Equal dignity under the law.
Mohr, Richard D.
A DISTRAUGHT STUDENT slips into the office of her high school
guidance counselor. The student thinks she might be a lesbian. It is
dawning on her that she seems to like girls rather than boys. And
someone has just called her a derogatory name. The counselor tries to
console, advise--counsel--the student to the best of her ability, given
available resources. She suggests that being a lesbian is not the end of
the world, that she herself, for example, likes women. Buoyed by her
success counseling this student and another gay male student, the
counselor begins to mention her bisexuality to some of the school's
faculty. In consequence, she is fired. After a decade bouncing around
the courts, her case reaches the U.S. Supreme Court in 1985; but only
two justices--half the number needed--even want to hear her case, which
claims her rights to equal protection have been violated. And so the
Court lets stand a ruling that allows Ohio to fire all its gay and
lesbian school teachers on the basis of their sexual orientation alone.
Two decades later, this state of legal affairs is unchanged.
This essay examines how we ought to understand the elusive concept
"equal" when used in the Constitution's cryptic, if
moving, promise that "no person shall be denied the equal
protection of the law." It explores the moral background of the
country's century-old belief that governments, both state and
federal, should not be allowed to discriminate and tries to determine
whether the constitutional promise of equality should be extended to
include the protection of lesbians and gay men--as it currently does
not. Indeed, across the whole range of law, it is on issues of equality
that gays have made the least progress to date. Neither the Supreme
Court nor any of the thirteen federal Circuit Courts has viewed gays as
having the same levels of protections against governmental
discrimination that blacks, women, and even illegal immigrant children
have. (1) The same is true of state supreme courts. Not one has held
that gays have the same equal protection rights held by blacks or women
under their state constitutions. Even in Vermont, where its supreme
court held in 1999 that the state had to give gay couples benefits
identical to those of heterosexually married couples, it did not use the
equal protection provision of its state constitution as the vehicle for
the ruling.
WHAT IS EQUALITY?
The task here is not an easy one. For it requires answering the
contested questions: What do we mean by equality anyway? What counts as
discrimination? Are lesbians and gay men relevantly like other minority
groups--blacks, the Irish, women, Jews, the handicapped, Mormons, and
others--traditionally thought deserving of protection from governmental
discrimination? And, for that matter, what is a "minority"?
I suggest that equality in a moral sense is at heart a principle
that asserts individuals as having equal dignity or personhood. Rising
to the level of a right, equality is the authoritative claim that a
person will not be held in lesser regard--as having less worth--unless
that lesser regard is warranted by something the person has (or has not)
done. A person may be held in lower regard, even contempt, because of
some action he performs (say, lying, thieving, murdering) or because of
his failure to perform some duty (say, neglecting to pay his taxes or
feed his kids). Such acts and omissions permit and warrant censure and
punishment. But a person may not legitimately be held in lower regard
because of some status he or she has, some group-membership independent
of any action that establishes the person as a member of the group.
Equality at its core does not merely hold that one should treat
similar cases similarly, that people should have equal access to
whatever (other) rights there are. This merely formal principle is a
component of procedural justice, but it does not exhaust or even capture
the core of equality. Indeed if this were all equality is, equality
would not add anything to whatever other rights there are, for all it
would entail is that a right or a law should be applied consistently in
its own terms--whatever those terms are. If its terms draw distinctions
between groups, then so would its consistent application.
As odd as it may sound at first hearing, equality also cannot only
or essentially mean equality of opportunity, though talk of
"equality of opportunity" is quite entrenched in
America's folk rhetoric of justice and even in its institutional
titles. The chief federal agency for the enforcement of the 1964 Civil
Rights Act, for example, is called the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission.
Equality means something more. Consider the following paradigmatic racist joke taken from Blanche Knott's Truly Tasteless Jokes, II:
"What do you call a black millionaire physicist who's just won
the Nobel Prize? Answer: Nigger!" Here the incongruity which is the
basis of the joke's supposed fun is that while the joke's
subject through his actions has achieved the pinnacle of socially
measured success, still he is viewed as a lesser, even naturally
debased, being. The joke turns on the presumed (white) listener's
assumption that the person's race makes him in some crucial sense
unequal--assigns him a status, a grade of existence, immeasurably lower
than the average person, the listener, even though his accomplishments
are infinitely higher.
The joke is revelatory for understanding equality. First, the
structure of the joke's humiliating fun shows that equality cannot
chiefly mean equality of opportunity. The person in the joke has availed
himself of and realized opportunity as fully as anyone could. The
joke's butt could not launch a suit against the joke's teller,
or anyone else, claiming that he had been denied access to some right,
some freedom, some opportunity--for he has it all. Rather the joke
presumes that true equality is a consequence of one's status and
has nothing to do with one's actions. In the joke's moral
system, which is to say America's popular morality, this person
could never be equal no matter what he did.
Second, the joke shows that the lesser status which inequality
assigns its object is a devolution away from the standard of full
personhood. Here race eliminates the subject of the joke from being
viewed fully as a person--that is, as an individual with ends of his
own, the ability to revise those ends, and the ability to respect others
as having ends of their own. The subject is viewed rather as at best an
object, tool, or thing. In the social dynamics of this joke, the black
person is merely an instrument for others' entertainment, like a
porpoise at Sea World.
This same moral vision was espoused by the Supreme Court in the
landmark Dred Scott decision of 1856 when it upheld the moral
acceptability of slavery, claiming that blacks are an "unfortunate
race ... [correctly] regarded as being of an inferior order, and
altogether unfit to associate with the white race, either in social or
political relations; and so far inferior, that they had no rights which
the white man was bound to respect; that the Negro might justly and
lawfully be reduced to slavery for his own benefit." Although
slavery is, like a tax too high, an unjust restriction on liberty, the
chief moral problem with slavery is that it is a violation of equality.
An injury, a harm, or a restriction to one's freedom may interrupt
one's ability to carry out one's life plan, but an assault on
equality, viewed as individual dignity, presumes that one is not even
the sort of thing to deserve the status of having a life plan in the
first place. To be treated inequitably is to be held in morally lesser
regard independently of what one has done. It is to suffer degradation
and humiliation.
Now admittedly, dignity itself is an elusive notion, but it can be
placed in a conceptual network that helps clarify its nature. Consider
what counts as a harm or offense against dignity. The common phrase
"adding insult to injury" affords an intuitive grasp of a
distinction between two types of offense. An insult is an offense
against dignity, while an injury is something that reduces one's
happiness, denies one some benefit, wealth, power, or useful possession,
or generally reduces one's material circumstances in the world.
This distinction between dignity and well-being or happiness is
also reflected in the different moral emotions we feel toward those
whose well-being or dignity is of interest to us. The moral emotion that
has happiness and harm as its proper objects is sympathetic
concern--sympathetic joy or sympathetic sorrow. But we feel sympathetic
concern, even love, for things which are not full persons, for example,
pets. In contrast, the appropriate moral feeling directed to
another's dignity is not sympathy, but respect. If our regard for
others does not include respect, we fail to treat them as persons, and
treat them instead as lesser beings.
Insults are a graver form of evil than injuries, for they attack
persons as persons--in two ways. First, by focusing importance on
largely irrelevant characteristics, insults treat the insulted as though
their moral agency counts for nothing. Thus raw invectives like
"nigger" and "faggot" violate their targets'
right to equal respect in that the insulted person's ability to
formulate and carry out a plan of life--to realize his desires, plans,
aspirations, and sense of the sacred--is not considered worthy of social
care and concern on a par with that of others.
Second, by holding a person in morally diminished regard, insults
also show disrespect for persons by treating those insulted as though
they were not really full moral agents to begin with. In this way,
metaphor-inflected invective (say, calling a black adult male
"boy" or "buck" or a woman "babe,"
"girl," "bitch," or "cow") demotes the
insulted person to the level of children or non-human animals, creatures
who are not held responsible for their actions, who are not viewed as
creators of their own destinies, and who require paternalistic
intervention for their own good.
THE LANGUAGE OF INSULT
The ill-treatment of gay men and lesbians chiefly takes the form of
denials of equality. To be sure, lesbians and gay men are subject to
violations of freedom and inflictions of severe harms. Still, these
violations and inflictions are usually perpetrated with an eye to their
serving as vehicles for the denial of equality. Being fired or being
physically attacked because one is gay is a harm, but even more so it is
a degradation. In cracking the skull of one gay man, the queer basher is
looking to insult all gay men, by framing all gay men as being
death-worthy for who they are. The particular victim is a standin for
the whole group. Gay oppression is chiefly the denial of gay dignity.
A look in some detail at language will perhaps provide the most
telling complex of examples to show that gays in America are indeed
viewed--and, in turn, treated inequitably--as a group degraded
independently of any behavior that makes one a member of the group.
Surprisingly, even non-slang terms used to denote gay men and
lesbians preponderantly indicate that society does not think of
homosexuals as defined by certain kinds of acts. Dictionaries'
tracking of common usage and their definitions of "homosexual"
reveal much, especially ones from the era before the gay rights movement
made the term "homosexual" a contested one. The Oxford English
Dictionary (1964) defines "homosexual" simply and solely as
"having a sexual propensity for persons of one's own
sex." Similarly Webster's New Twentieth Century (1952) has for
the adjective "characterized by sexual inclination toward the same
sex," and for the noun "one whose emotions, feelings, and
desires are concerned with the individual's own sex rather than
with the opposite sex." No mention of actions is made here. Actions
are not necessary for the label to apply to a person. Nor, importantly,
are actions here even sufficient for the label to apply. For one can,
and quite often does, will and perform actions without having a desire,
inclination, propensity, or (positive) feeling for the actions
performed--carrying out arduous tasks and undergoing major surgery are
actions of this sort.
Anti-gay slurs in American English also target a person's
status rather than behavior. With the apparent exception of
"cocksucker," no widespread anti-gay slur gives any indication
that its censure is directed at sex acts rather than despised social
status. Group-directed slurs (dyke, queer, fag) place lesbians and gay
men in a significant social category along with blacks (nigger, shine,
shitskin), other racial groups (chink), women (cunt, gash), various
ethnic groups (wop, dago, gook, jap, JAP, mick, kike), religious groups
(kike, papist, christer), native peoples (redskin, injun, eskimo),
non-native peoples (kike, gypsy), and the physically challenged (crip,
gimp, veg, vegetable, crispy critter). It does not place them in the
same category as liars, hypocrites, murderers, and thieves--those who
commit immoral and criminal actions and yet for whom culture in no case
has coined group-based invectives. This schema of slurs strongly
suggests that gay men and lesbians are held to be immoral because they
are hated, rather than hated because they are immoral.
Many slang pejoratives explicitly denote homosexual status rather
than homosexual acts. The whole host of putdowns of gay men nominally
based on charges of effeminacy are of this sort. They put down gay men
not as performers of sodomy but as having a low status derivative from
the low status in which society holds women, and additionally from the
sense that they have betrayed their socially assigned gender-status. To
be sure, betrayal is a willful action, but here it is not the
willfulness of being a "queen" that is the brunt of slurs like
"sissy" and "nelly." It is the challenge which the
queen's status presents to socially-managed gender distinctions
that is condemned. Hence the condemnation of will is inextricably bound
up with the protection of status--the queen's very existence is a
challenge to the status of "real manhood." Action has little
to do with the perceived threat.
Another large set of slurs explicitly denotes status in their
metaphoric vehicles, and thus suggest that their target--male
homosexuality--is also being viewed as a status. These slurs include:
pansy, panz, fruit, fruitcake, and finocchio (Italian for fennel and the
name of a decades-old Sausalito transvestite bar). These slurs, which
have no lesbian counterparts, obviously make no reference to behavior of
any kind. All of them derive from the cosmic order "vegetable"
and vegetables don't do anything.
These slurs suggest that America's mind believes in a Great
Chain of Moral Being. Straight men--fully real persons--constitute the
highest tier of all the gradations of human moral worth. Of sublunary beings, they are nearest the ascending heavenly hierarchy of saints,
cherubim, seraphim, archangels, and gods. Descending down the Chain from
real men, we arrive next at women, whose nature is essentially,
abidingly, and pervasively viewed in slang as animal. Women are chiefly
referred to in slurs by designations of animal species (bitch, beaver,
cow, fish, vixen, pussy, shrew), by terms that assimilate women to
immature animals and children (chick, doll, babe, baby, girl), or which
reduce women to the body parts by which their animality differs from
that of males (cunt, gash, beaver, pussy, bag, muff, rack). Note that
there are no corresponding derogatory terms for males in contemporary
culture. The derogatory terms that have male genitalia as their
metaphoric vehicles--prick, dick, dickhead--are not in fact putdowns of
men as men, but are simply equivalents to "bozo,"
"dolt," or "jerk." Real men are unassailable. Their
antipode down at the bottom of the human heap is vegetable
existence--pansies, fruits, and the physically challenged, who, like gay
men, also are typically denoted and demoted with vegetative slurs. The
lowly placement of gay men on a scale which contains women, men, and the
congenitally deformed shows that the social treatment of gay men depends
not upon what they do, but upon some perceived degenerate status.
Quite generally then, it would appear that when animosity against
some group reaches a level where the group is the subject of highly
developed, sharply derisive slang and the butt of vicious jokes, then
the group's members are being held accountable not for what they
do, but for what they are. At present society chooses to treat gay men
and lesbians not as agents of their own destiny, but simply as having a
degenerate status for which questions of action and accountability are
irrelevant.
SOCIAL FORMS THAT DEGRADE GAYS
In addition to the linguistic record, much more and diverse
evidence shows that in lopsided preponderance society views lesbians and
gay men first and foremost as morally lesser beings. In the 1980's
three major institutions--the military, religion, and medicine--weighed
in to affirm the moral model that classifies lesbians and gay men by
status rather than actions.
The military: According to the formulations developed in the early
1980's to carry out the military's ban on homosexuals, it
turns out that engaging in homosexual behavior is neither a necessary
nor a sufficient condition for being considered a homosexual and treated
accordingly. In these formulations, homosexual desire (as expressed,
say, in a diary entry) is, even in the absence of any behavior,
sufficient to have one kicked out of the Armed Forces for being
homosexual; yet if a member of the Armed Forces is caught actually
performing homosexual acts, he is permitted to plead successfully that
these do not indicate his true nature and that "such conduct is a
departure from the member's usual and customary behavior." One
may claim, "Just skylarking," or "Boy, was I drunk last
night," and be retained. Clearly, here it is one's status as a
homosexual--a status that can float completely separate from any
behavior--that is the brunt of military policy.
Religion: In 1986, the Catholic Church, in a major ideological
shift, branded as "an objective moral disorder" the mere
status of being a homosexual, even when congenitally fixed and
unaccompanied by any homosexual behavior. Previously such status had
been viewed as morally neutral and only homosexual acts--sins--were
morally censured. Both the Vatican letter stating this shift, a 1992
Vatican letter interpreting it as warranting employment discrimination
against lesbian and gay men, and a Vatican letter of 2003 saying that
the mere presence of gay people constitutes violence against children,
all seemed, by their wording and the way they framed issues, to be a
specific response to the development of lesbian and gay politics in the
United States. (2) Political stirring produced ideological retrenchment,
in a way, though, that tipped religion's hand. The Catholic
Church's conception of gay people is a species of racism.
Medicine: On April 15, 1985, in Atlanta, during the keynote address
for the first International Conference on AIDS, President Reagan's
Secretary of Health and Human Services, Margaret Heckler, in a burst of
good intentions gone painfully awry, held: "We must conquer AIDS
before it affects the heterosexual population ... the general
population. We have a very strong public interest in stopping AIDS
before it spreads outside the risk groups, before it becomes an
overwhelming problem." The determinate prospect of a million or so
dead gay men was not seen to be a problem for the Reagan administration.
Now, in America the value of a person's life is not normally pegged
by reference to the means by which the person comes to have diseases.
For instance, the life of a CEO who suffers a heart attack from years of
gluttony is not thought to be worth less than that of a person who
suffers a heart attack under torture. So that even if one drew a moral
distinction between the HIV-conveying sex acts of heterosexuals and
those of homosexuals, still this would not ground a further distinction
between lives to be saved and lives to be junked. So it is not the moral
assessment of actions which grounds Heckler's distinction; rather
she holds heterosexual status as more worthy of care and concern than
gay men's status. Gays, here, are lesser beings; their agency
doesn't matter.
The social understanding of homosexuality essentially as a
degenerate status rather than as a form of censurable behavior was given
its most clear and honest formulation in the 20th century by Heinrich
Himmler, who, in a speech to his SS generals, explained that the
medieval German practice of drowning male homosexuals in bogs "was
no punishment, merely the extermination of an abnormal life. It had to
be removed just as we [now] pull up stinging nettles, toss them on a
heap, and burn them."
DEMOCRATIC PRACTICES
On this view, a minority, for the purposes of law, will simply be
any group whose members are held in morally lesser regard independently
of what they do. When a group is socially presumed to be unworthy, it
can hardly be expected to be treated equally in democratic decision
making. Quite apart from any history of intentional discrimination
against gay men and lesbians, the combination of widespread background
presumptions that gays are degraded beings and the existence of anti-gay
stereotypes that operate as unacknowledged social lenses in policy
making ensures that democratic processes cannot be relied upon to ensure
fair and impartial treatment of gay and lesbian concerns. Indeed the
effects of false presumptions and stereotypes in society's
judgment-making undercut the very grounds for affirming representational
democracy as a form of government. When these presumptions and
stereotypes are rife in culture, representative democracy cannot justify
its policies as being the product of rational deliberation. For reasons
of the coherence of democratic theory, gays and lesbians ought to be
given the same equal protection rights against governmental
discrimination which the courts have given to blacks and women.
To put it bluntly: If the Supreme Court, which is structurally
positioned to be above the fray of politics, can admit in 2003 that it
itself has been unable to give gay men and lesbians a fair shake--as it
admits in Lawrence v. Texas's recantation of Bowers v. Hardwick (1986)--then it would be irrational for the Court to assume that the
fray of politics itself can give gay men and lesbians a fair shake. If
the Court's redemptive reading of itself in Lawrence is not to ring
as just so much hollow self-congratulations, the Court must now begin to
move aggressively to address the remaining areas of law where
distinctions are drawn with reference to sexual orientation.
How, then, are we to assess whether specific laws are inequitable?
A law will be a violation of equality if it draws upon or in its effects
enhances the view that some group is held in morally lesser regard
independently of any action that puts a member of the group in the
group. A law does not violate equality simply by virtue of its
distributing some benefit or opportunity differently between two groups.
As important: nor will the law necessarily be an equitable treatment by
virtue of its distributing the same benefits and opportunities to
different groups.
A differential distribution violates equality only if the
distribution draws on or enhances society's perception that one of
the groups is worthy of less moral regard than the other. So, for
example, an affirmative action program which gives some benefits and
opportunities to blacks which it does not give to whites would be
inequitable only if the differential distribution would be socially read
as deriving from or reinforcing social structures that hold white people
in lesser moral regard than blacks--an impossibility in current American
culture.
On the other hand, an identical distribution will be inequitable if
it socially serves as a means of insulting, humiliating or degrading one
of the groups. Such is the case in most separate-but-equal schemes.
To determine whether a distribution insults or degrades a group,
one has to look at the social context of the distribution. In some
societies, a flicked middle-finger might be a serious insult, in others
it might be a meaningless gesture, in still others it might be a sign of
greeting. More specifically, whether the flicked finger is an insult
depends on how the culture reads the symbolism of the gesture. It does
not turn on whether the target of the gesture reads it as an insult.
Indeed the target need not even know that he has been insulted--he can
be insulted nonetheless. Thus we say that a person can be insulted
behind her back or even beyond the grave.
The Supreme Court got this all backwards in the 1896 case Plessy v.
Ferguson with which "separate but equal" was established as
the law of land for over half a century. The Court was wrong, almost
certainly disingenuous, when it claimed that if blacks were insulted by
being forced to sit in racially segregated railway coaches, the insult
was the result of black's sensitivities, not of the Louisiana law
mandating the segregation. The Louisiana legislature knew how the
segregation would be socially read and the law was passed for that very
reason. This segregation, like anti-miscegenation laws, gave blacks and
whites the same opportunities--blacks could not marry whites or sit in
their coaches, whites could not marry blacks or sit in their
coaches--but such identical treatments were inequitable because,
socially viewed, the identical distributions were still means of society
viewing blacks in lower social regard than whites. So the Supreme Court
correctly ruled in 1967 in Loving v. Virginia, when it finally declared
anti-miscegenation laws unconstitutional violations of equality.
WHY "CIVIL UNION" DOESN'T PASS MUSTER
Now consider states like Vermont which have established licensing
schemes which give homosexual couples exactly the same benefits and
opportunities as they give heterosexual couples--except for the name
"marriage" on the licenses issued to secure the rights and
benefits. The licenses for gay and lesbian couples instead have
"civil union" written on them. Is this licensing scheme an
equitable treatment of gay men and lesbians?
It would not be an equitable treatment of lesbians and gay men,
even if it were to give more privileges and benefits to them than to
heterosexuals, just as it would still be inequitable to require blacks
to sit at the back of a bus even if the bus had a "rear exit
only" requirement that gave blacks the opportunity to exit the bus
out the back door first. The reason is that the culture reads the ritual
of placing blacks at the back of the bus as degrading to blacks.
So too, reserving the sacred sign "marriage" for
heterosexuals when homosexuals are offered separate-but-equal civil
unions, serves--and only serves--to degrade gay men and lesbians by
denying them one of the chief social forms by access to which America
marks out membership in full humanity. It is not just a word that is at
stake, it is a highly symbolic civic ritual that civil union schemes
deny gay men and lesbians. And the more politicians of all stripes call
the institution of marriage itself sacred, rather than the love within a
marriage or the couple's sacred valuing of their relationship, the
more inequitable the separate-but-equal scheme becomes.
In December 2003, the Massachusetts legislature asked the
state's highest court whether a civil-union arrangement that gave
lesbian and gay couples all the rights and benefits of marriage, only
just not the name "marriage," would meet the standard for
equal treatment laid out in the court's November 2003 decision
giving gay and lesbian couples the right to marry. By a four-to-three
vote the Court answered, "No." (3) To the bewilderment of the
dissenting judges, the Court clarified that, as far as equality was
concerned, the civil-union scheme was a more inequitable treatment of
gay and lesbian couples than the state's past refusals to grant
them marriage licenses, despite all the goodies that come along with
civil-union status, goodies which lesbian and gay couples did not have
under the state's marriage laws. The reason: The state's past
refusal to give marriage licenses to gay and lesbian couples was based
on a statute that, when it was drawn into Massachusetts law from the
English common law in 1810, was not established with lesbians and gay
men in mind. The Massachusetts marriage law did not intentionally draw
distinctions on the basis of sexual orientation. By contrast, the
civil-union scheme was intentionally drawn to distinguish heterosexuals
from gays, and since all the rights and obligations of unions and
marriages would be the same under the scheme, the distinction was wholly
drawn to differentiate gays from heterosexuals. The differentiation
itself is one thick with social significance: "The [civil unions]
bill would have the effect of maintaining and fostering a stigma of
exclusion that the Constitution prohibits. It would deny to same-sex
'spouses' only a status that is specially recognized in
society and has significant social and other advantages. The
Massachusetts Constitution does not permit such invidious discrimination, no matter how well intended."
HETEROSEXUAL SUPREMACY
All this is true, but one could press even farther. The law (it
will be remembered) claims--and so does any society that accepts the
law's claim--that marriage is the only legally acknowledged
relation between the sexes. Through marriage the law creates the legal
relation between the sexes; the law, in short, creates heterosexuality,
legally speaking. Without legal marriage the sexes would be as related
to each other at law as mangos and tangos. Marriage more
generally--religious, social, as well as legal marriage--needs to be
understood as an institution that creates a social status, in particular
a heterosexual status--and then ratifies that status. Marriage--the
legal and social ritual--doesn't lay value on something that
already exists. It draws into being a social form, even as it ratifies
that very form.
Marriage, in short, is an initiation ritual. A typical initiation
ritual takes a male and turns him into a Man. Biology and
non-ritualistic behavior could not do that. So too biology and
non-ritualistic behavior could not turn a person into a heterosexual.
Indeed Don Juan, Casanova, and Lothario, those frisky male seducers of
endlessly numerous ladies, are now taken as cultural symbols for
homosexual denial rather than heterosexual affirmation. Not biology, not
behavior, but marital status is the social essence of heterosexuality.
And the required ritual of marriage, getting wed--the legally, socially,
religiously required ceremony of solemnization--is the initiation rite
that both confers that status and endows it with value.
So, the social and political stakes in marriage turn out to be much
higher than even the Massachusetts court realized. It is not just any
old non-material benefit that gays and lesbians are being denied by
civil-union schemes, important as such non-material benefit may be, say,
access in a theater to the even numbered seats, which are thought to be
particularly dear to the gods, even though the view of the stage is just
as good from the odd numbered seats. Rather, in civil-union schemes, all
of the sanctity and holiness associated with heterosexual status per se
as created and ratified by the ritualistic solemnizing of marriages
would be denied gays and lesbians by law. And more even than that, as
intentionally and wholly designed to symbolically differentiate
heterosexuals from gays around the very institution by which in the eyes
of the law and society heterosexuality is established, the
separate-but-equal civil-union scheme flags to society that to let
lesbians and gays marry would be not just to besmirch the sanctity of
heterosexuality, but more so to destroy Heterosexuality itself.
Analogously, if a colonial ruler imposed a new order of equality
mandating that henceforth both males and females must go through the
initiation rituals of Manhood, then for those upon whom the new order is
imposed, the new order would destroy Manhood, would destroy what it is
to be a Man.
Civil-union schemes, then, are instruments in the
institutionalization of Heterosexual Supremacy, just as, in the
racist's mind, letting a black man marry a white woman would not
just besmirch Whiteness, but would also destroy the very ritual,
pureblood marriage, by which Caucasians are initiated into Whiteness,
are made White, and so further would destroy Whiteness itself, what it
means to be White. The parallels here between gays' justice and
blacks' is more uncanny than even most lesbian and gay activists
realize. In 1967, when the Supreme Court ruled anti-miscegenation laws
unconstitutional violations of equality, it did so on the ground that
such laws were "measures designed to maintain White
Supremacy." A future Court should declare civilunion schemes
violations of equality on the ground that they are measures designed to
create and maintain Heterosexual Supremacy.
It goes almost without saying that the enormous political
resistance to gay marriage lies in the masses' conception of
themselves as heterosexual. If gays could get married, heterosexuals
would no longer be Heterosexuals. They would just be people. Horrors!
NOTES
1. Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U.S. 429 (1984) (blacks); Craig v. Boren,
429 U.S. 190 (1976) (women), Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202 (1982) (illegal
immigrant children).
2. Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, "Declaration
Persona humana" (December 29, 1975), "Letter on the Pastoral
Care of Homosexual Persons" (October 1, 1986). "Some
Considerations concerning the Response to Legislative Proposals on the
Non-discrimination of Homosexual Persons (July 24, 1992),
"Considerations regarding Proposals to Give Legal Recognition to
Unions between Homosexual Persons" (July 31, 2003).
3. Goodridge v. Dept. of Public Health, 798 N.E.2d 941 (Mass.
2003); In re Opinions of the Justices to the Senate, 802 N.E.2d 565
(Mass. 2004).
Richard Mohr is Professor of Philosophy at the University of
Illinois-Urbana and author of The Long Arc of Justice: Lesbian and Gay
Marriage, Equality, and Rights (Columbia University Press, January
2005), from which this essay is excerpted.