Rethinking the care-market relationship in care provider organisations.
King, Debra
The market organisation of care services
Care provider organisations are central to the effective delivery
of home and community care services for the frail aged and people with a
disability. Their significance, however, is often overlooked or
underestimated in research into home care which tends to focus either on
the care giver and care recipient, or on particular care programs. Yet,
among a myriad of other things, organisations are employers of care
workers, they respond to care needs, they allocate care services and
they negotiate care with unpaid carers.
Consequently, this research brings organisations back into the
frame. It does so by questioning whether organisations can (or do)
actually support the provision of 'good care': care that
incorporates the relational, emotional and physical needs of both care
givers and care recipients. (In this paper, the term caregiver refers to
all people involved in providing care for someone; care worker refers to
those caregivers who have a formal, paid relationship with an
organisation which is responsible for providing care services; and carer refers to the mainly unpaid caregivers who provide care
informally--though they may receive a carers allowance--that is with no
responsibilities or obligations to a care providing service). I
demonstrate that even if organisations would prefer to provide such a
notion of care through their services, their dependence upon government
funding and their accountability in relation to regulatory frameworks
makes this difficult. In effect, organisations are caught up in a
restrictive, managerial-market approach to care provision. This paper
identifies three tensions in the market approach which suggest that the
current direction is unsustainable as well as ineffective at meeting the
needs of care recipients, care workers and carer partners. Furthermore,
I argue that there are alternatives to the instrumental rationality of
market-managerialist logic. What is needed is an approach that can hold
together both the rational and emotional elements of care provision. One
such alternative is for organisations to utilise the norms and
principles of 'bounded emotionality.' A shift in this
direction could well open up possibilities for organisations to explore
how they might provide a more holistic approach to care, one focused on
broad notions of well-being.
Within Australia the types of organisations engaged in the
provision of home-based personal care services include government
organisations such as Domiciliary Care and Local Governments,
not-for-profit organisations, private-for-profit organisations and quasi government organisations. All organisations are required to tender for
authorization to provide particular services and attract state funding
for programs like Home and Community Care (HACC) and the Aged Care
Assessment Program. This arrangement means that organisations are
contracted by, and accountable to, the State and Federal governments
(depending on their type of funding) for the amount, type, quality and
cost of their care services. In order to secure funding it is necessary
to anticipate and meet government priorities which are set annually. For
example, within the HACC program one 2005 priority stipulates that value
is placed on organisations 'with a good track record in or
strategies in place to ensure:
* continuous quality improvement practices
* regular review of their services for appropriateness
* compliance with the HACC Minimum Data Set
* financial accountability
* financial viability
* agencies which provide good value for money' (2005a: 27)
The principle of competition between organisations is integral to
the tendering process. It encourages them to become more focused on (or
some might say distracted by) the efficient management of financial and
human resources in order to meet huge demands on care services.
This emphasis on financial management and market principles has
occurred throughout the OECD countries as part of the process of the
dismantling of the welfare state. Knijn (2000), in an analysis of care
provision in the Netherlands, constructs a typology which compares four
logics of care: professional, market, bureaucratic and family. She uses
this typology to demonstrate that although other logics or imperatives
around care provision exist, they have largely been subsumed by market
logic. Each of these logics has a different construction of care
recipients and care-givers and different ways of approaching issues
regarding quality of care and care work (see table I for an overview).
Knijn suggests that the welfare state approach, which balanced
bureaucratic, familial and professional logics, and was relatively
successful in organising care work, has been all but dismantled since
the 1980s. Since this time, care work has become increasingly organised
around market logic. Knijn observes that the effect of this shift is
that efficiency and managerialism have redefined the character of, and
the conditions under which, home care is provided. This process has
resulted in increasing levels of casualization, deprofessionalization,
work pressure and dissatisfaction, and, as a result, 'high rates of
burn-out and job diseases' (2000: 246).
Knijn's analysis of the changes in logic could be applied to
Australia, where care provider organisations operate within the
government's regulatory framework with its emphasis on contractual
relations, performance management systems, and economic rationalism.
Research by Stack and Provis (2000) has provided critical insight into
the impact of New Public Management principles on the delivery of aged
care services in Australia. They 'identified cost-cutting
techniques, contracting out of services, introduction of fees for
service, the establishment of business units and entrepreneurial
management practices for efficient service delivery' as the norm in
approaches to care provision. Stack and Provis argue that such an
approach has a detrimental impact on care work and care workers, as well
as impacting on broader aspects of quality care.
Within care provider organisations, then, managerialism can be seen
as acceding to Knijn's market logic, with the professional logic
having a presence in the language of home care but not necessarily in
its delivery. For example, care recipients are now called
'clients' even though in practice they are treated as
consumers. Within the market logic, a number of factors place boundaries
around the extent to which an organisation's culture can be
organised around anything other than the pragmatic allocation of
care-related tasks. Such factors include: the flexibility of staff
rosters, occupational health and safety considerations, risk management,
the optimal use of financial resources, systems of accountability, and
the emphasis on 'quality'. In essence, organisations are
somehow required to remain competitive, meet regulatory demands, and
meet care receiver (client) needs. As a result, they have become overly
focussed on a pragmatic instrumental approach to care, one that is
mainly concerned with the physical and health needs of care recipients.
An alternative approach would see care linked to overall well-being:
meeting not just the physical health needs of care recipients but also
their coexisting social and relational needs.
Tensions in the market approach to care
There are three areas of tension in this instrumental, market
approach to care that are likely to make it unsustainable in the long
term. These tensions relate to three key stakeholders of care provider
organisations: care recipients, care workers and carers. Although all
three groups have particular needs that challenge the capacity of
organisations to limit care provision to the market mode, the newly
defined powers of carers--reinforced by legislation and a Carers'
Charter--are likely to present particular challenges.
The first tension relates to the ever-growing movement in consumer
rights that places the needs of care recipients at the centre of care
provision. Over the next few years, baby boomers will enter into the
care recipient group in larger numbers (see Hugo, this edition). Having
lived in an era of increased consumer rights and individualism, this
group is likely to be more assertive in demanding that services be
provided at a level and in a way that maximises their sense of
well-being and quality of life. These are most likely to be maximised
when care need assessments take into account care recipients'
emotional and social needs, as well as their (more narrowly defined)
health and medical requirements.
This is not to suggest that all care recipients require high levels
of emotional and social support. As research on the Disability
People's Movement in the UK suggests, recipients have different
requirements ranging from those seeking healthcare and technological
assistance only, to those warranting high levels of all types of care
(Hopkins et al 2005). Incorporating a relational notion of care into
care provision, however, would take individual needs and attitudes
toward 'care' into account. Relational care is distinct from
paternalism and familial care and does not involve the self-sacrifice
and sympathy that these forms of care often perpetuate. In contrast,
relational care is about constructing a connection between care provider
and care recipient that is respectful and reciprocal, where each person
is sensitive to the other's needs and expectations and is capable
of reflexively respond to an 'other' (Nussbaum 2001; Miehls
and Moffatt 2000). While this form of care is underpinned by the social
relations of those involved, it also requires particular skills and
knowledge (see discussion in next sections) if care is to be
appropriately provided and mutually satisfying.
However, some care recipients do need high levels of social and
emotional support, particularly if they are without access to familial
and/or community care. The combination of high levels of mobility in the
Australian labour market and low levels of residential mobility amongst
the aged is likely to produce high numbers of aged care recipients whose
needs are not reliably met by familial or other forms of community care.
So while it is clear that the numbers of care recipients are going to
increase, it is also likely that this particular cohort will generate
new pressures on care provider organisations and care-givers to be
responsive and flexible in their delivery of a range of care needs,
including the need for social and emotional support.
A second tension is in the ongoing issue of the recruitment and
retention of care workers (HACC 2005b, 2003) in an environment where
demand outstrips supply. In order to attract (good) care workers,
organisations will need to be more cognizant of what it might take to be
an employer of choice. This will require knowing more about care workers
(particularly home care workers) and the meanings they ascribe to their
work. From existing literature it is evident that many of the rewards in
care work derive from the practical autonomy that working relatively
unsupervised and in someone's home allows; the ability to develop
and maintain relationships with clients at whatever level this may
occur; and the capacity to see the work as worthwhile: as contributing
to the wellbeing and quality of life of another person (Stacey 2005;
Ryan et al 2004; Piercy 2000; Stone 2000; Cancian 2000). However, when
activities such as showering clients, changing their dressings, or
providing respite for carers are routinized and managed to maximise
outputs (for example, the number of clients) rather than the quality of
interaction, these relational and emotional aspects of care that care
workers value risk being sidelined. Indeed, as Meagher (2006: 48-9)
argues, 'organisational factors are more likely than anything else
to make it difficult for providers and recipients of paid care to
establish successful relationships.'
Developing organisational rules that separate out and prohibit
these aspects of care is not particularly helpful for retaining care
workers. Despite this, organisations continue to be drawn toward
recruiting people who are likely to provide relational care,
irrespective of whether they will/can provide organisational support for
it. In effect, the relational aspects of care work are individualised,
while the pragmatic physical aspects accrue organisational support. As a
result, care workers often feel obliged to go above and beyond the
boundaries of their position description, either to please their clients
or to maintain their jobs. This is demonstrated in research by Stone who
found that there is considerable stress associated with balancing guilt
about not caring in a manner perceived as adequate, with fear of being
caught caring by the organisation (2000: 111). In other research, Stacey
reports on several instances of care workers who 'stay a little
longer, lend a little money or take on a little more' arguing that
the relational aspects of caring can mask the 'inequality and
exploitation of the carework arrangement' (2005: 839; see also
Stone 2000). What much of this research demonstrates, however, is that
exploitation leading to burn-out and withdrawal is less likely where
there is organisational support for the relational aspects of care work
(Cancian 2000; Kangas, Kee and McKee-Waddle 1999; Kahn 1993; Scott et
al. 1995). As a range of sources stress, the capacity for care workers
to endure the challenges of care work, and to sustain effective caring
relations can be greatly enhanced by organisational frameworks that
adequately support their workers, both logistically and psychologically
(Scott et al. 1995; Kahn 1993).
So far I have argued that organisations that accede to market
logic, with its emphasis on rationality and restrictions on the range of
care, are likely to be in conflict with two of its key stakeholders
groups: care recipients and care workers. The third tension relates to
the requirement for organisations to recognise unpaid carers as partners
in the care-giving process and as people who need to be supported in
their provision of care. This is a relatively new responsibility for
organisations and will have an impact on their approach to care
provision, not least because more attention will need to be given to
supporting familial care. While many carers remain invisible in the
formal system, providing care to family members without recognition or
assistance from care-provider organisations, those who do come into
contact with the formal system are often considered primarily as a
resource. Organisations tend to view these carers as the first option
for the provision of care to family members, and pressure is often
placed on them to maximise their level of caring. Dissenting from this
view, the Carers' Association (2003) argues that 'in this
model ... carers' rights and needs are not heeded.' The
problems with this model are illustrated in the story of Denise McEvoy,
a carer on the public record about her caring experiences.
Denise spent 5 years caring for her father Clarrie who had high
dependency status due to advanced Parkinson's Disease and
Alzheimers'. Her story is on public record in conference papers,
media interviews and documentation from the Carers' Association,
and this has been augmented by a personal interview with me in February
2006. At the time she wrote her story in 2004, Clarrie was still in the
family home because:
... public hospitals will not take what they term 'social
admissions' [to provide carers with respite], and nursing homes do
not have the staff numbers to monitor him constantly 24 hours a
day. This leaves me between a rock and a hard place; because I now
have to be 'on duty' 24 hours a day, 7 days a week, whereas
professional nursing staff normally work an 8-hour shift (McEvoy
2004).
While Denise was viewed as the main care provider, she was provided
with 'assistance' from care provider organisations, but only
after a battle and a great deal of begging--in her words, 'service
providers generally don't offer anything.' What assistance she
was offered did not take her needs in relation to Clarrie into
consideration. For example, she claimed that while twice a week, 2 care
workers shower Clarrie, '... they are permitted to spend only 1
hour with him. One hour is often not long enough, so I have to complete
their tasks' (McEvoy 2004). In addition, lack of consistency in
provision of care workers, meant that each time they came Denise would
have to tell them how to shower Clarrie so that he did not become rigid
or begin to aspirate--and this would take nearly 20 minutes out of the
allocated hour. One care worker provided by an agency was seen as
'particularly rude', wanting Denise to prepare Clarrie for a
shower (usually a two person job), so they could get on with the
washing, and even then:
... she was treating him really badly. She needed a lesson in
understanding the way Parkinson's works and how people can freeze,
their muscles just sort of go rigid, and you can't move him, can't
lift an arm or a leg. And she was just yelling at him. It was just
awful, absolutely awful (interview).
It was then left to Denise to calm Clarrie down, suction him to
alleviate the aspiration and finish the showering. Ironically, the way
in which paid care was provided in such situations, both by the
organisation and by the individual care worker, ultimately had a
detrimental, rather than beneficial, impact on Denise's workload.
Denise's story is testament to the myriad of issues that
carers can face in providing long-term high levels of care for family
members. The system of paid care provision was not flexible enough to
give Denise assistance to do everyday things such as the shopping; not
extensive enough to provide her with real respite even when she was sick
herself; not responsive enough to her physical and emotional needs even
when looking after Clarrie caused her sleep deprivation, a fractured
lumbar spine, and chronic back, neck and shoulder pain; and not caring
enough to supply staff who could actually provide the level of care (in
terms of health care and relational care) that Clarrie required (McEvoy
2004). The lack of organisational support for Denise placed stress on
her relationship with her father, made her increasingly frustrated with
an 'uncaring' system and created friction between her and
other care-givers. The provision of paid care can therefore have a huge
impact on the capacity of carers to sustain and, as is often required,
increase their levels of caring over long periods of time. Conceding
that the existing economic infrastructure cannot afford to provide paid
care workers to do all of the caring required, the SA Carers'
Recognition Act (2005) is an attempt to redress the power imbalance
between carers and the organisation of paid care.
While the UK has had a Carer (Recognition and Services) Act since
1995, Australia is currently following suit. South Australia now has a
Carers' Charter (2005) backed up by legislation, and the ACT looks
set to do something similar. In many ways the new legislation recognises
the integral relationship between care provider organisations and the
capacity for carers to sustain their role. The focus now has to be on
both care recipients and carers. This is evident in the objects of the
SA Carers' Recognition Act (2005), which are:
a) to recognise and support carers and their role in the community;
and
b) to provide for the reporting by organisations of the action
taken to reflect the principles of the Carers' Charter in the
provision of services relevant to carers and the persons they care for.
Care provider organisations are therefore going to have particular
responsibilities towards carers, ensuring that their employees
understand the Carers' Charter and that their services reflect
this; and that any public sector organisation involves caters in both
policy and program development and strategic/operational planning so as
to maximise relevance to carers and care recipients.
In effect the legislation calls on organisations to treat unpaid
carers as partners in the provision of care. This elevates their
position to a point where their needs, as well as those of care
recipients have to be taken into account. This is quite different to
their previous relationship with the formal system and is likely to
place new pressures on organisations responsible for providing care
services. Catering for Denise's needs, for example, would require
organisations to consider 'care' in terms of her relationship
with her father, her relationship to other care-givers and her
relationship to the organisation (or organisations). Accordingly, one
likely implication of the Carers' Charter is that many
organisations will need to incorporate a more robust notion of care into
their service provision and their organisational culture.
The three tensions identified here challenge the wisdom of pursuing
market logic in care provider organisations. The increasing empowerment
of care recipients highlights the need for organisations to be more
responsive to different needs in relation to care, including the
relational, emotional and psychological aspects of care. Difficulties in
relation to the recruitment and retention of care workers suggest that
organisations need to find ways to support these workers in providing
the care required of them by both care recipients and unpaid carers,
including the relational forms of care. Meanwhile, the Carers'
Charter, backed up by legislative requirements, imposes a bureaucratic
logic of care while simultaneously recognising the value of the familial
logic of care, demanding greater collaboration with, and responsiveness
towards, unpaid carers. There are, then, pressing and legitimate reasons
for rethinking the relationship between care and the market at an
organisational level. The question is, how can organisations operate
such that the efficient and effective delivery of services includes
providing support for the development and maintenance of caring
relationships?
Rethinking the organisational approach to care service provision
In this section I examine how care might be supported in an
organisational context. In arguing that that there is scope for
organisations to develop a system of care services that incorporates
both relational and emotional aspects, I draw on the work of Mumby and
Putnam (1992, 1993) and propose a framework of bounded emotionality as a
way forward. The key to this framework is the recognition that
organisations are both rational and emotional arenas. As demonstrated
earlier, tensions in the managerialist approach are occurring because
market logic is primarily based on rational principles which either
disregard emotions or view them as useful only when they are
instrumental in achieving market objectives. In contrast, the concept of
bounded emotionality recognises that there is a need for organisational
structures and mechanisms that are supportive of workers and their
emotional attachments to, and practices within, the workplace.
The term 'bounded emotionality' is a deliberate ploy used
by Mumby and Putnam to disrupt the conventional association between
rationality and organisations. In some ways the term is a misnomer because Mumby and Putnam also recognise the importance of rationality in
the development of individual and organisational identities. Indeed,
they argue that neither rationality nor emotionality 'should be a
privileged conceptual and experiential frame for organisations'
(1992: 480-1). Maintaining a balance between rationality and
emotionality involves shifting 'rationality to include
intersubjective understanding, community, and shared interests'
(Mumby and Putnam 1992: 481). This shift has two dimensions to it.
Firstly, there is a need to recognise the emotionality of rationality.
Rather than being objective or value-neutral, rational decisions are
subjectively constructed and influenced by what Mumby and Putnam (1992:
480) call the 'consensus that emerges through the communicative practices of organisations.' Secondly, there is a need to develop a
more rational conception of emotion. This would involve recognising the
'knowledge-producing dimensions of emotion' (Mumby and Putnam
1992: 480). For many care workers, the knowledge they have of care
recipients is either learned through their emotional connection with one
another or because they have the skills to interpret the
recipients' emotions. From this perspective, the relational
dimension of care demands the incorporation of emotions and feelings and
recognises these as skills: learnable, transferable and valuable.
Bounded emotionality is a mode of organising based on nurturance,
caring, community, supportiveness, and interrelatedness (Mumby and
Putnam 1992). While the emotions required to engage in these kinds of
activities are recognised and valued, they are not given a free rein.
Emotions are bounded by the intersubjective constraints required to
ensure that individuals respond to others within the organisation in
ways that sustain the organisational community (Mumby and Putnam 1992:
474). An organisation which exemplifies a system of bounded emotionality
will display particular norms, which include (Martin et al 1998: 8-10;
King, forthcoming):
1. A tolerance of ambiguity and capacity to grasp two or more
points of view simultaneously in decision-making
2. A heterarchy (ie multiple, non-hierarchical categorization) of
goals and values which are organised and governed by the contextual
relations within an organisation
3. The facilitation of an integrated self-identity for
organisational members through breaking down the separation between
public and private domains, and nurturing and supporting members as
whole people (with emotions, bodies and rationality)
4. A labor process which is constructed within a community, and
maintained through the legitimation of feelings and caring relationships
amongst its members
5. Valuing those work feelings governed by relational feeling rules
and which are supported by organisational structures and cultures.
Of these norms, the idea of work feelings is likely to be
particularly relevant to care work. This point is taken up further later
in the article.
The norms associated with bounded emotionality can be empirically
identified and discussed, as in Martin et al's (1998) research on
The Body Shop. Martin et al found that The Body Shop's
pro-feminist, pro-environmental ethical orientation resulted in the
development of organisational norms that recognised the value of
emotional expression and work feelings and that viewed employees as
'whole people' (complete with mind, body and emotions) who
often had family and community roles. Although not all of the norms
associated with bounded emotionality were evident in The Body Shop, most
were. These helped to create an organisational environment that was
positive for workers, who had high levels of work-satisfaction and
enthusiasm, loyalty and commitment. At an organisational level, there
was greater stability in the workforce, higher levels of trust and
communication, and improved efficiency in areas such as information
exchange and customer service (Martin, Knopoff and Beckman 1998).
Parallels between The Body Shop and care provider organisations in
having an ethical orientation, a need to be financially viable and
obligations to external stakeholders, suggest that the development of
organisational systems that are supportive of the relational as well as
physical aspects of care are possible. Given the predominance of
religious and not-for-profit organisations operating in the field of
home and community care, the idea that organisations can be based on
rational and emotional principles would surely be appealing. Such a
framework is likely to be less alienating for care workers, for whom
care and other forms of emotionality are central to the performance of
their work roles and to their identities as workers. This is not to deny
that there are likely to be ongoing tensions between emotionality and
rationality within organisations. However, as Mumby and Putnam argue,
the challenge is actually to keep them in balance rather than allowing
one to dominate the other.
One of the premises of bounded emotionality is that work related
emotions are legitimate and need to be structurally supported. These
work related emotions refer to more than just emotional labour, which
has long been recognised as integral to care work, both as a source of
alienation and a basis for work satisfaction (eg Hochschild 1983).
Indeed, Mumby and Putnam are critical of organisations that view
emotional labour as the only valid expression of emotion. They argue
that within these organisations, emotional labour is structured
according to primarily rational principles to the extent that an
individual's emotions are organisationally controlled and ascribed
(see Table 2). This results in feelings being commodified and only
viewed as useful if subjected to instrumental purposes such as
efficiency, profit and productivity (1992: 471). This instrumental view
of emotions in the workplace cannot incorporate (and therefore cannot
support) the 'individual experience, the relational context, and
the intimacy that typifies [the] expression of personal feelings'
(Mumby and Putnam 1992: 472) that are particularly pertinent to forms of
work such as care work. The alternative proposed by Putnam and Mumby
(1993) is to value workplace emotions through the concept of work
feelings.
In care work, many of the feelings that are associated with work
are spontaneous and emerge from what Mumby and Putnam would call the
'ongoing process of task and social activities rather than from
organisational control' (1992: 477). Within care work emotions are
primarily communicative involving a range of skills (listening,
negotiating, understanding other people's feelings) that encourage
interrelatedness and mutual understanding between co-workers, workers
and clients, and management and workers. The purpose (or reasoning)
behind such work feelings is therefore always practical in that it aims
to maintain intersubjectivity (such as respect for others) and mutual
understanding. As these are key components of the provision of good
care, work feelings provide a means of discussing organisational
emotionality in supportive, cognitive and operational ways. An
organisation does not, therefore, have to tell care workers what are and
are not permissible emotions or feelings. Instead, because both
organisation and workers have a mutual understanding of what constitutes
good care, feeling rules become meaning-centred, allowing individuals to
'interpret and adapt to organisational contexts and
relationships' (1992: 478).
The work feelings approach facilitates a way of viewing
organisational emotionality in ways that limit the potential for
dissonance and bum-out and optimise the ability to provide practical
support and recognition. In addition, the approach also enables the kind
of spontaneity and autonomy required for responsive caring, as opposed
to mechanical performance of tasks. The development of such an approach
requires juxtaposing rationality with bounded emotionality to the extent
that instrumental goals become embedded within a heterarchy of
organisational values (and therefore not permitted to become
hierarchically dominant). This requires organisational commitment and
recognition of the importance of emotions in providing the levels of
physical and relational care expected by care recipients, carer partners
and care workers.
Toward a practice of bounded emotionality
The provision of home and community care needs to be responsive and
effective, appropriate and efficient, and meet relational and physical
needs. The current market-managerialist model preferred by government
funding bodies focuses on being effective, efficient and meeting
physical needs. It therefore often fails to meet the expectations of
care recipients, care workers and carer partners. The tensions that this
creates for service provider organisations are unsustainable and
unnecessary. There are ways of organising care services that enable
organisations to also deliver responsive, appropriate and relational
care. Bounded emotionality provides one example.
Restructuring organisations around norms associated with bounded
emotionality is more likely to create an environment where organisations
can meet the needs of its care recipients, care workers and carer
partners. Firstly, it would support the provision of care that is
attentive and responsive to the emotional, social and physical needs of
care recipients. Secondly, it is likely to improve the retention and
recruitment rates of care workers. Organisations would have the
structures and cultures required to meet the needs of good quality care
workers by providing a community that values relational autonomy, having
the capacity to meet the relational and physical care needs of care
recipients and providing support for workers to use their skills to make
a difference to care recipients' lives. Thirdly, it would respond
to the needs of (unpaid) carers and their right to be considered as
partners in care provision.
In this respect, the system of bounded emotionality affords a
unique opportunity for organisations whose core business is the
provision of care and care services. For these organisations, care is
central and it needs to be supported and understood if it is to be
sustained. Care recipients, care-workers and carer partners all have
different needs in relation to care. While the physical aspects of care
are an important component, the emotional, psychological and relational
aspects are equally important. Delivering holistic care involves
understanding the skills required to identify the appropriate types and
levels of emotional engagement for each individual and to manage a care
relationship in ways that will optimise the outcomes for both the
physical and emotional aspects of care provision. Such skills are based
on effective communication and emotional and social competencies (such
as those used in emotional intelligence--see Goleman 1998). As with any
form of work, however, care work requires organisational support for it
to be effectively delivered. It is a core premise of this article that
care work cannot be effectively provided (and sustained) if the
organisational structures and cultures are 'uncaring'.
Given that the provision and, I argue, the support of care are core
business for care-provider organisations it would be presumptuous to
assume that bounded emotionality does not already exist. While it is
evident that the managerialist logic of care is the dominant one and
certainly the one expected from funding bodies, the religious and
charitable background of many non-profit care-provider organisations is
undoubtedly conducive to the principles of bounded emotionality. It is
possible, perhaps even probable, that some organisations already
implicitly embed principles of bounded emotionality in their structures
and cultures. In developing a more empirical research agenda it would be
interesting to examine the extent to which care provider organisations
already utilize bounded emotionality and the impact this has on employee
morale and retention rates, on the capacity of the organisation to meet
recipient needs and on its relationship with carer partners. At another
level, there is also a need to explore the impact on the experiences of
care workers, carers and care recipients; the financial viability of
organisations; and organisational cultures and structures.
While this paper has canvassed the perceived advantages of
organisations adopting systems of bounded emotionality, there could also
be disadvantages. An obvious issue is the potential complexity of
balancing emotionality with rational principles and norms. Identifying
the practices that organisations use to prevent one being subsumed by
the other would help to make the concept of bounded emotionality more
robust and transferable to other organisational contexts. This would
also be enhanced by research into the means by which individual
organisations might maintain systems of bounded emotionality within the
context of inter-organisational interdependence. Organisational
boundaries are permeable and therefore subject to pressure from
'outside'; how organisations counteract (or accede to) this
pressure would provide interesting insights in relation to
inter-organisational power and influence, as well as any changes to the
broader value of 'care' in society.
Other, perhaps more practical, issues would need to be addressed if
research on Australian care-provider organisations found that bounded
rationality was indeed useful in rethinking the provision of care. For
example, what might be the best process for organisational change? What
are the cost implications and how might these be managed? How would the
boundaries around work feelings and emotional labour be organised and
reviewed? Beyond the organisational aspects of bounded emotionality, the
approach also affects care givers and care recipients. For example, how
would the different stakeholders construct and reconstruct the
boundaries of care? How could care givers be trained in the appropriate
provision of emotional, social and relational care--to take into account
their own as well as the care recipient's needs?
There is still much to be learned about the ways in which care
provider organisations can best be structured in order to deliver and
support 'good care' to the frail aged and people with
disabilities. Care is not only relevant to the relationship between
care-givers and care recipients, even though this is the most obvious
point of transfer. There is a need for organisations to also care, and
in this way to support the capacity for care-givers to sustain the level
of caring that we as a society are demanding. The concept of bounded
emotionality provides one way of thinking through how this might be
possible.
Acknowledgements
My thanks go to Jacky Morris, whose knowledge of care theories and
assistance in discussing the themes of the paper has been invaluable.
References
Carers' Assocation of SA (2003) 'State carers policy
discussion paper', unpublished report presented to the Caret Ministerial Advisory Committee.
Cancian, F. (2000) 'Paid emotional care: organisational forms
that encourage nurturance'. In M. Harrington Meyer (ed.) Care Work:
Gender, Class and the Welfare State, New York, Routledge.
Carers Recognition Act (2005) [accessed 7 March 2006 online at
http://www. parliament.sa.gov.au/Catalog/legislation/Acts/c/2005.55.un.htm]
Goleman, D. (1998) Working with Emotional Intelligence, London,
Bloomsbury.
HACC (2005a) 'Home and Community Care South Australia: HACC
position paper 2005-2006', Govt. of SA, Dept for Families and
Communities.
HACC (2005b) 'Queensland Home and Community Care Program: HACC
Workforce Skills Development Strategy', Qld Govt, Queensland
Health.
HACC (2003) 'Home and Community Care (HACC) new entrant development project: final report', State Govt. of Victoria, Dept
of Human Services.
Hochschild, A.R (1983) The Managed Heart: The Commercialization of
Human Feeling, Berkeley, University of California Press.
Hopkins, D., McKie L., Watson, N. & Hughes, B. (2005) 'The
problem of emotion in care: contested meanings from the Disabled
People's Movement and the feminist movement'. In H. Flam and
D. King (eds) Emotions and Social Movements, London, Routledge.
Kahn, W. A. (1993) 'Caring for the caregivers: Patterns of
organisational caregiving', Administrative Science Quarterly 38
(4), 539-63.
Kangas, S. Kee, C.C & McKee-Whaddle, R. (1999)
'Organisational factors, nurses' job satisfaction, and patient
satisfaction with nursing care', The Journal of Nursing
Administration, 29 (1), 32-42.
King, D. (forthcoming) 'Bounded emotionality'. In S.
Clegg and J.R. Bailey (eds.) International Encyclopedia of Organisation
Studies, London, Sage.
Knijn, T. (2000) 'Marketization And the struggling logics of
(home) care in the Netherlands'. In M. Harrington Meyer (ed.) Care
Work: Gender, Class and the Welfare State, New York, Routledge.
Martin, J., Knopoff, K. & Beckman, C. (1998) 'An
alternative to bureaucratic impersonality and emotional labor: Bounded
emotionality at the Body Shop', Administrative Science Quarterly,
43 (2), 429-69.
Meagher, G. (2006) 'What can we expect from paid
carers?', Politics & Society, 34 (1), 33-53.
McEvoy, D. (2004) 'Clarrie'. Paper presented in
Carers' Week at the Service Providers' Forum.
Mumby, D.K. & Putnam, L.L. (1992) 'The politics of
emotion: a feminist reading of bounded rationality', Academy of
Management Review, 17 (3), 465-486.
Miehls, D. & Moffatt, K. (2000) 'Constructing social work
identity based on the reflexive self', British Journal of Social
Work, 30(3), 339-348.
Nussbaum, M. (2001) Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of
Emotions, New York, Cambridge University Press.
Piercy, K. W. (2000) 'When it is more than a job: close
relationships between home health aides and older clients', Journal
of Aging and Health, 12 (3), 362-387.
Putnam, L.L. & Mumby, D.K. (1993) 'Organisations, emotion
and the myth of rationality'. In S. Fineman (ed.) Emotion in
Organisations, Boston, Harvard Business School Press.
Ryan, T., Nolan, M. et al. (2004) "Part of the family':
sources of job satisfaction amongst a group of community-based dementia
care workers', Health and Social Care in the Community, 12 (2),
111-118.
Scott, R. A., Aiken, L. H. Mechanic, D. & Moravcsik, J. (1995)
'Organisational aspects of caring', The Milbank Quarterly, 73
(1), 77-95.
Stacey, C. L. (2005) 'Finding dignity in dirty work: the
constraints and rewards of low-wage home care labour', Sociology of
Health and Illness, 27 (6), 831-854.
Stack, S. & Provis, C. (2000) 'The slide from public
sector to private sector in-home care: some ethical concerns'.
Paper presented at the conference of the International Institute for
Public Ethics, Ottawa, Sept 24-28.
Stone, D. (2000) 'Caring by the book.' In M. Harrington
Meyer (ed.) Care Work: Gender, Class and the Welfare State, New York,
Routledge.
Table 1. Logics of care
Professional Market
Care recipients Clients Consumers
Care providers Professionals / Entrepreneurs
experts
Assumptions / Expertise / Efficiency /
enacted through personal treatment effectiveness /
profit
Mechanisms of Professional ethics Supply and
Control demand
Bureaucratic Familial
Care recipients Citizens Kin / significant
others
Care providers Public services Relatives /
volunteers
Assumptions / Justice / equal Social bonds
enacted through treatment / reciprocity /
normative claims
Mechanisms of Democratic Social and
Control personal
(adapted from Knijn 2000)
Table 2. Models of emotionality in organisations
Emotional labour Work feelings
Organisationally controlled Spontaneous and emergent
Feelings as commodities Feelings as interrelatedness
Organisationally ascribed Meaning-centred
Instrumental reasoning Practical reasoning
(adapted from Mumby and Putnam 1992: 477)