Is more antitrust the answer to wealth inequality? Market power often serves progressive aims.
Crane, Daniel A.
Wealth inequality has reemerged as a major political issue and may
become one of the defining themes of the 2016 presidential election.
Progressives claim a broad set of causes for wealth inequality, from tax
loopholes favoring the wealthy to the decline of private sector
unionization.
Recently, a number of high-profile public intellectuals have begun
to finger an additional culprit--lax antitrust enforcement. According to
prominent progressives such as Nobel economics laureates Joseph Stiglitz
and Paul Krugman, former labor secretary Robert Reich, and Oxford
economist Anthony Atkinson, weak enforcement of the antitrust laws has
permitted the flourishing of anticompetitive mergers, monopolistic
conduct, and other exclusionary and collusive behavior, with the effect
of redistributing wealth upward to corporate shareholders and senior
executives and away from the less wealthy strata of society. This
monopoly regressivity claim is increasingly being repeated in legal and
economic scholarship and in the media.
The monopoly regressivity claim may have considerable political
appeal, but it is vastly overstated. Although there are surely some
violations of the antitrust laws that exacerbate wealth inequality, the
generalization that more antitrust enforcement would lead to a more
equitable distribution of wealth misunderstands the actual incidence and
effects of antitrust enforcement. Exercises of market power have
complex, crosscutting effects, some of which may be regressive, but many
of which may also be progressive or distributively neutral. More
antitrust is not the answer to wealth inequality.
THE MONOPOLY REGRESSIVITY CLAIM
There are many good reasons to favor competitive markets, and to
think that some degree of antitrust enforcement is necessary to produce
such markets. Competitive markets result in innovation, lower prices,
and expanded output. This is all good and healthy, but it does not
necessarily result in greater income equality. Suppose a more
competitive economy results in a 20 percent increase in gross domestic
product, with all members of society benefiting, but the wealthiest
stratum obtains a greater per-capita share of the wealth than the lower
strata. In that case, competition would have resulted in growth and
gains for everyone, even while it would have increased wealth
inequality. More competition does not inherently lead to greater
equality.
Indeed, many of the social welfare policy interventions favored by
progressives are designed to mitigate the inequality-inducing effects of
competitive markets. Minimum wage laws require employees to be
compensated based on some measure of merit or need rather than the value
of their marginal contributions as ascertained in competitive labor
markets. Unions had to be exempted from the operation of the antitrust
laws because they replaced labor competition with labor cartelization.
The entire social welfare state is built on the premise that competitive
markets produce socially undesirable outcomes.
So where does the monopoly regressivity claim come from? In the
developing world, the claim can frequently be heard from proponents of
market liberalization. Such groups as the Organization for Economic
Cooperation and Development, United Nations Conference on Trade and
Development, and the World Trade Organization argue that the
introduction of competition law increases the welfare of the poor. And
indeed this story rings true in markets where productive assets are
closely held by a few conglomerate enterprises, labor mobility is low,
capital markets are underdeveloped, former or current state-owned
enterprises enjoy exclusive legal privileges, and trade barriers are
high. Although observe, again, that increasing the wealth of the poor
does not necessarily mean a reduction in the Gini coefficient in
developing countries, if increased competition also creates a class of
nouveau riche.
[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]
As for the developed world, the story is much more complicated. The
argument for the regressivity of monopoly, and hence the progressivity
of antitrust enforcement, is predicated on the belief that
anticompetitive market conditions systematically divert income toward
the wealthy. French economist Thomas Piketty had advanced the
much-publicized argument that market-driven economies produce inequality
when the return to capital exceeds economic growth. Proponents of the
monopoly regressivity claim argue that senior corporate executives and
shareholders are the primary beneficiaries of increasing returns to
capital and hence the primary group to absorb monopoly rents generated
by lax antitrust enforcement. According to this argument, because senior
corporate executives and shareholders are wealthier on average than the
general population, antitrust violations leading to monopoly have
regressive effects. More antitrust, then, would result in a progressive
redistribution of wealth.
For this argument to work, shareholders and senior corporate
managers would have to capture the lion's share of monopoly rents,
whereas relatively less wealthy consumers would have to pay the brunt of
those rents. Is that, in fact, the case?
DO SHAREHOLDERS AND MANAGERS CAPTURE THE RENTS?
Contrary to the claim that senior corporate managers are the
primary beneficiaries of monopoly, the literature on the relationship
between product market competition and executive compensation is
ambiguous. No general case can be made from the literature that chief
executive officer compensation goes up as product market competition
softens. Indeed, some empirical studies show the opposite--that CEO
compensation declines in less competitive markets. The intuition
explaining this effect is that CEO talent may be less valuable to the
corporation in a monopoly market, where earning high profits may be
easier than in a more competitive market.
What about shareholders? Certainly, shareholders capture some gains
from monopoly rents, but that does not necessarily make antitrust
violations regressive. Shareholding is widely distributed in the United
States, with 88 million participants in 401(k) or similar retirement
plans and pensions controlling 16 percent of domestic corporate
equities. So, directly or indirectly, many middle-class interests are
represented among the ranks of shareholders.
Proponents of the monopoly regressivity theory point to studies
showing that shareholding is disproportionately concentrated in the
hands of the very wealthy. But do shareholders reap a significant
portion of the monopoly rents generated by the corporation? While they
surely obtain some of the rents, it is far from clear that they reap the
lion's share.
It has long been understood that various interests within the firm
and outside its borders compete to appropriate any monopoly rents
generated by the corporation. Monopoly profits often do not show up on
corporate balance sheets (where they would benefit shareholders) because
they are eaten up within the firm. A standard trope in antitrust law
concerns the fat, lazy monopolist internally consuming its monopoly
profits through sloth and lack of incentive. As Judge Learned Hand
famously remarked in his landmark Alcoa decision, "Many people
believe that possession of unchallenged economic power deadens
initiative, discourages thrift, and depresses energy; that immunity from
competition is a narcotic." Or, as Nobel laureate John Hicks
remarked, "The best of all monopoly profits is a quiet life."
Workers are one of the groups well documented to benefit from
monopoly power. Empirical studies have shown a monopoly wage premium for
both unionized and non-unionized workers across a wide range of
industries, and also the tendency for unionization to increase with
increases in employer market power. Blue collar workers are thus able to
appropriate some of the monopoly rents generated by their employers.
Consistent with this economic literature, labor unions and other
progressive-leaning groups have sometimes supported large corporate
mergers that raised serious antitrust questions. The Communications
Workers of America supported the AT&T-T-Mobile merger that was
eventually blocked by the U.S. Justice Department and Federal
Communications Commission, and three airline employee unions supported
the controversial (and now widely derided) merger of American Airlines
and USAir. Prominent civil rights organizations have supported such
corporate mergers as Comcast-NBC and SIRIUS-XM. Whether or not those
mergers should have been blocked as anticompetitive, many organizations
ostensibly representing the interests of workers, minorities, and other
arguably disadvantaged groups saw benefits to their constituencies.
A final straw for the claim that shareholders and CEOs are the
chief beneficiaries of anticompetitive behavior arises from the fact
that antitrust law applies to non-corporate actors as much as to
corporate ones. Many of the "producers" whose commercial
agreements have been challenged by antitrust authorities are not
corporate at all, but rather sole proprietors or middle-class
professionals. For example, in 2014 the Federal Trade Commission brought
an enforcement action against an association of music teachers over an
association rule prohibiting teachers from soliciting clients from rival
teachers. According to the U.S. Bureau of Labor Statistics, music
teachers earn a squarely middle-class annual income of $66,000. In the
last two years, the FTC also brought enforcement actions against other
middle-class professions, including property managers, legal support
professionals, lighting and sign managers, and ice skating coaches.
Another case against middle-class professionals, this one brought
by the Justice Department, showcases the potential for antitrust
enforcement to have regressive rather than progressive wealth
distribution effects. In 2005, the Justice Department brought an
antitrust challenge against the National Association of Realtors based
on restrictions on the ability of home buyers to search for real estate
listings over the Internet. According to the Justice Department, the
effect of this restriction was to inflate realtor commissions. If that
allegation was true, then the enforcement action likely had highly
regressive effects. The median income of realtors is $41,990, and that
of home sellers (who typically pay commissions) is $97,500. Any rent
extraction by realtors would be progressive. Further, given the
magnitude of existing home sales ($1.2 trillion annually), the magnitude
of this progressive effect (and, conversely, the regressive effect of
antitrust enforcement) could be measured in the billions of dollars.
To be clear, my point is not to condemn the Justice
Department's enforcement action for its regressivity. Rather, it is
to point out that increased antitrust enforcement cannot be easily
equated with progressive wealth distribution effects.
DO POOR CONSUMERS BEAR THE BRUNT?
For the monopoly regressivity claim to work, not only would
shareholders and senior corporate executives have to be capturing the
preponderance of the monopoly rents, but relatively poorer consumers
would need to be paying for them. The argument for regressivity on the
payer side mirrors the arguments that sales taxes are regressive: since
the wealthy save at a higher rate than the less wealthy, a smaller
percentage of the wealthy's income is exposed to the tax. But this
argument falls apart when it comes to antitrust enforcement, for two
reasons.
First, household consumers are not the purchasers of large swaths
of economic activity covered by the antitrust law. General government
final consumption--government purchases of goods and services--accounts
for 16 percent of GDP. An anticompetitive defense industry merger, bid
rigging by contractors building schools, roads, or bridges, or
monopolistic practices by pharmaceutical companies selling directly or
indirectly to governmentally sponsored health programs result in
overcharges to taxpayers. Because the U.S. tax system is progressive,
those overcharges result in progressive wealth redistribution (at least
on the payer side).
The same holds true in much of the $1 trillion private health
insurance market, which, particularly because of the Affordable Care
Act, is highly progressive in redistributing wealth. Monopolistic
overcharges to third-party payers are passed on progressively to
household consumers, hence the overall effect of monopoly could be
progressive.
Intercorporate effects also mitigate the ostensible regressivity of
antitrust violations. Many antitrust violations happen far upstream of
household consumers. For example, only about 10 percent of cartels sell
directly to retail customers. Most occur in intermediate manufactured
goods, up many levels of manufacturers, assemblers, wholesalers, and
retailers from household consumers. Even if much of the overcharge is
eventually passed downstream to consumers, the absorption of some of the
overcharge in the distribution chain can mitigate any ultimate
regressive effect.
There are two additional reasons why the analogy of antitrust
enforcement and regressivity to sales taxes falls apart. First, the
regressive effect of the sales tax arises because unspent wealth is not
subject to the tax. But where monopoly conditions prevail in banking and
financial services (areas where proponents of the monopoly regressivity
claim have leveled much of their wrath), rents can be extracted from
unspent money as well--for example, through inflated service fees,
deflated interest rates, and the like.
Second, the regressivity of the sales tax depends on its flat rate,
but monopolists do not extract equal proportions of wealth from rich and
poor consumers. Economic theory holds that market power facilitates
price discrimination, and that price discrimination often has
progressive wealth redistribution consequences. In a world of lax
antitrust enforcement leading to greater market power, producers would
extract a higher share of monopoly rents from low-elasticity wealthy
consumers than from high-elasticity poorer consumers.
ANTITRUST AND PRIVATE EQUALITY INITIATIVES
An additional insight into the problem of monopoly and wealth
effects concerns the fact that antitrust enforcement not infrequently
impedes efforts to address issues of inequality through private
coordination. If, as previously argued, untempered market forces
generally tend toward inequality, then private actors committed to
redistributing wealth may need to subvert market forces. In a variety of
cases, such efforts have met with hostility from antitrust institutions.
An important example involves diversity and access to higher
education. Between 1958 and 1991, the eight Ivy League universities and
the Massachusetts Institute of Technology participated in an "Ivy
Overlap Group" that involved financial aid personnel from the
schools agreeing on the financial need profile of any student admitted
to two or more Ivy League Schools and guaranteeing that student an
adequate financial aid package at whatever school he chose to attend.
The schools' goal was to shift from merit-based financial aid,
which allocated scarce financial aid resources to privileged applicants
who often didn't need the money, to need-based aid. The schools
reported significant increases in income, racial, and demographic
diversity because of the Overlap program.
In 1991, the Justice Department brought an antitrust challenge that
resulted in the abandonment of the Overlap program. For better or worse,
antitrust killed a program ostensibly designed to redistribute wealth
and opportunity progressively.
The Overlap case is by no means unique. The currently pending class
action challenge to National Collegiate Athletic Association rules
limiting player compensation could well result in the enrichment of a
handful of star male football and basketball players at the expense of
less popular athletic programs and women's sports. U.S garment
manufacturers have cited antitrust fears in declining to organize
collectively to pressure their global suppliers to improve labor
conditions. In many other cases, antitrust law's insistence on
competition and market-determined allocation of resources flies in the
face of private efforts to achieve a more equitable distribution of
wealth or related social justice objectives.
CONCLUSION
Again, none of this should be taken as an indictment of antitrust
enforcement. There are many legitimate reasons other than wealth
inequality to take on monopolies and cartels. But it is time for
progressives to remove antitrust from their wealth inequality playbook.
In a time of anti-corporate sentiment, that theme may play well
politically, but it cannot withstand serious scrutiny.
DANIEL A. CRANE is associate dean for faculty and research at the
University of Michigan Law School.