brennan
1988). The Supreme Court in 2004 (Hamdi and Rasul) accepted the
proposition that the president may hold prisoners of war until the end
of an authorized military conflict, but held that the Due Process Clause
requires that any such prisoner who is a U.S. national on U.S. territory
must be given notice of the government's claim regarding his status
and an opportunity to challenge the factual assumptions underlying that
claim before a neutral decision maker. Citing Youngstown, the Court
stated: "We have long since made clear that a state of war is not a
blank check for the President when it comes to the rights of the
Nation's citizens." (24)
Many types of executive conduct have been accepted as being
consistent with the Constitution, despite the claim that the functions
at issue are exclusively assigned to Congress. Presidents since
Washington have exercised their powers, despite the fact that doing so
might cause a military conflict. Congress's power to declare war
includes the power to determine when and how the nation should fight
undeclared wars. But the fact that Congress is empowered to decide such
issues does not preclude presidents from using assigned powers despite
the possibility that their exercise might result in conflict. The
president may also use force without legislative approval to defend the
nation, despite Congress's power to declare war. Notes of the
Constitutional Convention debates recite that Congress was given the
power to "declare" war, rather than to "make" war,
in order to permit the president to defend against "sudden
attacks" (Farrand 1937, 2: 318), but self-defense is not so
restricted in practice. Presidents are widely regarded as vested with
the power of the nation to act consistent with international law for
such purposes as defending U.S. nationals, armed forces, or property
from attacks, or rescuing nationals in danger. Presidents have often
used limited force in a variety of situations, and the War Powers
Resolution implicitly condones some uses of force for limited times
without legislative approval. (25)
While the Constitution contains no provision that precludes
executive uses of force without legislative approval, presidents have
rarely claimed the power unilaterally to take the nation into a major
military conflict and (though sometimes asserting they can act
unilaterally) have only done so with Congress's approval in the
form at least of knowing financial support. The manner in which
Washington and his cabinet handled the crisis caused by the war between
France and England indicates that, while the president could use his
explicit powers despite the danger of causing war, these actions were to
be taken with a view to avoiding war. Other clear examples exist,
including President James Monroe's decision to give up attempting
to take control of West Florida by force, after Congress refused
repeated requests for such authority (Sofaer 1976, 378). Absent
legislative approval in some adequate form, the president lacks
authority to engage in major military actions that cannot be justified
on the basis of self-defense.
Legislative Approval of Executive Actions
So long as Congress acts consistently with the Constitution, its
support of the president maximizes the president's authority and
its opposition leaves the president to rely on his exclusive powers for
authority. Justice Jackson assumed in advancing this generalization that
Congress's will with regard to national policy in general prevails,
as it is vested with the legislative power of the nation. This
assumption is consistent with the views of the Framers, executive
practice, and authoritative Supreme Court decisions. Where Congress
expresses a view, therefore, even implicitly by denying a requested
authority, as in Youngstown, the second principle of separation of
powers decision making applies, and Congress's intent generally
prevails.
The Supreme Court has ruled that Congress controls the extent of
legislatively approved ("limited") wars, and any limit
established by legislation restricts the president's power to use
force even where he could lawfully have done so in the absence of the
limitation. (26) In Little v. Barreme, Chief Justice John Marshall
construed a legislative grant of power to seize vessels engaged in trade
to any French port to prevent the president from authorizing the seizure
of vessels engaged in trade from any French port. (27) When Congress has
ordered that funds may not be used for a particular use of force or
other national security purpose, presidents have complied, despite
having opposed such legislation. Congress has passed legislation
requiring, for example, that funds not be used after a specified date
for the support of combat troops in Cambodia (1970), for the support of
any combat activities related to the war in Vietnam (1974), and for the
use of armed forces in Somalia (1994) or in Rwanda (1994) (Grimmett
2001). Limitations on the use of funds to support the contras in
Nicaragua varied from year to year, and such spending as occurred in
violation of the few clear limits that were adopted was done secretly in
order to avoid Congress's legal mandate. Congress is able to
control the president's use of appropriated funds even in
situations where, but for Congress's limitation, the president
would have authority to act. When, despite the president's
long-established power to decide not to spend monies appropriated by
Congress, Congress required the president to spend monies that it
appropriated, that decision was controlling. (28)
Advocates of executive power have claimed in recent years that the
president has inherent and exclusive powers in the national security
area that are beyond Congress's power to limit or regulate. Some
executive powers, as noted above, are exclusive and beyond
Congress's power to regulate directly. In general, however, the
claim to powers over national security that are beyond Congress's
capacity to regulate is baseless. (29) Justice Jackson dismissed the
Truman administration's reliance on "nebulous, inherent powers never expressly granted but said to have accrued to the office from the
customs and claims of preceding administrations." What he said then
about executive power claims based on these vague phrases remains true
today: "Loose and irresponsible use of adjectives colors all
nonlegal and much legal discussion of presidential powers.
'Inherent' powers, 'implied' powers,
'plenary' powers, 'war' powers,
'emergency' powers, are used, often interchangeably and
without fixed or ascertainable meanings." (30) So inadequate is the
argument that the president may disregard a law applicable to his
conduct that it was not even advanced by the Bush administration in
Hamdan, and would in any event have been rejected. The Court concluded:
"Whether or not the President has independent power, absent
congressional authorization, to convene military commissions, he may not
disregard limitations that Congress has, in proper exercise of its own
war powers, placed on his powers. See Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v.
Sawyer, 343 U.S. 519, 637 (1952) Jackson, J., concurring. The Government
does not argue otherwise." (31)
Anti-executive power advocates, however, have their own exaggerated
claims. They often fail to acknowledge that, just as Congress can
control and limit the president, it can empower the president by broadly
delegating authority to him over national security issues, including the
use of force. Congress has frequently approved the use of force in
sweeping delegations of power, as in the Gulf of Tonkin Resolution of
1964 and the 2001 resolution authorizing force against those responsible
for the attacks of 9/11. And just as the Court in Youngstown found that
Congress can implicitly deny the president power to take a given action,
Congress can implicitly grant power to the president. When Congress
authorized the building of vessels intended for use against piracy in
the Mediterranean, for example, it was understood to convey authority to
use the vessels for that or any other defensive purpose (Sofaer 1976,
156-58). An argument for implied authority exists whenever Congress puts
a military capacity at the disposal of the president that is likely to
require prompt and secret action, ranging from the missiles and bombs
needed for a retaliatory nuclear strike to a special force intended for
the rescue of hostages.
In some instances, a failure by Congress to legislate may be seen
as approval, rather than as disapproval, of presidential action,
depending on the context and circumstances. In Dames & Moore v.
Regan, the Court upheld an executive agreement establishing a method for
settling claims with Iran and suspending pursuit of such claims in the
federal courts. The Supreme Court concluded that "Congress has
implicitly approved the practice of claim settlement by executive
agreement" by arranging and paying to implement such arrangements.
(32)
Congress can also approve military actions by paying for them.
Early in the Vietnam War, before Congress began acting to express its
disapproval, the Second Circuit found that the war was lawful, in part
because Congress had paid for its operation:
[T]he test [for mutual congressional participation in the prosecution
of war] is whether there is any action by the Congress sufficient to
authorize or ratify the military activity in question .... Congress
has ratified the executive's initiatives by appropriating billions of
dollars to carry out military operations in Southeast Asia and by
extending the Military Selective Service Act with full knowledge
that persons conscripted under the Act had been, and would continue
to be, sent to Vietnam. (33)
A more recent example is Congress's approval of the military
action in Kosovo, to prevent the ethnic cleansing of Muslims. Congress
failed explicitly to approve or to disapprove the operation, but the
Senate clearly signaled its approval for air operations before March 24,
1999 (the House votes were more ambiguous), when President Bill Clinton
ordered the bombing to begin, and on May 20, while the bombing
continued, Congress paid for "Operation Allied Force," knowing
that the funds were intended to pay the bill for bombing Kosovo (Sofaer
2000, 74-75).
The major action that is most difficult to justify in terms of
legislative approval is President Truman's decision to authorize
the use of armed force to defend South Korea from an attack by North
Korea that commenced on Sunday, June 25, 1950. Later that day, the
United Nations Security Council voted to order North Korea to withdraw,
and Truman ordered the use of air and naval power to evacuate Americans
and transport ammunition and supplies to the South. The president did
not seek legislation authorizing the action, though he would certainly
have obtained that support. Instead, he consulted with Senator Tom
Connally, chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, on Monday,
June 26, who said he did not believe legislative approval was necessary
for what he regarded as a defensive war. That evening, Truman authorized
the use of air and naval power to support South Korea. He later
consulted with other legislators who supported the initiative, but he
never sought explicit legislative approval and claimed the right to use
the armed forces without such approval (Crabb and Holt 1989, 127-32).
After the war was underway, however, Congress supported it by extending
the draft and with special appropriations intended to pay for the
military operation. These actions constituted retroactive approval, much
as President Lincoln had secured retroactive approval for some of his
actions during the Civil War. As Professor Ely commented: "Hornbook
law seems generally to be that programs unauthorized at the time can
constitutionally be authorized retroactively by Congress, nunc pro tunc (thus rendering them legal not simply 'from now on' but
'from the outset' as well). E.g., Swayne & Hoyt, Ltd. v.
United States, 300 U.S. 297 (1937)" (Ely 1993, 10-11, 198 n.55).
Truman was wrong that he had the power to act unilaterally. He correctly
judged Congress's position, however, and therefore never faced a
true test of his exaggerated claims. Had Congress indicated its
disapproval, he would have suffered two defeats in the Supreme Court
over Korea, not just the decision in Youngstown.
Congress adopted the War Powers Resolution (WPR) in an attempt to
prevent the executive and the courts from relying upon the traditional
bases for ascertaining legislative approval. Section 8 provides that an
inference of approval of a particular military action may be found in
legislation (or in a law implementing a treaty) only if the law
"specifically authorizes the introduction of United States Armed
Forces into hostilities or into such situations and states that it is
intended to constitute specific statutory authorization with the meaning
of this chapter." (34) The WPR seeks to require the executive and
the courts to disregard evidence of approval (including resolutions
approving the conduct at issue and appropriations specifically passed to
pay for it), unless Congress states specifically that the legislation
relied upon is intended as approval under the WPR.
This effort to restrict the form of approval is inconsistent with
universally accepted standards for determining civil or criminal
responsibility under national law, or state responsibility under
international law. No criminal group, no corporation, no individual,
could avoid responsibility for conduct that it knowingly supported or
paid for. It is irresponsible for Congress to claim otherwise.
Furthermore, the Supreme Court has invalidated an effort by one Congress
to limit the definition of a word in an unreasonably restrictive manner,
and the doctrine against entrenched legislation precludes the
application of such formulae in a manner that controls all future
Congresses (Eule 1987, 379). (35) How could one law forever restrict the
legal significance of what Congress does under subsequent law,
especially when the law that is earlier in time seeks artificially to
limit the legal consequences of subsequent legislative conduct? Section
8 of the WPR is an effort to modify the Framers' plan by
encroaching on the president's potential claims to authority in
interbranch disputes. It would, if valid, enable Congress to disclaim
the intended consequences of its actions in order to place sole
responsibility on the president for acts Congress knowingly made
possible. It is hardly surprising that Congress has failed to enforce
this provision, and that the courts have refused to intervene (Sofaer
2000).
A treaty may provide support for an executive use of force, without
further legislative action, though the House of Representative retains
the power to deny funding for even such uses of force. But the language
and intent of Congress with regard to the treaties most often claimed to
justify this claim--the UN Charter and the treaty establishing NATO--do
not confer legislative approval. These treaties provide that uses of
force contemplated pursuant to their provisions will be approved in
accordance with the constitutional process of each member state.
Resolutions of the United Nations Security Council establish the
legality of uses of force under international law, but they are
insufficient to provide authority under the U.S. Constitution for
actions that would otherwise be illegal (Stromseth 1995). The legal
process required by the Constitution to approve a use of force is made
no less complicated because of a reference to it in a treaty. The
president would still be empowered to act in self-defense and within the
full scope of his powers, and Congress would still be empowered to
approve, disapprove, or limit what the president proposes or does. But a
treaty calling for approval under the U.S. legal system cannot itself
tenably be relied upon as proof of legislative approval.
Executive Power in the Zone of Twilight
It is difficult to know precisely what Justice Jackson meant by
executive actions that fall within the zone of twilight. Chief Justice
William Rehnquist construed what Jackson acknowledged was "a
somewhat over-simplified grouping" as representing points on
"a spectrum running from explicit congressional authorization to
explicit congressional prohibition." (36) It seems that Jackson
meant that in some cases the Court will be able to find Congress had
approved an executive action (increasing the likelihood that it is
lawful), in some cases the Court will be able to conclude that Congress
had disapproved (increasing the likelihood of its illegality), but that
in some cases neither of these conclusions might be possible. The latter
situations, Jackson wrote, are those in which the president and Congress
"may have concurrent authority, or in which its distribution is
uncertain." By failing to act decisively in such instances,
Congress could "enable, if not invite, measures on independent
presidential responsibility." (37) The scope of this principle can
be seen in the rule that Congress's mere acquiescence to a course
of executive conduct, even if not amounting to approval, may in some
circumstances be treated as sufficient to justify its continuity.
Justice Frankfurter, in criticizing Justice Black's formalistic approach in Youngstown, wrote: "It is an inadmissibly narrow
conception of American constitutional law to confine it to the words of
the Constitution and to disregard the gloss which life has written upon
them. A systematic, unbroken, Executive practice, long pursued with the
knowledge of Congress and never before questioned, may be treated as a
gloss on the meaning of 'executive Power' as vested in the
President." (38) Justice Jackson understood this principle to
extend, not just to situations in which Congress makes a deliberate
decision to acquiesce in an executive practice, but also to those in
which Congress expresses neither approval nor disapproval but simply
allows the conduct to continue unchecked. "We may say," he
wrote, "that power to legislate for emergencies belongs in the
hands of Congress, but only Congress itself can prevent power from
slipping through its fingers." (39) The Supreme Court has applied
this principle to uphold the legality (and supremacy over state law) of
executive agreements, even when not authorized by Congress. (40)
An example of executive action within Jackson's zone of
twilight might be the Gulf of Sidra exercise during the Reagan
administration. Congress had at least implicitly approved the U.S.
Navy's program of ensuring freedom of the high seas by knowingly
funding its operation. President Ronald Reagan knew that he could cause
a military confrontation when he used this authority in 1986 to
challenge Libya's claims by sailing U.S. public vessels across the
Gulf of Sidra. The president may even have welcomed an effort by Libya
to block the exercise, so he could use force to punish Libya for
supporting terrorism. The president regarded himself as legally entitled
to engage in the operation despite the heightened risk of military
action (which did in fact occur), and he reported the incident to
Congress without any reference to the WPR. Congress took no action to
indicate approval or disapproval of this activity, thereby leaving the
conduct within the zone contemplated by Justice Jackson, in which the
president remains free to act on the basis of executive authority,
because the Congress has not attempted to establish limits on the degree
of risk involved.
Advocates of "interbranch dialogue and bipartisan
consensus," like Professors Koh (1990) and Ely (1993), may condemn
this principle as condoning "legislative inactivity." But this
principle neither condones nor condemns Congress's failure to act.
The power to set national policy is not a device for ensuring that
Congress will in fact exercise control in all situations, or that it
will do so explicitly and unambiguously.
The concept of a zone of twilight, in which authority may be
concurrent and therefore uncertain, is part of Jackson's insightful
description of how the American constitutional system works and was
intended to work. Where Congress does nothing definitive in situations
of concurrent authority or where the distribution of authority is
uncertain, the outcome "is likely to depend on the imperatives of
events and contemporary imponderables rather than on abstract theories
of law by political circumstances." This result suggests not only
the propriety of resorting in such cases to judicial abstention based on
the political question, standing, or other doctrines but the necessity
of doing so in order to preserve the Constitution's plan.
Executive actions that fall within the zone of twilight do so
because of uncertainties that result from the deliberate assignment to
the branches of overlapping powers designed to enable each to make
legitimate claims to authority in the anticipated battles over
governmental power. To clarify powers in this context would narrow
uncertainty and end conflicting claims in situations where the Framers
vested powers concurrently in order to enable both branches to act and
thereby to ensure the capacity for enduring conflict. The Framers
anticipated that the branches would clash in situations where both have
legitimate claims to authority, and the courts should no more decide
such conflicts on behalf of one branch or the other than they should
allow the branches acting alone or together to alter other intended
parts of the constitutional scheme.
The Framers wanted the political branches to have the means--which
in the U.S. system means the legally supportable measures of
opposition--to contest each other's claims. Every clarification and
limitation issued by the courts in such situations would reduce the type
and scope of available measures for legitimate conflict. This, in turn,
could tend to make it more likely over time that one branch would be
able to control the other on these fundamental issues. The courts should
avoid "clarifications" of authority that could facilitate such
a development.
Conclusion
Bush administration attorneys have triggered a new round of debate
over the scope of executive power. Their claim to executive authority
over the use of force and other national security issues that is beyond
the control of Congress is no more meritorious today than it would have
been in 1793, when Washington issued his proclamation, or in 1932, when
the Court and Justice Jackson rejected the argument.
The Constitution allocates powers over national security to all the
branches that enable each to affect national policy. Concurrent
authority is the general rule of constitutional allocations, because the
Framers wanted to mix powers, not merely to separate them. This means
that the executive may use his powers on national security issues with
initiative, but that the president's authority is subject to the
exercise of Congress's powers, and to the Supreme Court's
decisions on conflicting interpretations. Where Congress disapproves of
the president's action, the president's authority depends on
the existence of some separate and independent power to overcome
Congress's legislative authorities. Congress is also empowered,
however, to authorize executive actions in any form sufficient to
constitute approval. The power of Congress to delegate authority to use
force is clearly established, and courts have uniformly held that
Congress approves an action by knowingly funding it. In addition, the
fact that the president has concurrent powers over many aspects of
national security explains why the president can sometimes act lawfully
on such issues when Congress has neither approved nor disapproved his
conduct.
This set of rules makes clear why executive authority can only be
properly understood in light of the powers assigned to the other
branches, in a system of concurrent, rather than exclusive, authorities.
More fundamentally, the system of mixed government intended by the
Framers, and still the most tenable explanation of the U.S. system,
remains essential to prevent tyranny while enabling each branch of the
government to be active and effective in dealing with national security
challenges. Recent arguments of executive power advocates against this
system of mixed powers have been authoritatively rejected or abandoned.
Yet, the fact that such claims were so vigorously advanced by such
high-ranking executive officials makes it clear that the Framers'
concerns remain valid. Of particular concern is the fact that several
policies having a direct relationship to tyranny (including indefinite
detention, harsh if not illegal interrogation, and unsupervised
electronic surveillance) were implemented secretly with the intention
that they would remain--indeed with the claim that they were entitled to
remain--beyond the control of Congress or the courts. The U.S. system of
mixed government was designed by the Framers to provoke appropriate,
corrective rulings and practices to check executive initiatives, whether
or not they violate the Constitution. Secret operations could preclude
the system from functioning in its intended manner.
It is equally important to remember, however, that the system of
mixed government was designed to enable the president to be active and
effective in protecting and advancing U.S. interests. It also
contemplates that Congress is able to approve and fund national security
programs and military actions, and that such decisions are
constitutionally valid however unhappy the consequences. Efforts to
improve the quality of executive or legislative or judicial decision
making on national security issues should continue. But it is neither
constitutionally proper nor likely to be functionally effective to
expect that one change or another in procedures or legal requirements
will lead to a system that produces better national security outcomes.
It is difficult to understand, for example, the basis upon which
some assume that the more involved Congress becomes on use of force
issues the better off the United States will be. Congress certainly
knows it has the power to prevent or to terminate uses of force. Given
this reality, why would anyone expect that additional rules that purport
to limit the president's power by redefining the meaning of
approval, for example, will lead to more responsible and effective
legislative action? The nature of Congress cannot so easily be altered.
If the objective is to put pressure on Congress to accept responsibility
for its decisions, why is not the better rule to deem Congress to have
approved all the actions Congress supports or otherwise knowingly makes
possible? If Congress has the power to act and fails to do so, why is it
more likely to act and take responsibility if the courts were available
to stop the president from acting?
Moreover, what gives supporters of a rule requiring legislative
approval in advance of all uses of force the confidence to believe that
the nation will be best served by a more active Congress, and
particularly one that disallows executive actions? It is a matter of
intense dispute whether the nation's interests were better served
when Congress has funded military operations supported by the executive,
or when Congress has acted to constrain them. Secretary of State George
P. Shultz concluded, for example, that the limitation placed by Congress
on the use of troops in Lebanon in 1983 undermined the credibility of
U.S. efforts there, and was regarded by Syria as a clear sign that the
United States lacked resolve (Shultz 1993, 230-31). Among the most
definitive legislative directions that funds not be used to support a
military action was a September 1994 law that prevented the U.S. armed
forces from preventing the Rwandan genocide. (41) There simply is no
basis to believe that better decisions about war and peace will be made
merely because Congress is required rather than merely empowered to act.
The Constitution and its history support the view that situations
in which the branches have concurrent--and hence uncertain--authority
reflect the intended functioning of the Framers' design. It would
be wrong, and likely do far more harm than good, to alter this plan,
either in a quest for effective executive authority to win a "war
on terror" or for the purpose of depriving the executive of
authorities to act when Congress is unable or unwilling to do so. The
Supreme Court should continue to ensure that no branch is successful in
preventing the others from exercising the full range of their powers,
including those that are concurrently held and therefore likely to cause
controversy and competition. The authority of each branch has limits.
But the system was intended to provide capacities to all the branches
that enabled and were expected to lead them to compete with and thereby
constrain the others. The rules for such a system should aim to allow
the full range of disputes to remain unregulated, as a symptom of
constitutional well-being. In sum, my answer to the questions posed for
this exercise remains that:
The Framers expected the branches to battle each other to acquire
and to defend power. To prevent the supremacy of one branch over any
other in these battles, powers were mixed; each branch was granted
important powers over the same area of activity. The British and
Confederation experiences had led the Framers to avoid regarding
controversy between the branches as a conflict between good and evil
or right and wrong, requiring definitive, institutionally permanent
resolution. Rather they viewed such conflict as an expression of the
aggressive and perverse part of human nature that demanded outlet
but had to be kept from finding lasting resolution so that liberty
could be preserved. (Sofaer 1976, 60)
References
Bailyn, Bernard. 1968. The origins of American politics. New York:
Knopf.
Brennan, William J., Jr. 1988. The quest to develop a jurisprudence of civil liberties in times of security crises. Dordrecht, The
Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
Cox, Henry B. 1984. War, foreign affairs, and constitutional power:
1829-1901. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
Crabb, Cecil V., Jr., and Pat M. Holt. 1989. Invitation to
struggle: Congress, the president, and foreign policy. Washington, DC:
Congressional Quarterly Press.
Ely, John H. 1993. War and responsibility. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Eule, Julian N. 1987. Temporal limits on the legislative mandate:
Entrenchment and retroactivity. American Bar Foundation Research Journal
1987: 379.
Farrand, Max, ed. 1937. The records of the federal convention of
1787. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Fisher, Louis. 2006. Lost constitutional moorings: Recovering the
war power. Indiana Law Journal 8 l: 1199.
Fitzpatrick, John C., ed. 1931-1944. The writings of George
Washington. 39 vols. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office.
Ford, W., ed. 1889-1893. The writings of George Washington, 14
vols. New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons.
Ford, Paul Leicester, ed. 1892-1899. The writings of Thomas
Jefferson. 10 vols. New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons.
Freeman, Douglas S. 1948-1957. George Washington: A biography, 7
vols. New York: C. Scribner's Sons.
Grimmett, Richard E 2001. Congressional use of funding cutoffs
since 1970 involving U.S. military forces and overseas deployments,
RS20775. Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service.
Hamilton, J. C., ed. 1850-1851. The works of Alexander Hamilton, 7
vols. New York: John F. Trow.
Hunt, Galliard, ed. 1901-1910. The writings of James Madison. 9
vols. New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons.
Koh, Harold H. 1990. The national security constitution: Sharing
power after the Iran-contra affair. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Prakash, Saikrishna. 2005. Regulating presidential powers. Cornell
Law Review 91: 215.
Shultz, George P. 1993. Turmoil and triumph. New York: C.
Scribner's Sons.
Sofaer, Abraham D. 1976. War, foreign affairs and constitutional
power: The origins. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
--. 2000. The War Powers Resolution and Kosovo. Loyola of Los
Angeles Law Review 34: 61.
Stromseth, Jane E. 1995. Collective force and constitutional
responsibility: War powers in the post-Cold War era. Miami Law Review
50: 145.
Washington, H. A., ed. 1853-1854. The writings of Thomas Jefferson.
9 vols. Philadelphia: Taylor and Maury.
Yoo, John. 2005. The powers of war and peace. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
(1.) Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579,
634-35 (1952).
(2.) A group of distinguished scholars--Jack N. Rakove, Fred
Anderson, Caroline Cox, R. Don Higgenbotham, Charles A. Lofgren, Robert
L. Middlekauf, Lois G. Schwoerer, and John Shy--filed an amicus brief in
Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, U.S. Supreme Court, no. 05-184, supporting the
position that the president lacks inherent power of the sort claimed by
the Bush administration. In the brief, they rely on their view of the
background and history of the U.S. Constitution and the aversion to the
notion of royal prerogatives. They properly conclude that the Framers
would have rejected the notion that the president has extensive powers
over national security that are not subject to legislative control.
Louis Fisher, in a separate amicus brief in Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, also
argued against an inherent power for the president to establish military
commissions. This point may seem important today, given the Bush
administration's claims, but it is not the issue on which most
executive power controversies turn. The Bush administration in fact did
not even claim that it could disregard legislation found by the Court to
apply to persons in Hamdan's position. 126 S. Ct. 2749, 2774 n.23.
Hamilton advanced two versions of executive power in his debate with
Madison, and neither supported the view that Congress lacked the power
to set national policy. The pivotal issue between Hamilton and Madison
had nothing to do with Congress's ultimate authority and everything
to do with the president's power in the absence of legislative
direction. The issue was not whether the president was supreme, but
whether he was powerless to use his own authorities, because his actions
might prejudice Congress's power over war. The actions of all three
branches make clear that Hamilton, not Madison, correctly described
executive power in this regard. Madison's arguments on this point
disregarded the reasons he had given in the Federalist Papers for the
fact that the Constitution had "mixed" powers in both the
political branches.
(3.) The Court assumed that necessity may imply "powers to the
general Government," but concluded that it did not follow that the
courts could thereby be "vested with jurisdiction over any
particular act done by an individual in supposed violation of the peace
and dignity of the sovereign power. The legislative authority of the
Union must first make an act a crime, affix a punishment to it, and
declare the Court that shall have jurisdiction over the offence."
United States v. Hudson, 11 U.S. 32, 34 (1812).
(4.) Annals of Congress. 1834-1856. Debates and proceedings in the
Congress of the United States, 1789-1824, 42 vols. Washington, DC: Gales
and Seaton 4:11.
(5.) Ibid., 4: 17-18, 138.
(6.) Ibid., 4: 1461-64, 743-57.
(7.) Bas v. Tingy, 4 U.S. 37 (1800).
(8.) Little v. Barreme, 6 U.S. 170 (1808).
(9.) 343 U.S. 587.
(10.) 277 U.S. 189, 209 0928).
(11.) 343 U.S. 633.
(12.) Ibid.
(13.) Ibid., 637.
(14.) Ibid.
(15.) INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983).
(16.) For example, Process Gas Consumers Group v. Consumers Energy
Council, 463 U.S. 1216 (1983).
(17.) Bowsher v. Synar, 478 U.S. 714, 765 (1986). See Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976) (Federal Election Commission invalidated
because the majority of members were appointed by legislative leaders);
Metropolitan Washington Airports Authority v. Citizens for Abatement of
Airport Noise, Inc., 501 U.S. 252 (1991) (invalidating act conditioning
transfer of Dulles and National Airports to authority on which nine
congressional members were to serve in their "individual
capacities").
(18.) Clinton v. New York City, 524 U.S. 417 (1998).
(19.) For example, Reid v. Covert, 354 U.S. 1, 8 (1957).
(20.) "{I}t would be mistaken and mischievous for the
political branches to forget that the sworn obligation to preserve and
protect the Constitution in maintaining the federal balance is their own
in the first and primary instance." United States v. Lopez, 514
U.S. 549, 577 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring).
(21.) For example, Mistretta v. United States, 488 U.S. 361 (1989)
(upholding sentencing commission which included judges and which limited
the president's removal power to "good cause").
(22.) Both the majority and minority of the Joint Committee agreed
that, if the funds from the arms sales to Iran were property of the
United States, the surplus realized should have gone into the U.S.
Treasury. S. Report no. 100-216; H. Report no. 100-433. 100th Cong., 1st
sess. (November 1987).
(23.) The provision allowing suspension "when in Cases of
Rebellion or Invasion the public Safety may require it" appears in
Article I, section 9, which deals with the powers of Congress.
(24.) Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 519 (2004).
(25.) Pub. Law 93-148.
(26.) Talbot v. Seeman, 5 U.S. 1 (1801).
(27.) 6 U.S. 170 (1804).
(28.) Train v. City of New York, 420 U.S. 35 (1975).
(29.) The weaknesses of the arguments made by Professor John Yoo and others have been thoroughly addressed by Louis Fisher (Fisher 2006,
1230-47). Professor Yoo is correct, however, in arguing that the
president has the power to act without prior legislative approval to
protect the United States, its nationals, and even its interests; and he
properly recognizes that Congress is entitled to use its power over
funds to stop executive actions (Yoo 2005, 294).
(30.) 343 U.S. 646-47.
(31.) 126 S. Ct. 2749, 2774 n.23.
(32.) 453 u.s. 654, 680 (1981).
(33.) Orlando v. Laird, 443 F.2d 1039, 1042 (2d Cir.), cert.
denied, 404 U.S. 689 (1971).
(34.) The War Powers Act of 1973, Pub. Law 93-148.
(35.) Marcello v. Bonds, 349 U.S. 302 (1955).
(36.) 453 U.S. 669.
(37.) 343 U.S. 657.
(38.) Ibid., 610-11.
(39.) Ibid., 654.
(40.) United States v. Belmont, 301 U.S. 324 (1937).
(41.) P.L. 103-335, preventing use of funds in the Department of
Defense Appropriations Act for FY 1995 for U.S. forces in Operation
Support Hope after October 7, 1994, except as necessary to protect the
lives of U.S. citizens.
ABRAHAM D. SOFAER
Stanford University
Abraham D. Sofaer is George P. Shultz Senior Fellow at The Hoover
Institution, Stanford University. Mr. Sofaer was a professor of law at
Columbia University, 1969-1979, U.S. district judge, 1979-1985, and
legal adviser to the U.S. Department of State, 1985-1990.