Is an optimal carbon tax relevant? Political forces threaten to push carbon taxes too high.
Sutter, Daniel
Bob Litterman discusses the factors determining an optimal price or
tax for carbon emissions (p. 38). The exercise illustrates that from an
economic perspective climate change is not catastrophic, but is likely
to be of minimal importance in the ultimate determination of such a tax.
However, a carbon tax, once adopted, could easily be raised to a level
that chokes off economic growth--which would be catastrophic. Attempting
to calculate the optimal tax might have an unintended consequence of
making a terrible policy accident more likely.
A carbon tax rate would not be set at a permanent level when first
implemented. As Litterman notes, the optimal tax would likely increase
over time and new information about climate change or its consequences
could update the optimal rate. Adoption of a tax would have to include a
mechanism for future adjustments. Yet the optimal tax cannot be
precisely calculated; uncertainties about both the magnitude of losses
and the probability distribution of losses preclude precision in this
calculation. Congress could not commit, even if it wanted to, to setting
the tax based on the solution to the economic optimization problem. This
should not come as a surprise because efficiency is logically coherent
but difficult to operationalize.
Excessive tax | Adoption of a carbon tax commits us to the chosen
mechanism for adjusting tax rates. The case for a tax in the range
implied by many economic models ($5 to $25 per ton) is strong because,
even if one is highly skeptical about climate change and its potential
adverse effects on society, the probability of substantial costs must be
closer to 0.2 than zero. On the other hand, a carbon tax could be an
economic catastrophe if the tax ends up well above the range implied by
economic models.
An excessive tax is likely for three reasons. First, even within
the economic models, assumptions can be made that increase the present
value of the cost of carbon substantially. If truly catastrophic effects
are possible or if the catastrophic losses are sufficiently likely, an
optimal tax will be much larger. Climate change poses uncertainty and
not risk, as Litterman notes, and we have no evidence to rule out a
fat-tailed distribution of truly catastrophic outcomes. Consequently,
the adjustment process could readily be freed from any tight anchoring.
Second, many people reject setting a carbon tax based on economic
efficiency. Some scientists and engineers believe that carbon emissions
must be reduced to zero over the next 50 years to avert a catastrophe.
Other proponents see the threat of climate change as a means to achieve
fundamental societal changes. A carbon tax of even $100 a ton translates
to about $1 per gallon of gas, insufficient to stop Americans from
driving their cars. Many constituents would demand a tax well in excess
of any calculated economic optimal, and would lobby for steep increases.
Thus even if the establishment of a carbon tax is cast in the framework
of efficiency, once a tax and adjustment mechanism are in place, the tax
could be increased on other grounds.
Third, political equilibrium suggests a balancing of these lobbying
interests. Those advocating a carbon tax based on efficiency would
oppose any increase above the efficient level, but the strength of their
opposition would depend on their loss relative to the efficient price,
which is small for a price just above the efficient level. Efficiency
advocates would only really raise a fuss as the price rises beyond the
range of possible efficient values. Meanwhile, advocates of phasing out
fossil fuel use would engage in a full-court press to raise the tax from
the efficient level. Political balancing of these two lobbying groups
would lead inevitably to a price higher than the efficient level, even
if each group has similar overall political influence. As a result, the
economically efficient price is implausible as a political equilibrium.
While a small carbon tax might have net benefits, politically our
choices are likely between an excessive and perhaps prohibitive tax and
no tax at all. Once an apparatus for carbon taxation is in place,
discretion would lead to an excessive price. Citizens' only
recourse, if government discretion cannot be checked, is not allowing
government action at all. The zeal of climate change proponents
ironically might make adoption of an efficient tax less likely. The
argument here is of a second-best nature: it is not that a carbon tax of
any magnitude is harmful, but that the equilibrium tax will be worse
than no tax.
Projected economic growth provides perspective on the case for a
carbon tax. As Indur Goklany has argued, future generations in 2100 or
2200 will be significantly better off than people today without
mitigation under all climate change scenarios. This suggests that the
gains from an optimal carbon tax would be small. But future growth is
not guaranteed, especially if aggressive policies against climate change
are adopted. A carbon tax to reduce emissions to zero would likely
devolve into carbon rationing. Modest taxes will not reduce the use of
fossil fuels to zero, while a tax large enough to do so would result in
evasion. Consequently, command-and-control policies would be required to
ration fossil fuel usage toward zero. Given that energy use drives the
economy, carbon rationing would effectively amount to energy central
planning.
Calculating an optimal tax might have the unintended consequence of
making such a catastrophe more likely. Who could be against an optimal
carbon tax if it raises the price of gasoline by a quarter a gallon or
less? Economists offer a disarming case for taxing carbon. But promises
regarding taxes are notoriously unreliable; the 16~h Amendment was
adopted in part because Americans were promised that only the rich would
ever pay an income tax. Once established, politicians will set tax rates
based on predictable political forces.
Economic growth has been the exceptional condition in human
history, not the normal, and growth only began with the establishment of
the institutions of the market economy. Energy central planning would
force abandonment of market allocation of factors of production. Given
the potential for capture by interests looking to eliminate carbon
emissions, a carbon tax could spell the end of growth, courtesy of
government planning. Although catastrophe scenarios are usually invoked
to motivate action on climate change, the true catastrophe would be to
allow an excessive carbon tax to undermine prosperity.
READINGS
* "A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political
Influence," by Gary Becket. Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 98
(1983).
* "Discounting the Future, "by Indur Goklany. Regulation,
Vol. 32, No. 1 (Spring 2009).
* "Discretionary Policy Implementation and Reform," by
Daniel Sutter. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 39
(1999).
* "Rethinking Wedges," by Steven
J. Davis, Long Cao, Ken Caldeira, and Martin I. Hoffert.
Environmental Research Letters, Vol. 8 (2013).
* "The Constitution of Economic Policy," by James M.
Buchanan. American Economic Review, Vol. 77 (1987).
* The Reason of Rules, by Geoffrey Brennan and James M. Buchanan.
Cambridge University Press, 1985.
* "Towards a More General Theory of Regulation," by Sam
Peltzman. Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 19 (August 1976).
DANIEL SUTTER is the Charles G. Koch Professor of Economics at the
Manuel H. Johnson Center for Political Economy at Troy University and a
visiting scholar with the Center for Regulatory Studies at the George
Washington University.