Liberalism in the post-9/11 world *.
Boettke, Peter J. ; Coyne, Christopher J.
The current approach to the war on terror is largely ineffective.
Central to this approach are negative sanctions against actual and
potential terrorists coupled with attempts to spread liberal democracy
through war, occupation and reconstruction. We argue that negative
sanctions are unsuccessful and in many cases counter productive in
reducing terrorism. Further, we postulate that efforts to impose liberal
democracy in weak and failed states via occupation and reconstruction
have in large part failed. Only be returning to a position of principled
non-intervention can the war on terror ultimately be won.
Jel: B 52, B53, O17.
INTRODUCTION
Defined by the U.S. Department of Defense as the "unlawful use
of--or threatened use of--force or violence against individuals or
property to coerce or intimidate governments or societies, often to
achieve political, religious, or ideological objectives" (quoted in
Frey 2004, pp. 9), terrorism has a long and storied history. (1) The
term 'terrorism' originated during the French
Revolution's "Reign of Terror" (1793-1794). In that
period, Robespierre's Jacobins executed 12,000 people who were
deemed to be enemies of the Revolution. Over the following two hundred
years, terrorism has manifested itself in a number of forms and
locations throughout the world. The topic of terrorism received renewed
and increasing attention in the Western world at the beginning of the
new millennium with the World Trade Center attacks on September 11,
2001. On that date, two passenger airplanes were hijacked and
deliberately flown into the two towers of the World Trade Center in New
York City. A simultaneous attack took place against the Pentagon with a
single plane while another airplane crashed in Pennsylvania.
The 9/11 attacks involved the use of modern technology by foreign
hijackers to inflict harm upon innocent civilians. Terrorists
effectively turned instruments of progress into weapons of destruction
targeting clear symbols of modern western society. In total, the 9/11
related casualties were approximately 3,000 people from over 90
countries. Further, the 9/11 attacks marked the beginning of the modern
"war on terror." (2) The wars and ongoing reconstruction
efforts in Afghanistan and Iraq were two early manifestations of this
larger effort to eradicate terrorism. To understand the magnitude of the
war on terror, consider the monetary costs. Funding for homeland
security increased drastically after 9/11 including $64 billion in
emergency funds for 2001 and 2002. In total, between 2001 and 2003,
total funding for homeland security increased by 240%. (3) It is
difficult to obtain the exact costs to date of the war and
reconstruction in Iraq. However, estimates range from $100-$200 billion.
(4)
In the post-9/11 world, it would appear that liberalism has little
to offer. In the face of the threat of terrorist, the U.S. federal
government has significantly increased its level of intervention in a
wide array of activities as evidenced by the Patriot Act. From increased
federal involvement in airport security to widening the legality of the
ability of the federal government to engage in surveillance and the
detention of terrorist suspects, the federal government is seen by most
as the key player in the larger war against terror. (5) It is our
contention that the line of reasoning underlying these policies is in
need of revision. A return to a political economy of classical
liberalism, and not a reliance on government war socialism, is the most
effective means of reducing terrorism.
While both authors of this paper are committed non-interventionists
in foreign policy, we do not argue in this paper from the perspective of
first-principles. Instead, for the sake of argument in this paper we
attempt to argue as pure economists and limit our discussion to
questions that are of an empirical nature. The core thesis of our paper
is that the current approach to the war on terror is ineffective.
Central to the current policy approach is the belief that negative
sanctions against actual and potential terrorists coupled with attempts
to spread liberal democracy through war, occupation and reconstruction
will improve the situation both abroad and domestically. (6) In short,
an empirical conjecture is being put forth by those supporting current
efforts--raise the cost to terrorists of engaging in terrorist
activities and the likelihood of another terrorist assault against the
U.S. will decrease. Given existing preferences, we argue that negative
sanctions are unsuccessful and in many cases counter productive in
reducing terrorism. Further, we postulate that efforts to impose liberal
democracy in weak and failed states via occupation and reconstruction
have largely failed.
In what follows we analyze current efforts to reduce terrorism
through an economic lens. In section 2 we exam why negative sanctions
have been largely ineffective in reducing terrorism. In section 3 we
turn to the logic of conflict and cooperation in the context of
occupation and reconstruction. Economic theory predicts that we should
observe cooperation where mutually beneficial gains exist. Of course in
reality we often observe the persistence of conflict in such situations.
We consider some of the factors that contribute to this disconnect
between theory and reality. Understanding these factors sheds light on
the inability of foreign governments to effectively impose liberal
democracies as desired. We conclude by postulating that liberal values
are critical to overcoming the threat of terrorism. It is our contention
that only be returning to a position of principled non-intervention can
the war on terror ultimately be won. This return to liberal principles
will have the dual effect of reducing terrorist attacks against the U.S.
and providing a mechanism for peacefully finding common ground between
differing belief systems and cultures.
REDUCING TERRORISM: WHY NEGATIVE SANTIONS ARE INEFFECTIVE
The central element of current terrorist policy is negative
sanctions or what Frey (2004) refers to as utilizing a "stick"
to combat terrorism. The logic behind negative deterrence, seen along
the lines of Becker's crime and punishment model (1968), is
twofold. First, the aim is to increase the probability of detecting
potential and actual terrorists. Second, negative sanctions focus on
increasing the penalty of being caught. Overall, the end goal is to
increase the "price" of engaging in terrorist acts. Negative
sanctions impose a cost on the terrorist, or potential terrorist, and
may include such things as fines, imprisonment or execution and usually
involve police and military force. Analyzing the market for terrorism
will add insight into whether negative sanctions have the desired
effects. In considering the market for terrorism, and subsequent
attempts to deter terrorist activity, we employ the standard assumptions
of economic analysis--rational calculation and purposive action.
The market for terrorism consists of suppliers who are those
individuals who are willing to carry out or supply terrorist acts and
demanders who demand that terrorist activities be carried out. (7)
Following Iannaccone (2003), we focus on the demand side of the market.
The logic here is straightforward. While there is an ample supply of
individuals willing to supply terrorist behavior, there is a limitation
on the demand side of the market. This limitation is due to the fact
that there are usually not many organizations that want to recruit
terrorists. As such, focusing on the demand side of the market is
critical to understanding how to reduce terrorism.
Figure 1 illustrates the demand for terrorists and the subsequent
impact of negative sanctions.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
The motivation behind negative sanctions is that an increase in the
price of engaging in terrorist acts ([P.sub.1] to [P.sub.2]) reduces the
quantity of terrorist acts demanded as illustrated by movements along
the demand curve ([Q.sub.1] to [Q.sub.2]). The quantity of terrorism can
be measured either by the number of terrorist acts or the magnitude of
those acts as measured by the death and injury of innocent civilians.
Given the above, it would seem that the current policy of negative
sanctions should be effective in raising the price and reducing the
quantity of terrorism demanded. However, as those who have analyzed the
war on drugs using the tools of economics have noted, it is critical to
consider the elasticity of the good being analyzed (see Becker, Murphy
and Grossman 2004). Considering the elasticity of demand for terrorism
is important in understanding the effects of efforts to detect and
punish. In other words, it is critical for policymakers to consider how
individuals will react to changes in the price of the illegal good.
When one considers the demand for terrorism, there is good reason
to believe that the demand curve is relatively inelastic. This is due to
the fact that most terrorists are willing to pay an extremely high price
to engage in terrorist activities. (8) These terrorists believe they are
"doing the right thing" regardless of the costs associated
with carrying out the related act. (9) At the extreme, fanatical
terrorists are willing to pay the ultimate price (i.e., their life) to
engage in terrorist activities. Osama bin Laden, for example, in a
statement from October 6, 2002 states that the defensive jihad must
continue because the U.S. has shown no signs of regret for its
"previous crimes" against Muslims and instead that the
"criminal gang at the White House" is continuing its attack on
the Islamic world and therefore:
I am telling you, and God is my witness, whether America escalates
or de-escalates the conflict, we will reply to it in kind, God
willing. God is my witness, the youth of Islam are preparing things
that will fill your hearts with fear. They will target key sectors
of your economy until you stop your injustice and aggression or
until the more short-lived of us die. (quoted in Scheuer 2005, pp.
17).
Bin Laden and other Islamic leaders of the defensive jihad are
motivated by their love of Allah, and their hatred of US military acts
and geo-politics policy that is damaging the Muslim world. For our
purposes this reflects a set of given preferences that are reflected in
a relatively inelastic demand curve for terrorist acts. (10)
This realization has implications for terrorist policy and the
"war on terror." Given the inelasticity of the demand curve
for terrorism, efforts to raise the price of engaging in terrorist acts
will have a disproportionately small impact. This is illustrated in
Figure 2 by the solid demand curve.
As Figure 2 illustrates, a relatively large increase in price
([P.sub.2]-[P.sub.1]) has a disproportionately small effect on the
change in the quantity demanded of terrorism ([Q.sub.1]-[Q.sub.2]). The
main implication is that raising the price of engaging in terrorism
through negative sanctions will be relatively ineffective in preventing
the most extreme forms of terrorism. Instead of policies that lead to a
movement along the demand curve, what is ultimately needed is a shift in
the entire demand curve inward as illustrated in Figure 2 from the solid
demand curve to the dashed demand curve. (11)
The underlying logic of this realization is straightforward. Even
if current antiterrorist policies effectively capture the current
generation of terrorists, such policies would fail to shift the
underlying preferences or demand of future generations of terrorists. As
long as more individuals demand terrorism in future periods, punishing
current demanders does not change the underlying preference driving that
demand. Only by shifting the underlying preferences of current and
future generations of potential terrorists will the end goal of the war
on terror actually be achieved. A few points will further illustrate the
ineffectiveness of policies that lead to movements along the solid
demand curve.
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
Consider that government attempts to protect against terrorist acts
cannot effectively protect all potential targets. For instance,
resources may be allocated to protecting federal buildings but those
resources cannot be simultaneously used to protect "soft"
targets such as malls and other public areas. Raising the price of one
type of terrorist act causes terrorists to substitute to a relatively
lower cost set of terrorist activities. It is does not cause them to
leave the terrorism business. In other words, the underlying preferences
and market conditions have not been changed. Examples of substitution
may include switching to targets that are too costly for the government
to protect, substituting the modes of carrying out attacks, or employing
a new type of terrorist laborer--a different sex, age, education, etc.
In short, terrorist organizations will act in an entrepreneurial manner,
constantly seeking out their opponent's weakness where they can
maximize the damage done given the constraints they face.
Further, raising the cost of terrorism may be counterproductive in
that negative deterrence may increase the level of public attention
attached to certain terrorist groups or activities. One of the main aims
of terrorist organizations is to maximize publicity (Frey 2004, pp.
122-3). Allocating resources to deterrence or detection may increase the
attention paid to terrorists and terrorist organizations. Ultimately
these policies may assist the terrorists in achieving their end goals of
attention and publicity. Consider for instance the attention given to
terrorists when a government announces military strikes or raids or the
increased security of a certain potential target.
Finally, the current emphasis on negative deterrence may actually
contribute to the strength of the general demand for terrorism. As Frey
(2004, pp. 33-6) indicates, deterrence policy creates a negative-sum
situation where neither the terrorists nor the combating powers wins.
Coercive action is met with coercive action and this spirals into a
continuous process of negative-sureness. (12) Both parties are made
worse off and neither may achieve their end goals. In such an instance,
the war on terror turns into a classic prisoner's dilemma
situation. Both parties would be better off if they could credibly
commit to cooperate but instead both end up defecting.
Given the ineffectiveness of negative sanctions for the reasons
discussed above, the focus of policy toward terrorism must drastically
change. Instead of focusing on policies that lead to movements along the
demand curve, focus must be placed on shifting the entire demand curve
inward as illustrated in Figure 2. The logic underlying this claim is
straightforward. Given an inelastic demand curve, raising the price of
terrorism does reduce the quantity demanded but only by a relatively
small amount. At the same time, negative sanctions fail to remove the
underlying demand or preference for terrorist acts.
Only by changing the fundamental market conditions and preferences
of those that participate in the market, characterized by a shift in the
demand curve inward, will the underlying demand for terrorist acts
actually change in future periods. Unless there is buy-in from the
individuals within the country where a demand for terrorism exists,
sustainable deterrence will not occur. While negative deterrence can
stop some terrorist acts, it is not a long-term solution to
delegitimizing the fundamental demand and acceptance of terrorism as a
means for resolving disagreement. It is precisely because current
policies are ineffective in changing the underlying preferences driving
the demand for terrorism that we must look elsewhere for strategies to
reduce terrorist activities. The question then turns to determining the
best means for shifting the entire demand curve and changing the
fundamental economic, social and political conditions where a demand for
terrorism exists.
ILLIBERAL MEANS TO LIBERAL ENDS?
In addition to engaging in negative deterrence of actual and
potential terrorist activities, the United States and other foreign
governments have attempted to reduce future terrorist acts by
"spreading democracy" to weak, failed and conflict-torn
states. (13) These efforts have traditionally involved military
occupation and reconstruction with the aim of establishing
self-sustaining liberal political, economic and social orders. President
Bush recently reiterated this position in his second term Inaugural
Address when he indicated that U.S. foreign policy will aim to "...
seek and support the growth of democratic movements and institutions in
every nation and culture, with the ultimate goal of ending tyranny in
our world." (14)
The logic behind these efforts is that those countries with
dysfunctional or absent states often provide a safe haven for terrorists
and terrorist organizations. If these countries can be transformed into
liberal democracies, terrorism will be severely reduced if not
eradicated. In the context of the demand for terrorism discussed in
Section 2, if liberal ideals can be spread to weak and failed states,
the fundamental conditions and preferences will change, shifting the
demand curve inward. In short, effective reconstruction efforts will
shift the demand curve for terrorism inward as illustrated in Figure 2.
Given the increasing relevance of reconstruction in the post 9/11
world, a fundamental question comes to the forefront. Can foreign
governments effectively establish liberal democratic institutions in
weak and failed states at will? (15) Based on the historical record, the
answer is a resounding no. Consider Table 1, which shows the U.S. led
reconstruction since the late 1800s.
Table 1 shows the countries where U.S. led reconstruction efforts
have been attempted as well as the years of occupation. Liberal
democracy is measured by the Polity IV index which measures the level of
democracy or autocracy in a country (Jaggers and Marshall 2003). (17) In
Table 1, a country with a Polity IV score greater than +3 ten years
after the end of occupation is considered to be a successful case of
reconstruction. (18)
Economics can offer insight into reconstruction efforts and their
ultimate success or failure. Thomas Schelling (1960) was one of the
first economists to apply economic insights to conflict and cooperation.
Schelling pointed out the difference between games of pure conflict
(negative or zero-sum games) and games of pure cooperation (positive-sum
games). This general framework can be applied to the situation of
occupation and reconstruction (see Cowen and Coyne 2005). In the context
of reconstruction, conflict includes such things as terrorism, looting
and general insurgency. In contrast, cooperation includes peaceful
interaction and exchange around liberal ends.
Economic theory predicts that conflict should not persist where
gains from exchange exist. Specifically, the Coase theorem indicates
that conflict should be unlikely as all parties peacefully bargain to
realize the mutual gains of interaction and exchange. Of course one
observes the persistence of conflict of various magnitudes in various
locations throughout the world. While the Coase theorem is an imperfect
model of the world, it serves as a useful foil to understand the various
factors that facilitate or constrain the predicted outcome of
cooperation. In other words, within the occupation and reconstruction
context, it is important to understand the factors that contribute to,
or prohibit, the transformation of situations of conflict into
cooperation. In what follows, we consider several factors which
influence the level of conflict or cooperation in weak or failed states.
(19) Our aim is not to gauge the magnitude of these factors, which will
vary depending on the context, but rather to understand how they may
constrain the achievement of the desired outcome of self-sustaining
mutually beneficial cooperation.
Transaction Costs and Property Rights
The standard response to the Coase theorem is that the presence of
high transaction costs and/or a lack of well-defined property rights
will constrain the achievement of the predicted outcome. Given this,
both factors must be considered in the context of occupation and
reconstruction. Transaction costs--in the form of various parties,
factions, etc. meeting and bargaining-may indeed be present but one
should not expect these costs to be overly prohibitive. The occupying
forces seek to play the role of mediator in which they bring the
relevant parties together to the bargaining table. The aim is to strike
a mutually beneficial agreement between the various parties involved.
The presence of well-defined and enforceable property rights may be
more of a problem. If party A cannot trust that party B will not cheat
them, an agreement may not be reached. Similar to the bargaining
situation, the occupying forces, in the role of mediator, often monitor
and enforce any agreement that is reached. However, occupying forces
have often failed to be effective in the role of enforcer. Oftentimes,
elites in reconstructed countries have reneged on the specifics of the
agreement reached under the guidance of foreign occupiers.
For example, Horacio Vasquez Lajara was elected president of the
Dominican Republic on the eve of U.S. exit in 1924. Vasquez ignored the
constitutionally dictated term limits established under U.S. guidance
and remained in office for six rather than the stipulated four years.
This initial disregard for the constitution led to a military led coup
resulting in autocratic rule for the next several decades.
In sum, the transaction costs associated with bargaining during
reconstructionare not likely to be a significant barrier. Enforcement is
more likely during the occupation while occupying forces have resources
dedicated to upholding any agreement reached. However, it is unclear
that foreign powers can effectively enforce agreements over the
long-term. This commitment problem may result in parties defecting from
agreements once occupiers exit causing the cooperative agreement to
unravel. (20)
Social Capital and the Art of Association
The notion of social capital has been receiving increasing
attention from social scientists. Social capital emphasizes the role of
social networks and connections. More specifically, social capital can
be defined as the existence of a certain set of informal values or norms
that are shared among members of a group. These shared norms and values
facilitate cooperation and coordination (Fukuyama 1999: 16; Putnam 2000,
pp. 18-20).
In the context of reconstruction, social capital around shared
norms by heterogeneous members of a society is critical for achieving a
shared liberal ethic around meta-level political, economic and social
institutions (Coyne 2005b). In short, the art of association that
characterizes a liberal order requires a certain type of social capital
that provides norms of trust, loose ties, respect for private property
and the rule of law.
A fractionalized country with many heterogeneous groups that are
not interconnected is less likely to share an ideology and ethic. In
other words, it is less likely that common knowledge around the ends of
the reconstruction will evolve (Coyne 2004). In contrast, a society
characterized by social capital fostering loose ties is more likely to
share a common ideology and ethic given that heterogeneous groups and
individuals are connected.
Examples of this last point would be "nigh trust"
societies such as Japan and Germany which are often considered to the
two most successful U.S.-led reconstruction efforts (Fukuyama 1996, pp.
149-255). While individuals and groups in these societies differ on many
margins, there is a shared ethic consisting of a minimal level of trust,
honesty and respect that pervades almost all daily activities. This
underlying ethic that arises when a society shares a certain set of
values, allows for the movement from personal to impersonal exchange.
The widespread sharing of values requires a certain connectedness among
individual members of the society. (21) Social capital encompasses the
norms and values to facilitate such interaction and cooperation.
Different societies will have varying endowments of social capital.
Given that social scientists and policymakers do not have a firm
understanding of how to create social capital anew, the existing
endowment in countries characterized by weak and failed states is an
exogenous constraint on reconstruction efforts. In many cases, the
endowment of social capital will constrain the achievement of
self-sustaining meta-institutions which are the very goal of
reconstruction efforts.
The Meta-game and Nested Games
Reconstruction efforts focus on resolving the meta-level game of
creating self-sustaining liberal institutions at the national level.
Oftentimes, these efforts overlook the fact that there are nested games
embedded within the general meta-game. (22) These nested games are often
the result of historical interactions and experiences which occurred
prior to reconstruction efforts. In many cases, these nested games
constrain the achievement of a solution to the general meta-game.
Indeed, the nested games may be so complicated that the meta-game cannot
be easily characterized let alone solved.
One example of how nested games can constrain the larger
reconstruction meta-game is the case of Somalia. Somalia has existed
with no central government since 1991. Further, no central government
has ever evolved endogenously although exogenous forces established a
government in 1960. Historically the clan, and not any notion of a
central state or nation, has been the most important source of identity
in Somalia. The result has been many small, overlapping and simultaneous
games between the various actors throughout Somalia both within and
across clans. Solutions have evolved to these mini-games which allows
for widespread cooperation but the nature of these games also constrain
the achievement of the larger reconstruction game.
Indeed, attempts by foreign governments to construct a central
government and solve the Somalia meta-game have exacerbated conflict.
These efforts lead to a large bargaining game between the many dispersed
parties throughout the country. In this context players want to
establish their reputation as a "power player" within the
political process. In turn, this situation leads to a struggle,
oftentimes violent, for control of power. The process of conflict
continues until the attempts to solve the meta-game end, after which
social relations can again be characterized by the many nested games
which existed prior to the attempt at reconstruction (see Coyne 2005a).
The desire of parties to establish a firm reputation in the
reconstruction bargaining game may intensify divisions and contribute to
the failure to solve the meta-game. The parties involved in the
reconstruction game realize that they will be involved in further
interactions with the other parties in future periods. As such, they may
seek to establish a "tough" reputation in the attempt to gain
an edge in future interactions. In such a case, it is precisely because
there will be future interactions and gains to be had that parties may
fail to strike an agreement (Cowen 2004, pp. 3-4). Both parties will
hold out for a greater share of the available surplus resulting in a
negative-sum situation where an agreement cannot be reached and neither
party benefits.
Expectations and Self-deception
While the specifics of each reconstruction situation will differ,
in each case there is some set of expectations where the meta-game is
one of coordination rather than conflict. If the expectations of the
citizens of the country being reconstructed country are aligned, at
least to some degree, with the aims of the reconstruction, there will
tend to be a greater degree of coordination.
As recent work in behavioral research illustrates, a critical
element of expectation management is how outcomes relate to
expectations. This realization can be applied to the situation of
reconstruction (Cowen and Coyne 2005, pp. 38-40). For instance, work by
Diener (1984) and Frank (1989, 1997) concludes that individuals value
their current state of affairs relative to their expectations.
Behavioral research in the area of wage rigidity adds further insight
into expectations in the context of conflict (Cowen 2004, pp. 5).
In this latter area of research, economists seek to answer why
involuntary employment exists. Employers and employees, following the
assumptions of economics, should negotiate lower wages. Both parties
would be better off as compared to a situation where the worker is laid
off. One explanation for the failure to negotiate such an agreement is
that employers fear that employees will engage in uncooperative behavior
because employees, under the renegotiated contract, will receive less
than they believe they should (see Bewley 1999). In the context of
reconstructions, this research indicates that a disjoint between
expectations and outcomes may lead to the persistence of conflict. When
individuals are forced to participate in an agreement that provides an
outcome which "pays" less than they expected, they may very
well refuse to act in a cooperative manner.
In some cases it will be preferable for individuals to have low
expectations and in others it will be better if individuals have higher
expectations. It may appear that it is always preferable for the
populace to have low expectations so that there can never be backlash
against occupiers. However this overlooks that a successful
reconstruction requires an investment on the behalf of the citizens of
the occupied country. For instance, in order for impersonal social and
economic interaction to take place, individuals must have an (high)
expectation that their property rights will be respected.
To generalize, low expectations are beneficial when the citizens in
the occupied country will tend to blame the occupying forces for the
every minor mistake. Things such as infrastructure beyond basic
necessities, welfare and other acts of "goodwill" fall into
this category. In other situations, it will be beneficial if the
populace has high expectations so that they will make the necessary
investment to participate and further the reconstruction process.
Occupying forces can seek to influence expectations to some extent
but they cannot completely control the expectations held by the citizens
of the occupied country. There is some range over which individuals have
pre-conceived expectations which cannot be significantly influenced. For
instance, individuals may lack "meta-rationality" meaning they
fail to have realistic expectations of one's abilities and the
prospects for achieving one's desired ends. Indeed, self-deception
can be seen as a contributing factor to political failure (Cowen,
forthcoming). In the context of reconstruction, each party may have
unrealistic expectations of what they can realistically achieve in the
larger reconstruction game. The achievement of a long-term sustainable
agreement may be constrained where each side possesses unrealistic and
disjointed expectations of what they deserve and can ultimately achieve.
The Knowledge Problem and Unintended Consequences
Austrians emphasize the role of local knowledge which cannot
possibly be possessed by those designing and carrying out government
interventions. Indeed, the dynamics of intervention indicate that one
intervention creates a new set of incentives for both political and
private actors. These incentives may create a set of circumstances that
prevent the achievement of the desired goal and require additional
interventions on the part of political agents. However, these subsequent
interventions again cause the underlying incentive structure to shift.
The process then continues in a similar manner (see Mises 1977 and
Rothbard 1977).
In the context of reconstruction, foreign governments can never
have full and complete information of how to effectively craft and
implement self-sustaining liberal: political, economic and social
orders. Policies that may appear to generate the desired outcome may
have undesired consequences in future periods. These unintended
consequences may in turn generate the need for further government
interventions which in turn create a new set of unintended consequences.
To illustrate this, consider the case of U.S. intervention in
Afghanistan in the late 1980s. The aim of the U.S. intervention was to
assist Afghanistan resistance forces in expelling the Soviet Union.
After achieving the desired goal, the U.S. removed itself from the
situation in Afghanistan. The result was various factions within
Afghanistan turning against one another. The ensuing civil war created
an environment in which the Taliban and al Qaeda assumed significant
positions of control ultimately resulting in further U.S. interventions
in 2001 (Eizenstat et al. 2004, pp. 139). Further, in some cases, the
weapons that the U.S. had provided to resistance forces to expel the
Soviet Union were used against U.S. troops during the recent war.
Current reconstruction efforts will likewise have unintended
consequences in future periods which may cause preclude cooperation over
the long-term.
Public Choice Issues
Most studies of reconstruction fail to consider the motivations of
the various actors that comprise the occupying forces. Indirectly, these
studies assume benevolence on the part of occupying forces. Occupiers
often state the ends of reconstruction efforts as the establishment of a
liberal democracy. The assumption of benevolence coupled with the stated
ends of reconstruction efforts leads one to conclude that occupiers take
the most effective steps known to achieve the stated ends.
Public choice theory, which demands symmetry of behavioral
assumptions applied to both private and public actors, leads to a very
different conclusion. Public choice theory dictates that if one assumes
that private economic actors act in a self-interested manner, the same
assumption must be applied to those in the political and public realm.
This has major implications in the context of reconstruction efforts.
There is a wide array of actors involved in the reconstruction
process. Politicians, bureaucrats in a wide range of government offices
and bureaus, military personnel and interest groups all have different
ends that they are pursuing in the wider reconstruction context. In many
cases, these individual interests may conflict with the end goal of
achieving a self-sustaining liberal order. For instance, politicians aim
to maximize votes, while bureaucrats aim to maximize their budget. As
such, one should expect politicians to tend to be more optimistic about
the status of reconstruction efforts while bureaucrats will tend to be
more pessimistic, demanding more resources to achieve the stated ends.
Further, there will often be conflict between the aims and goals of
different agencies within the same government. For instance, there is
tension between the missions and activities in the CIA and FBI in the
United States (see Scheuer 2005, pp. 185-192). Likewise, special
interest groups may seek to influence the allocation of resources and
aid in the occupied country. The various interests at play will also
influence the picking of political winners within the occupied country.
Recently, there have been several critical analyses of the current
efforts to reconstruct Iraq (see for instance Diamond 2005 and Phillips
2005). These authors discuss the tensions between the various parts the
U.S. government, military and intelligence agencies which have, in many
cases, limited the effectiveness of reconstruction efforts.
In sum, a complete analysis of occupation and reconstruction
requires a consideration of the motivations of actors in the public
realm. Actors in the public realm face a set of incentives that will
often lead them to act in a manner inconsistent with the stated ends of
reconstruction efforts. Indeed, there is no feedback mechanism in the
public sphere to ensure that the most efficient and effective steps will
be taken to achieve the stated ends. The pursuit of private interests by
public actors may contribute to the persistence of conflict. Put
differently, public actors may fail to take steps that would result in
cooperation if those activities fail to align with their private
interests.
Summation
Historically, reconstruction efforts have failed to consistently
establish self-sustaining liberal democracies. As Table I indicates,
excluding Afghanistan and Iraq, the United States, has had a success
rate of approximately 26% since 1898. Further, it is not just the case
that reconstruction efforts that fail leave the country in question just
as well off as prior to the attempted reconstruction. Such a view
suffers from a "nirvana fallacy" where it is assumed that
foreign government scan achieve a better outcome as compared to the
status quo in weak and failed states, and at worse will leave the
country no worse off. This assumption overlooks the possibility that
reconstruction efforts may, on net, cause more harm than good (Coyne
2005a). For instance, the overall level of cooperation has been higher
in Somalia when foreign governments are not present or involved in
attempts to establish a central government. Efforts to exogenously
establish a central government have increased conflict instead of
accomplishing the intended goal of increasing cooperation.
As outlined in the previously subsections, there are numerous
factors which may preclude the achievement of a cooperative solution
around liberal orders in those countries characterized by weak and
failed states. This is not to say that reconstruction efforts can never
successfully achieve the desired goals, but rather' to indicate
that foreign governments lack a clear understanding of how to achieve
such ends on a consistent basis. Given the inability of foreign
governments to effectively change the underlying preferences and
conditions as desired, it is far from clear that occupation and
reconstruction are effective means in achieving the stated ends of
eradicating terrorism.
CONCLUSION: WHAT ROLE FOR LIBERALISM?
Recently, Michael Novak (2005) has pointed out that there is a
"universal hunger for liberty." This hunger cuts across
national and cultural boundaries. While Novak's conclusion should
be a source of optimism, he fails to consider the most effective means
of satiating the universal hunger. Our analysis indicates that attempts
to protect and spread liberty through negative sanctions against
terrorists and attempts to impose liberty via occupation and
reconstruction are largely ineffective. How then is the universal hunger
for liberty to be satisfied? Or stated differently, how are we to close
the gap between "the West and the Rest?" (23) Whatever the
answer, our analysis indicated that steps must be taken to shift the
entire demand curve for terrorism inwards. It is our contention that the
key to achieving this end lies in a return to fundamental liberal
principles of non-intervention and a commitment to free trade. Only be
returning to these principles can the underlying preferences, and hence
the demand curve for terrorist acts, shift as illustrated in Figure 2.
These liberal principles have a long history in the United States.
(24) As George Washington emphasized in his farewell address in 1796:
The great rule of conduct for us in regard to foreign nations is,
in extending our commercial relations to have with them as little
political connection as possible. So far as we have already formed
engagements let them be fulfilled with perfect good faith. Here let
us stop...It is our true policy to steer clear of permanent
alliances with any portion of the foreign world ... (25)
On July 4,1821, Secretary of State John Quincy Adams made clear his
view of America's role in the international arena in a speech to
the House of Representatives:
America does not go abroad in search of monsters to destroy. She is
the well-wisher of freedom and independence of all. She is the
champion and vindicator only of her own ... She well knows that by
once enlisting under banners other than her own, were they even the
banners of foreign independence, she would involve herself beyond
the power of extrication, in all the wars of interest and intrigue,
of individual avarice, envy, ambition, which assumed the colors and
usurped the standards of freedom. The fundamental maxims of her
policy would insensibly change from liberty to force (quoted in
Scheurer 2005, pp. 200).
The logic behind pursuing principled non-intervention with a
commitment to free trade is grounded in basic economic reasoning.
Specifically, the gains from exchange model indicates that individuals
who engage in exchange expect, ex ante, to be made better off due to the
interaction. The gains from exchange manifest themselves in a number of
ways. Economic gains, in the form of prosperity and standards of living,
are one clear manifestation of trade. William Cline estimates that
worldwide free trade could help 500 million people escape poverty while
simultaneously injecting $200 billion annually into developing nations
(2004). Perhaps more importantly, trading partners are less likely to
engage in conflict because the aggressor incurs part of the cost of
their actions in the form of foregone future exchanges.
Free trade also provides potential benefits beyond economic gains.
As Cowen (2002) indicates, trade in cultural products increases the menu
of cultural choices available. Cultural exchange causes cultures to
become more homogeneous on some margins but simultaneously increase
heterogeneity on other margins. As such, the possibility of exchange
provides the ability of the exchange of cultural practices and ideas.
Free trade can be seen as a means of finding a common ground between
cultures and the potential for enemies to be transformed into trading
partners. Along similar lines, free exchange allows for the imitation of
both formal and informal institutions across national borders. As such,
it is a means of generating social change through peaceful interaction.
A commitment to non-intervention as outlined by Washington and Adams
will reduce the U.S.'s exposure to terrorist attacks in other
countries. It will also allow different cultures to find areas of
commonality serving as a foundation for coexistence.
A common objection to this course of action is that Islam is
fundamentally opposed to Western culture and values. However a detailed
analysis of terrorism indicates this is not the case. As Pape indicates,
"The United States has been exporting cultural values that are
anathema to Islamic fundamentalism for several decades, but bin Laden
and the al-Qaeda organization did not turn toward attacking the United
States until after 1990, when the United States sent troops to Saudi
Arabia, Qatar, and Bahrain" (2005, p. 52). Indeed, Pape's
analysis of suicide terrorism concludes that past and current suicide
campaigns are not driven by Islamic fundamentalism, but instead are
driven by foreign occupation of the terrorist's homeland.
In sum, a commitment to the liberal principles of free trade and
non-intervention will have two key benefits. First, if Pape's
analysis is accurate, the number of terrorist attacks against the United
States should decrease with the end of occupation. Second, free trade
offers a means of finding a common ground between cultures. Instead of
inducing reform at the point of a gun, free trade provides a means of
peaceful evolution.
Of course free trade in goods, services, culture, ideas and
institutions depends on the existence of some core values such as
tolerance and respect for property (see Coyne 2005b). We must recognize
that some countries may not possess these prerequisites. (26) However,
as past reconstruction efforts demonstrate, these preconditions cannot
be imposed at will. Institutions that are imposed on societies where the
fundamental conditions and preferences are not in place to serve as
foundation will fail to "stick" and operate as desired. In
short, attempting to export liberal democracy at gunpoint severs the
voluntary nature of exchange. As such, the coerced parties are less
likely to voluntarily accept the "good" being exported once
the gun is removed.
It is not simply a matter of the desired liberal institutions
failing to stick. Additionally, efforts to export liberal democracy via
occupation can be counter productive. As Huntington points out,
"Western efforts to propagate such ideas [liberal democratic values
and ideas] produce instead a reaction against 'human rights
imperialism' and a reaffirmation of indigenous values ..."
(1993, pp. 41). It is critical to realize that in many cases
establishing a liberal political, economic and social order via
occupation is simply not an option. Given that imposing the necessary
values and preferences is often not in the feasibility set, the best
that can be done is to offer the possibility of free trade of goods,
services and ideas.
With increases in technology available at decreasing costs, there
is reason for optimism. With the advent of new technologies such as the
Internet, cell phones and other telecommunications technologies, the
world is interconnected and integrated as never before. This should
allow for the continual exchange across the several margins discussed
above. On the flipside, these same technologies allow small groups of
individuals to engage in acts that pose potential threats of massive
proportions. The tension between these two possibilities poses what is
perhaps the greatest challenge in the world today.
Given this challenge, we have attempted to show that while a
position of principled non-intervention coupled with a commitment to
free trade is not a panacea, it is the most effective means available to
generate sustainable social and political change along liberal lines. We
are not arguing that governments shouldn't protect their citizens
against immediate terrorist threats. Instead, it is our contention that
while current anti-terrorist efforts may be effective in rooting out
existing terrorists, they are largely ineffective in changing the
underlying preferences that will drive terrorism in future generations.
REFERENCES
Becker, G.S. (1968), "Crime and Punishment: An Economic
Approach", Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 76, No.2, 169-217.
Becker, G.S., M. Grossman and K.M. Murphy (2004), "The
Economic Theory of Illegal Goods: The Case of Drugs", NBER Working
Paper No. W10976.
Bewley T.F. (1999), Whys Wages Do Not Fall During a Recession.
Cambridge, Harvard University Press, Massachusetts.
Boettke, P.J. (2001), "Credibility, commitment, and Soviet
economic reform", In, P.J. Boettke (Ed.), Calculation and
Coordination, pp. 154-175. Routledge: New York.
Boulding K.E. (1962), Conflict and Defense, Harper & Row: New
York.
Cline, W. (2004), Trade Policy and Global Poverty, Institute for
International Economics: Washington, D.C.
Cowen, T. (2002), Creative Destruction, Princeton University Press:
New Jersey.
--(2004), "A road map to the Middle East peace?-A Public
Choice perspective", Public Choice Vol. 118, 1-10.
--.(Forthcoming), "Self-Deception as the Root of Political
Failure", Public Choice.
Cowen, T. and C.J. Coyne (2005), "Postwar Reconstruction: Some
Insights from Public Choice and Institutional Economics",
Constitutional Political Economy, Vol. 16, 31-48.
Coyne, C.J. (2004), "Culture, Common Knowledge and
Post-Conflict Reconstruction", Working Paper.
--.(2005a), "Reconstructing Weak and Failed States: Foreign
Intervention and the Nirvana Fallacy", Working Paper.
--(2005b), "The Institutional Prerequisites for Post-Conflict
Reconstruction", The Review of Austrian Economics, forthcoming.
Diamond, L.J. (2005), Squandered Victory: The American Occupation
and the Bungled Effort to Bring Democracy to Iraq, Times Books: New
York.
Diener, E. (1984), "Subjective Well-Being", Psychological
Bulletin, Vol. 95,542-75.
Eizenstat, S.E., J. Edwards Porter and J.M. Weinstein (2005),
"Rebuilding Weak States", Foreign Affairs, January/February,
134-146.
Frank, R.H. (1997), "The Frame of Reference as a Public
Good", The Economic Journal, Vol. 107, 1832-1847.
--(1989), "Frames of Reference and the Quality of Life",
American Economic Review, Vol. 79, 80-85.
Frey, B.S. (2004), Dealing with Terrorism-Stick or Carrot? Edward
Elgar Publishing, Ltd.: United Kingdom.
Fukuyama, F. (1996), Trust. Bowling Alone, Simon & Schuster:
New York.
--(1999), The Great Disruption, Basic Books: New York.
Gause, G. (2005), "Can Democracy Stop Terrorism?",
Foreign Affairs, Vol. 84, No. 5, 62-76.
Huntington, S. P. (1993), "The Clash of Civilizations?",
Foreign Affairs, Vol. 72, No. 3, 22-49.
Iannaccone, L.I. (2003), "The Market for Matyrs," Global
Prosperity Initiative Working Paper 35, Mercatus Center, Arlington, VA.
Irwin, D.A. (1996), Against the Tide: An Intellectual History of
Free Trade, Princeton University Press: New Jersey.
Jaggers, K. and M.G. Marshall (2003), "Polity IV Project"
Center for International Development and Conflict Management, University
of Maryland. Website: http://www.cidcm.umd.edu/inscr/polity/
Mahbubani, K. (1992), "The West and the Rest", The
National Interest, Summer, 3-13.
Mises, L. von. [1929] (1977), A Critique of Interventionism:
Inquiries into Economic Policy and the Economic Ideology of the Present,
translated by H.F. Sennholz, Arlington House: New York.
--[1952] (1990), "The Plight of Underdeveloped Nations",
In R. Ebeling, (Ed.), Money, Method and Market Process: Essays by Ludwig
yon Mises, Kluwer Academic Publishers: Boston.
Novak, M. (2005), The Universal Hunger for Liberty: Why the Clash
of Civilizations is Not Inevitable. Basic Books: New York.
Ostrom, E., C. Gibson, S. Shivakumar and K. Andersson (2002), Aid,
Incentives and Sustainability. An Analysis of Development Co-operation.
Swedish International Development Co-operation Agency (SIDA): Stockholm.
Pape, R.A. (2005), Dying to Win: The Strategic Logic of Suicide
Terrorism. Random House: New York.
Parry, A. (1976), Terrorism: From Robespierre to Arafat. Vanguard
Press: New York.
Pei, M. (2003), "Lessons from the Past", Foreign Policy,
Vol. 137, 52-55.
Pei M. and S. Kasper (2003), "Lessons from the Past: The
American Record on Nation Building", Carnegie Endowment for
International Peace, Policy Brief 24.
Phillips, D.L. (2005), Losing Iraq: Inside the Postwar
Reconstruction Fiasco, Basic Books: Colorado.
Putnam, R. (2000), Bowling Alone. Simon & Schuster: New York.
Rothbard, M.N. (1977), Power and Market: Government & the
Economy. Sheed Andrews & McMeel: Kansas City.
Schelling, T.C. (1960), The Strategy of Conflict, Oxford University
Press: New York.
--(1984), Choice and Consequence: Perspectives of an Errant
Economist, Harvard University Press: Massachusetts.
Scheuer, M. (2005), Imperial Hubris: Why the West is Losing the War
on Terror. Potomac Books, Inc.: Washington: D.C.
Shughart, W. (Forthcoming), "An analytical history of
terrorism, 1945-2000", Public Choice.
Sinclair, A. (2003), An Anatomy of Terror: A History of Terrorism,
Macmillan: London.
Tsebelis, G. (1990), Nested Games: Rational Choice in Comparative
Politics, University of California Press: Berkeley.
Wieviorka, M. (1993), The Making of Terrorism. The University of
Chicago Press: Chicago.
Zakaria, F. (2003), The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at
Home and Abroad. W.W. Norton & Company: New York.
PETER J. BOETTKE
Department of Economics, George Mason University
CHRISTOPHER J. COYNE
Department of Economics, Hampden-Sydney College
NOTES
We would like to thank John Cochran, Claire Morgan and Alex Padilla for useful comments and suggestions. An earlier version of this paper
was presented by Peter Boettke at Cambridge University to the Faculty of
Social and Political Sciences when he was the 2004 Hayek Visiting Fellow
at the London School of Economics and by Christopher Coyne at the annual
Southern Economic Association meetings, Washington, D.C., November 18,
2005. Financial assistance from the Earhart Foundation and Mercatus
Center is acknowledged. The usual caveat applies.
(1.) On the history of terrorism, see Parry 1976, Sinclair 2003,
Shughart forthcoming and Wieviorka 1993.
(2.) Major terrorist attacks since 9/11 have taken place in Bali
(2002), Madrid (2004), Beslan (2004) and London (2005).
(3.) Source of homeland security spending:
http://www.heritage.org/Research/NationalSecurity/ bg1731.cfm
(4.) For an estimate of the costs of war that is based on
Congressional appropriations see, http:// www.costofwar.com/
(5.) We take the end goal of the war on terror to be an end to
anti-American terrorist acts that aim to kill innocent American
citizens. We do not address the loss of life in foreign countries that
are a direct result of US military intervention.
(6.) Throughout the analysis we are careful to use the term
"liberal democracy." As Fareed Zakaria (2003) has emphasized,
"democracy" is often confused with "liberal" or
"constitutional democracy." Democracy deals with the method of
selecting government officials while constitutional democracy deals with
the goals of government--the protection of individual rights, the rule
of law, etc. In the absence of constitutional liberalism, democracy will
not necessarily yield the desirable results. The election of Hitler in
Germany or the elections in Iran, considered by most to be a corrupt
sham, provide but two illustrations of the point that democracy in
itself is not enough to obtain the desired outcome of liberalism.
(7.) The market for terrorism is unique in that in many cases the
demanders and suppliers are the same individuals. For instance, Osama
bin Laden is both demander and supplier of terrorism in the same way
that an executive at Wal-Mart both is the supplier of goods and the
demander of those goods to the extent that they shop at Wal-Mart.
(8.) As Michael Scheuer (2005) has argued, from the point of view
of Islamic terrorists they are fighting a defensive jihad. It is not
western secular culture that incites bin Laden, but U.S. acts that
challenge God's word, attack Muslims, and occupy Muslim lands. The
importance of Scheuer's work is that it focuses our attention on
the beliefs and preferences of those we are attempting to defeat in a
military campaign.
(9.) For a comprehensive analysis of the logic of suicide
terrorism, see Pape (2005).
(10.) Consider, for example, the recent video statement by London
suicide bomber Mohammed Sadiq which played on Al-Jazeer where he states:
"Our words are dead until we give them life with our blood"
... "I, and thousands like me, have forsaken everything for what we
believe. Our driving motivation doesn't come from tangible
commodities that this world has to offer" ... "Your
democratically elected governments continuously perpetuate atrocities
against my people all over the world, and your support of them makes you
directly responsible, just as I am directly responsible for protecting
and avenging my Muslim brothers and sisters. Until we feel security, you
will be our targets, and until you stop the bombing, gassing,
imprisonment, and torture of my people, we will not stop this
fight." Source: http://www.memritv.org/Transcript.asp?P1=835
(11.) In short, the more effective policy from the point of view of
attaining the stated US goals must move from the eradication of the
terrorist threat in a crime and punishment framework to one of winning
the hearts and minds of generations of Muslims.
(12.) For more on the negative-sum nature of conflict see Boulding
(1962) and Schelling (1960, 1984, pp. 269).
(13.) Eizenstat et al. discuss the characteristics of weak and
failed states. The weakness of states can be measured along three
margins performed by the governments of strong states: security, the
provision of basic services, and the protection of essential civil
freedoms. Failed states do not provide any of these functions while weak
states are deficient along one or two of these margins (2005, pp. 136).
(14.) Inaugural Address available at:
http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2005/01/20050120.1.html
(15.) As Gause (2005) discusses, simply establishing democracy in
the Arab world will not reduce terrorism and will most likely generate
outcomes that are not favorable to the U.S.
(16.) Source: Pei (2003).
(17.) The Polity IV Index ranks the political institutions of a
country on an additive eleven point scale (0-10). The authors compute a
combined "polity score," by subtracting the Autocracy score
from the Democracy score. The resulting scale ranges from +10 (strongly
democratic) to -10 (strongly autocratic). Institutionalized democracy,
as defined by the authors, consists of three key elements: (1) the
presence of institutions and procedures through which citizens can
express their preferences, (2) the presence of institutionalized
constraints on the executive, and (3) the guarantee of civil liberties
for all citizens in both their daily lives and political participation
(Polity IV Project, Dataset Users Manual, pp. 13). The authors define
autocracy "in terms of the presence of a distinctive set of
political characteristics." Specifically, autocracies
"suppress competitive political participation. Their chief
executives are chosen in a regularized process of selection within the
political elite, and once in office they exercise power with few
institutional constraints." Following Pei and Kasper (2003), we
take a score greater than +3 (Iran's current score) ten years after
exit to be a successful case of democracy.
(18.) The range of Polity IV index seeks to register the strength
of democracy or autocracy. To put a score of +3 in context, Iran
currently scores a +3. As such, we are holding the success or failure of
past reconstruction efforts to an extremely charitable standard. By
employing these benchmarks we are asking, "Did U.S.-led
reconstruction efforts generate a political order that is equivalent to
present day Iran?"
(19.) The identification and analysis of these factors draws on
previous work by Cowen (2004), Cowen and Coyne (2005) and Coyne (2004,
2005, 2006).
(20.) For a discussion of the commitment problems faced by
reformers in the Soviet Union, see Boettke (2001). A similar argument
can be made in the context of reconstruction.
(21.) It is important to note that the existence of social capital
that fosters bridging ties does not guarantee a successful
reconstruction. This is due to the existence of the "dark
side" of social capital that include shared norms around perverse
ends which run counter to general progress. In other words, social
capital can be seen as a necessary, but not sufficient, condition for
post-conflict reconstruction. It is necessary because interconnectedness
is needed to share the required ethic across a society. However, it is
not sufficient because it is possible for social capital to exist around
perverse ends that oppose reconstruction efforts.
(22.) For the importance of considering the entire network of games
that individuals are involved in to fully understand their behavior, see
Ostrom et al. (2002) and Tsebelis (1990).
(23.) This phrase is borrowed from Mahbubani (1992).
(24.) For an intellectual history of free trade see Irwin (1996).
(25.) Source of quote: http://www.libertyl.org/farewell.htm
(26.) As Ludwig von Mises pointed out: "The problem of
rendering the underdeveloped nations more prosperous cannot be solved by
material aid. It is a spiritual and intellectual problem. Prosperity is
not simply a matter of capital investment. It is an ideological issue.
What the underdeveloped countries need first is the ideology of economic
freedom and free enterprise and initiative that makes for the
accumulation and maintenance of capital as well as for the employment of
the available capital for the best possible and cheapest satisfaction of
the most urgent wants to the consumers. In no other way can the United
States contribute to the improvement of the economic conditions of the
underdeveloped countries than by transmitting to them the ideas of
economic freedom" (Mises 1952, pp. 173).
Table 1
U.S. Reconstruction Efforts, 1898-Present (16)
Democracy after
Country Years 10 Years
Iraq 2003-present N/A
Afghanistan 2001-present N/A
Haiti 1994-1996 No
Panama 1989 Yes
Grenada 1983 Yes
Cambodia 1970-1973 No
South Vietnam 1964-1973 No
Dominican Republic 1965-1966 No
Japan 1945-1952 Yes
West Germany 1945-1952 Yes
Dominican Republic 1916-1924 No
Cuba 1917-1922 No
Haiti 1915-1934 No
Nicaragua 1909-1933 No
Cuba 1906-1909 No
Panama 1903-1936 No
Cuba 1898-1902 No