Memorializing Paul A. Samuelson: a review of his major works, 1915-2009.
Ramrattan, Lall ; Szenberg, Michael
Introduction
We have lost the dean of American economists, the unrivalled leader
of neoclassical economics on December 13, 2009. Paul Anthony Samuelson
was born on May 15, 1915 in Gary, Indiana to his parents Frank Samuelson
and Ella Lipton. The family moved to Chicago, where Paul attended the
Hyde Park High School. He entered the University of Chicago at age 16
and took up economics after having heard a lecture on the Reverend T. R.
Malthus. After graduating with a BA from there in 1935, he attended
Harvard, where he earned an MA in 1936, and a PhD in 1941. He married a
fellow student, Marion Crawford, in 1938, and after her death in 1978,
he was married to Risha Clay Samuelson.
Samuelson's Ph.D. thesis became the celebrated Foundations of
Economic Analysis published in 1947. A year later, he published his
famous text, Economics. Those two works bracketed his contribution from
the simple to the complex aspects of economics that were imitated by
many and had educated over a generation of economists.
Samuelson started teaching as an instructor at Harvard in 1940, but
after a month he moved to MIT as an assistant professor. While at MIT,
he became an Associate Professor (1944), Professor (1947), and finally
Institute Professor (1966). He also received honorary doctoral degrees
from the University of Chicago (1961), Oberlin College (1961), Indiana
University (1966), and East Anglia University (1966), and was a Ford
foundation Research Fellow during 1958-1959. His numerous awards include
the David A. Wells Prize in 1941 by Harvard University, the John Bates
Clark Medal by the American Economic Association in 1947, and the Nobel
Laureate Prize in economics by the Bank of Sweden in 1970 for his
scientific contributions to economics.
Because he did not wish to compromise his thinking in economics,
Samuelson turned down President Kennedy's requests to serve as the
chair of the economic council. Samuelson, however, has been credited
with educating the president on Keynesian economics, and he also was the
one to encourage the tax cut that was implemented during Johnson's
administration.
Goals of Economics
Samuelson's goal was to understand the "... behavior of
mixed-economies of the American and Western European type"
(Samuelson, CW, 1986, V. 3,728). His means to this goal was to be
scientifically honest. He held that "... science consists of
descriptions of empirical regularities" (Ibid., 772). Therefore,
"... a good economist has good judgment about economic
reality" (Ibid., 775). One should not wonder why he often refers to
Thomas Kuhn, for Kuhn holds that "economic analysis advances
discontinuously. After a great forward step, time must be taken to
consolidate the gains achieved" (Samuelson, 1966, V. 2, 1140).
Within this research mentality, Samuelson goes after reality with
economic models, being well aware that "the science of economics
does not provide simple answers to complex social problems" (Ibid.,
V. 2, 1325). Economics for him was different in degree but not in kind
from the physical sciences: "All sciences have the common task of
describing and summarizing empirical reality. Economics is no
exception" (Ibid., V. 2, 1756). But unlike the falsificationist, he
does not look at facts to terminate a theory. Rather, "in economics
it takes a theory to kill a theory; facts can only dent the
theorist's hide" (Ibid., V. 2, 1568).
Samuelson's representative definition of economics is:
"the study of how people and society end up choosing, with or
without the use of money, to employ scarce productive resources that
could have alternative uses, to produce various commodities and
distribute them for consumption, now or in the future, among various
persons and groups in society. It analyzes the costs and benefits of
improving patterns of resource allocation" (Samuelson, 1980, 2). We
also see elements of production, distribution, consumption, and cost
benefit analysis in his definition.
Methodology
Samuelson has evolved the "operational" method of
economics. He said: "my work in the theory of revealed preference,
in Foundations of Economic: Analysis, and in the several volumes of
Collected Scientific Papers, consistently bears out this general
methodological procedure" (Samuelson, 1986, V. 5, 793 [Italics
original]). Basically, the procedure is "...to learn what
descriptions [new literature and mathematical paradigms] imply for
observable data" (Ibid., V. 5,793). With data on the one hand, and
logic and theory on the other, operationalism seeks a correspondence of
the two sides. "Samuelson's 'correspondence principle
between comparative statics and dynamics' ... shows how the problem
of deriving operationally meaningful theorems in comparative statics is
closely tied up with the problem of stability of equilibrium"
(Morishima, 1964, 24).
In the realm of dynamics, Samuelson postulated that dp/dt =
H([q.sub.D] - [q.sub.s]), where the term on the left is the rate of
change of prices, dp with respect to changes of time, dt. H is a
proportional constant, q is quantity, S is supply, and D is demand
(Samuelson, 1966, V. 1, 544). Stability is therefore assured if as time
goes to infinity, the solution of the differential equation breaks down,
which in economic terms means, "... the supply curve cuts the
demand curve from below" (Samuelson, 1947, 18).
Areas of interest
Samuelson described himself as a generalist. He once claimed to be
the last generalist in economics, writing and teaching such diverse
subjects as international trade and econometrics, economic theory and
business cycle, demography and labor economics, finance and monopolistic
competition, history of doctrines and locational economics (Samuelson,
1986, V. 5, 800). His works were published in five volumes titled
Collected Scientific Papers of Paul Samuelson, with two more volumes
expected. We sample some of his major works by topics below.
Macroeconornies
In macroeconomics, Samuelson forged the 'neoclassical
synthesis' view, which added the neoclassical economic foundation
to Keynesian economic thought. From the fourth (1958) to the eleventh
(1980) edition of his Economics, he held that economists have been
synthesizing traditional theory with newer Keynesian thoughts on income
distribution. He accepted the Keynesian synthesis as a revolutionary way
to look "... at how the entire gross national product is determined
and how wages and prices and the rate of unemployment are determined
with it" (Samuelson, CW, V. 5, 1986, 280). Looking through the
Keynesian lenses, Samuelson saw that economic policies should operate
from the point of view of a 'mixed-economy', mixed because
government works side-by-side with the private sector in economic
affairs during business cycles. Such cycles are generated when the
traditional concept of the accelerator (constant capital to output in
the naive version) interacts with the Keynesian multiplier, a concept
first seized by Samuelson.
In 1958, Samuelson introduced the overlapping generation model
(OLG), which is seen as a rival to the famous Arrow-Debreu general
equilibrium model for the economy, and is a popular model in modern
macroeconomic analysis (Samuelson, CW, V. 1, 1966, 219-234). The model
allows intergenerational trading such as where a middle-aged person
lends his savings to a younger person, expecting from him savings in
return in a later period. The model "... breaks each life up into
thirds: men produce one unit of product in period 1 and one unit in
period 2; in period 3 they retire and produce nothing" (Ibid.,
220). U - U([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2], [C.sub.3]) represents the utility
function on consumption in each period. The rate of interest is the
price of exchange between current and future foods. [R.sub.t] =
1/(1+[i.sub.t]) is the discount rate. Equilibrium is achieved in period
three when the discounted value of consumption equals the discounted
value of production, or [C.sub.1] + [C.sub.2][R.sub.t] +
[C.sub.3][R.sub.t][R.sub.t+1] = 1 + 1[R.sub.t] + 0[R.sub.t][R.sub.t+1] =
1 + 1[R.sub.t] (Ibid., 221).
If savings is income less consumption, we can specify the model
from the savings and the savers' points of view.
[S.sub.p]([R.sub.t], [R.sub.t+1]) is the saving function for p periods:
1, 2, 3. The population, B, at time, t, can be written as [B.sub.t]. The
population at different periods can be represented by a first period,
[B.sub.t], a second period [B.sub.t-1], and a third period [B.sub.t-2].
The equilibrium condition can then be represented as
[B.sub.t][S.sub.1]([R.sub.t], [R.sub.t+1]) +
[B.sub.t-1][S.sub.2]([R.sub.t-1], [R.sub.t]) + [B.sub.t-
2][S.sub.3]([R.sub.t-2], [R.sub.t-1]) = 0 (Ibid., 222). If all the
B's are the same (i.e. a stationary population), then [R.sub.t] =
1. If B grows exponentially, then the equality of the discount rate with
the population growth rate is also a solution. The solution being that
there would be harmony between current and future savings and
consumption plans across generations, with the model addressing how they
would grow alongside zero and the actual growth rate in population.
Considering further developments, Solow elevated this model in the
history of economic thought: "... this innocent little device of
Samuelson's has been developed into a serious and quite general
modeling strategy that uncovers equilibrium possibilities not to be
found in standard Walrasian formulations" (Solow, 2006, 40).
Cambridge Controversy
In 1962, Samuelson derived a Walrasian-like production function by
creating an index for capital from the many equations that capture the
technique of production of firms that populate the economy (Samuelson,
1966, V. 1,325-337). Using this surrogate capital index, he derived a
surrogate production function to capture certain stylized facts about
neoclassical economics. According to C. E. Ferguson, (1975,
245)"The essential issue may be put this way. If production
functions are smoothly continuous and everywhere continuously
differentiable, the neoclassical results hold (possible in a somewhat
attenuated form if one allows for heterogeneous capital goods)."
The problem of measuring capital came up with David Ricardo, to
which the roots of marginal analysis are traced. "The whole
marginal analysis was born of Ricardo's attempt to explain the
share of rent in the national income, and to show why some rents on some
land were higher than on other...'land' could be measured...in
acres...adding together different acres weighted by their relative
prices... the same could be done for labor...using relative wages as the
basis of weights. With capital the problem was an entirely different
one, since there was no unit in which we could reduce capital to
homogeneous units" (Lutz and Hague, 1961, 305). As K. Wicksell
(1911, V. 1,149) puts it:
Whereas labor and land are measured each in
terms of its own technical unit (e.g. working
days or months, acre per an- num) capital ... is
reckoned ... as a sum of exchange value-whether
in money or as an average of
products, in other words, each particular
capital-good is measured by a unit extraneous
to itself. [This] is a theoretical anomaly which
disturbs the correspondence which would
otherwise exist between all the factors of
production. The productive contribution of a
piece of technical capital, such as a steam
engine, is determined not by its cost but by
the horse-power which it develops, and by the
excess or scarcity of similar machines. If capital
were to be measured in technical units,
the defect would be remedied and the correspondence
would be complete. But, in that
case, productive capital would have to be
distributed into as many categories as there
are kinds of tools, machinery, and materials,
etc., and a unified treatment of the role of
capital in production would be impossible.
Even then we should only know the yield of
the various objects at a particular moment,
but nothing at all about the value of the goods
themselves, which it is necessary to know in
order to calculate the rate of interest, which in
equilibrium is the same on all capital.
The measurement of capital is therefore, among the top two problems
in capital theory, the other being the capital-output ratio (Lutz, 1961,
9). Leon Walras' view on capital is also foundational, although his
model is different from Ricardo's (see Nell, 1967, 15-26). Walras
postulated "... a capital goods market, where capital goods are
bought and sold...They are demanded because of the land-services, labor
and capital-services they render, or better, because the rent, wages and
interest which these services yield" (Walras, 1954, 267). The price
of the capital goods depends on the price of its services or its income.
Net income is the gross income, p, less the price of the capital goods,
P, adjusted for depreciation, It, and insurance premiums, v, i.e, [pi] =
[p - ([Mu] + v)P]. (Ibid., 268). From this we get the rate of net income
i = [pi]/P, suggesting that p - ([MU] + v)P = iP, from which we can get
the price of all capital goods (Ibid., 269). Walras suggested that we
should not deduct depreciation or insurance charges for land, nor for
personal faculties (human capital) because they are natural and known.
Land and personal faculties are hired in kind in the capital market, but
capital is usually hired in the form of money in the money market. The
proper capital goods are artificial (not natural), and are subject to
cost of production, depreciation and insurance premiums (Ibid., 271).
"Capital formation consists ... in the transformation of services
into new capital goods, just as production consists in the
transformation of services into consumer goods" (Ibid., 282).
Putting it all together, "Once the equilibrium has been established
in principle (through groping), exchange can take place immediately.
Production, however, requires a certain lapse of time ... equilibrium in
production ... will be established effectively through the reciprocal
exchange between services employed and products manufactured within a
given period of time during which no change in the data is allowed"
(Ibid., 242). A similar situation holds for capital formation (Ibid.,
282). In the end, "Capital formation in a market ruled by free
competition is an operation by which the excess of income over
consumption can be transformed into such types and quantities of new
capital goods proper as are best suited to yield the greatest possible
satisfaction of wants" (Ibid., 305).
With this Walrasian background, we can appreciate Joan
Robinson's position that "a piece of equipment or a stock of
raw materials, regarded as a product, has a price, like any other
product, made up of prime cost plus a gross margin. These costs (direct
and indirect) are composed of wages, rents, depreciation and net profit.
The amount of net profit entering into the price of the product is,
obviously, influenced by the general rate of profit prevailing in the
industries concerned. Thus the value of capital depends upon the rate of
profit. There is no way of presenting a quantity of capital in any
realistic manner apart from the rate of profit, so that to say that
profits measure, or represent or correspond to the marginal product of
capital is meaningless" (Robinson, 1971, 601). Yet we find attempts
to construct an aggregate production function in a J. B. Clark and Frank
Ramsey style, where the definition of capital represents a challenge.
From the macroeconomic point of view, the aggregate production function
is written as Y = f(K, L) which is read that output is a function of
capital and labor, respectively. In equilibrium, the marginal product of
labor is the wage rate. The marginal product of capital is set equal to
the rate of interest, which is at the center of the controversy.
Joan Robinson sets up the controversy this way: "In 1961 I
encountered Professor Samuelson on his home ground; in the course of an
argument I happened to ask him 'When you define the marginal
product of labor, what do you keep constant?' He seemed
disconcerted, as though none of his pupils had ever asked that question,
but the next day he gave a clear answer. Either the physical inputs
other than labor are kept constant, or the rate of profit on capital is
kept constant. I found this satisfactory, for it destroys the doctrine
that wages are regulated by marginal productivity" (Robinson, 1970,
310).
The problem has to do with time, or the time period of production.
"Wicksell never used the term K ... but always inserted the term T
on the grounds that it is by allowing labor to use roundabout,
time-consuming processes of production that capital raises the
productivity of labor and thus is itself production" (Lutz, 1961,
10). But in a letter to Alfred Marshall, Wicksell (1905, V. 3, 102
[Italics original]) wrote: "... the theory of capital and interest
cannot be regarded as complete yet. As I have tried to show several
times ... so long as capital is defined as a sum of commodities (or of
value) the doctrine of the marginal productivity of capital as
determining the rate of interest is never quite true and often not true
at all--it is true individually, but not in respect of the whole capital
of society."
Samuelson wrote several articles on the topic of capital theory
leading to his 1962 milestone article on the surrogate production
function. His 1937 article, "Some Aspects of The Pure Theory of
Capital" probed the aspect of time and timeless analysis of the
production function (Samuelson, CW, V. 1, 1966, 161-188). He posited
relationships for "constant rate of interest" and "the
rate of interest itself in an unrestricted function of time"
(Ibid., 163). Treating the rate of interest, r, as a constant, one can
capitalize an income stream at the beginning and at the end of a period,
returning values V(0, r), and V(t, r) for time t = 0, and t = t,
respectively. The internal rate of return, f, makes the initial value of
the investment zero, V(0, F) = 0 (Ibid., 165-167). We can show
"...at any instant of time the value of every investment account is
unequivocally determined" (Ibid., 169). The income stream so
determined will vary in the real world due to uncertainty, imputation of
income and market imperfections (Ibid., 170).
The treatment of a constant rate of interest represents a condition
of stationary society without capital accumulation. Making the rate of
interest a function of time, r = r(t), requires the consideration of an
average rate, p. The relation of p to r is the same as the relationship
of the margin to the average. The constancy of the rate of interest is
seen as a special case of the variation of the rate of interest with
time. The same relationship between perpetual income and value will hold
for the constant and variable view of the interest rate (Ibid., 177).
In 1939, Samuelson furthered the analysis to show "...some of
the forces which help to determine the market rate of interest at which
all can borrow or lend under ideal conditions" (Ibid., 189200). He
used discrete periods, when the interest rate in any period equilibrates
total asset holdings with the total assets of all enterprises. The
approach he took "... does not require any definition of capital as
a physical quantity" (Ibid., 199).
In 1943, Samuelson considered dynamic, static, and stationary state
conditions for the rate of interest to be zero (Samuelson, CW, 1966, V.
1,201-211). After considering cases where capital should have a zero net
productivity (according to Frank Ramsey), and where the maximum output
is never attained for a finite value of capital (according to Frank
Knight), Samuelson took the position "... not to reify the limit by
asking what really happens at a zero rate of interest, but rather to
concentrate upon the dynamic path toward this limiting condition"
(Samuelson, Ibid., 211).
In 1956, Samuelson and Robert Solow extended consideration of the
Ramsey zero interest and one capital-good model to heterogeneous capital
goods (Samuelson, CW, 1966, V. 1,261-286). This article was setting the
stage to "... reconstruct the composition of its diverse capital
goods so that there may remain great heuristic value in the simpler J.
B. Clark-Ramsey models of abstract capital substance" (Ibid.,
261-262). Broadly speaking, the treatment of capital, fixed or
circulating, can be looked at either as inputs or efficient outputs or
consumption it generates. Simplified, the Ramsey model maximizes all
future utility of consumption, U(C), constrained by a saving function,
f(s). The model, however, does not consider "... differences
between different kinds of goods and different kinds of labor, and
suppose them to be expressed in terms of fixed standards, so that we can
speak simply of quantities of capital, consumption and labor without
discussing their particular forms" (Ramsey, 1928, 544).
Samuelson's and Solow's effort was to drop that assumption.
In a Clark-Ramsey framework, capital enters as a constraint, f(s)
in the initial period. In his 1961 paper on "The Evaluation of
Social Income: Capital Formation and Wealth", Samuelson (CW, V. 1,
1966, 299-324) elaborated on this capital constraint. There was one
output, produced from inputs, F(K, L) which can be invested or consumed.
Capital K can be changed to say K2 with twice the value of the original
capital, which will no longer be produced. The production function for
gross output is now F(K + [K.sub.2], L), which is netted for
depreciation at a rate equal to m. He used this model to answer an old
"... 1935 debate between Pigou and Hayek as to the meaning of
maintaining capital intact" (Ibid., 302). From this model also, the
factors are rewarded their marginal products (Ibid., 304). The article
"... dealt with the problem of efficiency by valuing all capital in
terms of new capital" (Lutz and Hague, 1960, 314). His treatment of
depreciation seems to be dealing with mortality or accident as in the
Walrasian insurance premium case (Ibid., 314). The income article
though, did not address the problem of measuring capital. The model
avoided the "... heterogeneity of capital goods. He had been able,
with his methods, to avoid the problem of whether one was dealing with
four-or five-year-old cars, or with different qualities of land as in
Ricardo's theory" (Ibid., 315).
In a milestone article of 1962, Samuelson wanted to show that the
surrogate production function, represented by a w - r frontier, can be
derived from heterogeneous capital goods as well as from an aggregate
homogenous capital good (Ferguson, 1972, 169). If we start with a
heterogeneous set of capital-goods, each associated with labor, then
"one need never speak of the production function, but rather should
speak of a great number of separate production functions, which
correspond to each activity and which have no smooth substitutability
properties" (Samuelson, CA, V. 1, 166, 326). These have a linear
programming-like structure that Samuelson and others explored in Linear
Programming and Economic Analysis (Dorfman, Samuelson, and Solow, 1958),
and in an independent piece on the subject (Samuelson, CW, V. 1, 1966,
287-298).
In general, production has two sectors, one producing consumption
goods, and one producing capital goods--A). [P.sub.k] = [a.sub.k]W +
[b.sub.k] (r + [delta])[P.sub.k], where p is the price, W is the wage, r
is the interest rate, [delta] is the depreciation, k represents the
capital sector, a and b are labor requirements per unit of output, and
B). [P.sub.c] = [a.sub.c]W + [b.sub.c] (r + [delta])[P.sub.c]. Given the
rate of interest, we can find the wage rate, and vice versa. One method
in solving them is to eliminate prices in each equation and then set the
results equal to each other. The linearity comes out if we assume with
Samuelson that [a.sub.k] = [a.sub.c]; [b.sub.k] = [b.sub.c], for then we
get W/[P.sub.c] = [1 - [b.sub.k](r + [delta])]/[a.sub.k], which is
linear (Samuelson, CW, V. 1, 1966, 337).
In stationary or steady state conditions, a tradeoff frontier
between wage and profit emerges. For a certain rate and wage level, we
get a point on the w - r frontier. The slope will be constant for the
fixed proportion of labor and capital, yielding a straight line. Many
such relationships exist for various capital goods, yielding many
negatively sloped straight lines in the w-r plane.
If we parametize the coordinates of these points to time, then we
will find that the more roundabout a production process is, the steeper
will be its w - r frontier. This is because one process will be used at
very high interest or profit rate in preference to another. As the
interest rate is lowered, society will consider using one process rather
than the other. This way an envelope of all the straight lines will be
formed, representing a piece-wise linear factor-price frontier.
Samuelson wants to demonstrate that even in the "...
discrete-activity fixed-coefficient model of heterogeneous physical
capital goods, the factor price (wage and interest rate) can still be
given various long-run marginalism (i.e., partial derivative)
interpretations" (Ibid., 322). Garegnani (1970, 412) has shown that
if we make the parameters of the A) and B) defined for an interval in
which the value of the functions are positive, then the curves will have
a 'smooth' envelope enclosing them. This continuous feature
makes good comparison for a smooth frontier derived from the
Clark-Ramsey model.
Samuelson then used the Clark-Ramsey homogenous capital model to
approximate the w - r of the discrete heterogeneous capital model as
close as we like. Let output depend on labor and capital: Q = F(L, J).
If the function is homogenous, we can factor out an input, yielding: Q =
LF(I, J/L). In equilibrium, w = [partial derivative]Q/[partial
derivative]L, and r = [partial derivative]Q/[partial derivative]J.
Taking their derivatives, and forming the ratio yields: dw/dr = -(J/L),
the slope of the frontier. The heterogeneous discrete capital case for
deriving w - r can be made arbitrary close to approximate the homogenous
smooth capital case of deriving w - r. In his 1966 article, "A
Summing Up," Samuelson (CW, V. 3, 1972, 236) wrote "the fact
of possible reswitching teaches us to suspect the simplest neoclassical
parables." Reswitching is a situation where one technique is
feasible at two different levels of the rate of interest. It can occur
if two frontiers intersect. Both Samuelson (CW, V. 4, 136) and Pasinetti
(2006, 151-152) point to Pierro Sraffa's work as fundamental to the
origin of the reswitching debate. According to Pasinetti, the basic
conclusion of the debate ends with Samuelson's admission that
reswitching is possible.
Trade Theory
During his lifetime, Samuelson had made major contributions to
trade theory. He put the production possibility and indifference curves
to work in a general equilibrium framework. He kept that framework in
focus through his works on trade, but had integrated his discovery of
preference theory into the framework. He not only brought trade theory
under the general equilibrium (GE) framework, but had reversed the
traditional approach to trade theory. The reversal worked from autarky to trade (Krugman, 1995, 1245).
Samuelson's scientific approach to trade theory started with a
hypothesis elaborating gains from trade in 1938. This was followed by an
attempt to use numbers to validate and find possible counter examples in
his 1939 paper, a problem with the prediction of the model in his
Stolper-Samuelson approach in 1941, and a proof of the propositions in
the 1940s.
In his 1938 paper (Samuelson, 1966, V. 2, Item 60) he assumed given
taste and technology, one person or one country model, two goods, (x,
y), and two productive services, (a, b). Given a, b, y, one can find the
maximum amount of x that is produced. Given a, b, and x, the maximum
amount of y that is produced can be estimated. The general
representation is: [phi])(x, y, a, b) = 0. The Production Possibility
Curve can be derived by setting values for a and b, then solving for y =
f(x). To get the indifference curve, assign values for x and y and solve
for b = f(a). The equilibrium condition for each country under autarky
occurs at the tangency of these curves for their respective countries.
For gains from trade to take place in this model, a person or a country
can perform with less productive services (a or b) in trade, foregoing
one commodity for another to attain a higher indifference curve, or one
can gain by moving to a higher position on its preference scale at the
expense of the other. The argument for gains from trade is inconclusive
because we need a welfare utility function to measure gains or losses.
Samuelson (1966, V. 2, 775) concluded that "it is demonstrable that
free trade (pure competition) leads to an equilibrium in which each
country is better off than in the absence of trade.... Nevertheless,
this does not prove that each country is better off than under any other
kind of trade; indeed, if all others are free trading, it always pays a
single country not to trade freely."
The objective in his 1939 paper was to refine the conclusion of the
1938 paper to show that "... free trade or some trade is to be
preferred to no trade at all" (Ibid., 781). The theorem
investigated was stated as follows:
Samuelson Theorem I. (1939): "the introduction of outside
(relative) prices differing from those which would be established in our
economy in isolation will result in some trade, and as a result every
individual will be better off than he would be at the prices which
prevailed in the isolated state" (Samuelson, 1966, V. 2, 786
[Italics original]).
Samuelson tries to find counterexamples for this theorem. He
pondered whether there are any numbers for which the theorem is true.
Using numbers for prices, p, and quantities, q, Samuelson examines three
commodities and two factors prices, w, and factor quantities, a, by
creating four scenarios or cases. The cases were used to validate the
hypothesis that
[summation]p'x' - [summation]w'a' [greater than
or equal to] [summation]p'[bar.x] - [summation]w'a (1)
s.t. [summation]px = [summation]p[bar.x] (2)
where the prime indicates preassigned prices and quantities, and
the bar indicates optimal values. The summation runs over n commodities
and s factors. The "subject to" condition of equation 2
requires that exports must equal import (Ibid., 784).
With his 1938 and 1939 papers, Samuelson was committed to the free
trade doctrine. He even announced that proofs were forthcoming. In those
regards, his Review of Economic Studies, 1941 piece with Wolfgang F.
Stolper was a moment of pause. The "... argument seems to have
relevance to the American discussion of protection versus free trade ...
labor is the relatively scarce factor in the American economy, it would
appear that trade would necessarily lower the relative position of the
laboring class as compared to owners of other factors of
production" (Ibid., 832). The Stolper-Samuelson Model assumes there
exists perfect competition between two countries, I and II, where two
homogenous goods, wheat (A) and watches (B), have relative prices,
[P.sub.a]/[P.sub.b]. There also exist two fixed factors, Labor (L) and
Capital (C), assuming full employment with perfect factor mobility and
the same production functions (Ibid., 835). Four additional assumptions
(two relating to the HO model and two for case studies) are
incorporated.
a) Capital is abundant and labor is scarce,
b) Capital is more important in the production of wheat (A) than in
the production of watches (B), and
1) Capital is relatively more important in wheat (A) as the wage
good.
2) Capital is relatively more important in watches (B) as the wage
good (Ibid., 838).
The equations provided are:
[L.sub.a] + [L.sub.b] = L (1)
[C.sub.a] + [C.sub.b] = C (2)
A = A([L.sub.a], [C.sub.a]) (3)
B = B([L.sub.b], [C.sub.b]) (4)
where the subscripts of the factors indicate the factor amount
required to produce wheat (A) or watches (B). The model predicts that
"... the introduction of trade lowers the proportion of capital to
labor in each line and the prohibition of trade, as by a tariff,
necessarily raises the proportion of capital to labor in each
industry" (Ibid., 841). These have the consequence that: (1) trade
will lower the real wage of the scarce factor of production, and (2)
protection will increase the real wage of the scarce factor of
production.
To determine the predictions of the model, a consistent set of
equations needs to be solved for their unknowns. Given the production
functions above, equilibrium conditions require that the factor prices
must equal their marginal productivities. Since we assumed that the
production functions for the two goods are the same, instead of writing
two equations for labor (i.e., a wage rate equation for wheat, and a
wage rate equation for watches), we can write one wage rate equation for
labor, namely w = [P.sub.a][partial derivative]A/[partial
derivative][L.sub.a] = [P.sub.b][partial derivative]A/[partial
derivative][L.sub.b]. A similar reason for capital can also be applied.
Instead of writing two separate equations for the return of capital in
each industry, we can write one equation for the return on capital,
namely r = [P.sub.a][partial derivative]A/[partial derivative][L.sub.a]
= [P.sub.b][partial derivative]A/[partial derivative][L.sub.b]. Along
with the four equations above, we now have eight additional equations
for the production side of the economy. We need equations on the demand
side to close the system to create a solution. We can add at least two
more equations, one representing the demand for wheat and the other
representing the demand for watches. With ten equations at hand, one is
redundant according to Walras's law, leaving nine independent
equations to solve for nine variables--two for the quantity of labor in
each industry, two for the quantity of capital used in each industry,
one for the total amount of watches and wheat, the real wage rate, the
real return on capital, and the relative price of the two goods
(Burmeister and Dorbell, 1970. Ch. 4; Takayama, 1972, 47).
Samuelson continued to develop his contributions to trade theory
with papers in 1948, 1949, 1953, and 1967. The purpose of the 1948 paper
was to probe the proof of Ohlin's partial equalization theorem that
"(1) free mobility of commodities in international trade can serve
as a partial substitute for factor mobility and (2) will lead to a
partial equalization of relative (and absolute)factor prices"
(Ibid., 847 [Italics original]). Samuelson enunciated four propositions,
of which the first two are proven, and the latter two are derived. The
two main propositions are: 1) Given partial specialization and each
country producing some of the two goods, factor prices will be
equalized, absolutely and relatively by free trade, and 2) If factor
endowments are not too unequal, commodity mobility will always
substitute perfectly for factor mobility (Ibid., 853).
In his 1949 paper, Samuelson admitted that his 1948 paper argued
that "... free commodity trade will, under specified conditions,
inevitably lead to complete factor-price equalization and appears to be
in need of further amplification" (Ibid., 869). In the 1948 paper
he advanced a relationship between wage/rent to the labor/land ratio
that was tied to two areas, Europe and the U.S. (Ibid., 857). In 1949 he
added a wage/rent to the commodity price ratio, (Ibid., 876) and used a
more integrated model, treating the world itself as a country.
Figure 1 below is an abridged diagram of Samuelson's 1949
paper, representing a generalization of the Stolper-Samuelson theorem where L is labor, T is Land, C is clothing, F represents food, w is the
wage rate, r is rent, and P indicates commodity prices. Clothing is
labor intensive, and food is land intensive.
This 1949 based Figure 1 incorporates Quadrant I of his 1948 paper.
The new diagram in Quadrant II shows the relationship of factor prices
to commodity prices. In the diagram the distance, OM, has a similar
weighted average interpretation as equation (5) below, where the
commodities are clothing and food, and the factors are labor and land
(Samuelson, 1966, 858). Samuelson equates the overall C/L = [bar.k] to a
weighted average of the [C.sub.a]/[L.sub.a] = [k.sub.a] for the wheat
industry, and [C.sub.b]/[L.sub.b] = [k.sub.b] for the watch industry.
The weights are the labor share for the wheat and watch industry, i.e.,
[L.sub.a]/([L.sub.a] + [L.sub.a]) == [[lambda].sub.a],
[L.sub.b]/([L.sub.b] + [L.sub.b]) == [[lambda].sub.b], respectively. We
therefore have
[[lambda].sub.a][k.sub.a] + [[lambda].sub.b][k.sub.b] = [bar.k] (5)
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
The distance OM is a new expression for equation (5) involving the
following terms:
OM = total labor/total land = (food land/total land x food
labor/food land) + (clothing land/total land x clothing labor/clothing
land) (5')
Figure 1 indicates that OM's range is between M' and
M". In between those points, both commodities, food and clothing,
will be produced, marking the case of incomplete specialization. Outside
of that range, only one commodity will be produced in each country
implying complete specialization.
The QQ line in Figure 1 represents a situation where the wage/rent
ratio is the same for each industry. This underscores that the factor
proportion will have to be the same in both industries. If the factor
price ratios were not equal, it would be necessary to draw two such
lines, say QQ and Q'Q' not shown, which would represent
different factor price ratios and different factor proportions. The
different factor mix will result in different marginal productivities,
which, in equilibrium, will yield different factor prices. With equal
factor prices, however, there will be equal factor proportions in the
first quadrant, corresponding to a unique commodity price ratio in the
second quadrant. Samuelson summarized his 1949 paper with the finding
that "within any country." (a) an increase in the ratio of
wages to rents will cause a defined decrease in the proportion of labor
to land in both industries; (b) to each determinate state of factor
proportion in the two industries there will correspond one, and only
one, commodity price ratio and a unique configuration of wages and rent;
and (c) the change in wage/rents factor proportions incident to an
increase in wage must be followed by a one-directional increase in
clothing prices relative to food prices (Samuelson, V. 2, 1966, 875
[Italics original]).
The rest of the 1949 paper lays out the mathematics behind Figure
1. Food and clothing are made homogenous functions of the inputs labor
and land, namely F = [T.sub.f]f([L.sub.f]/[T.sub.f]) and C =
[T.sub.c]c([L.sub.c]/[T.sub.c]) respectively. Partial derivatives for
the marginal physical products for (1) labor in food, (2) land in food,
(3) labor in clothing, and (4) land in clothing are taken. These
marginal productivities are converted into values by multiplying them by
their respective prices. The values of labor in food and clothing
industries are equated to form one equation. The values of land in both
industries are then equated to form a second equation. We now have two
equations with three variables. From Figure 1, the variables are
[L.sub.c]/[T.sub.c], [L.sub.f]/[T.sub.f], and [P.sub.f]/[P.sub.c]. Given
prices, it is now possible to solve for the other two variables.
To solve the 2 x 2 matrix described above, Samuelson looked for a
condition on the determinants to guarantee a solution. The condition is
that the determinant of the Jacobian matrix must not vanish.
Technically, the Jacobian matrix is derived from a set of differentiable
functions. Given a set of equations: [y.sub.1] = 5[x.sub.2] and
[y.sub.2] = [x.sub.1][x.sub.2], the determinant of the Jacobian matrix
can be written as:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (6)
If the determinant is zero, then the two equations are dependent,
and no solution exists for the system. If the determinant is not equal
to zero, then the equations are independent, meaning that it is possible
to solve for the unknown variables.
For Samuelson's 2 x 2 case, the determinant is derived from
the commodity price ratio, the second derivatives of the two homogenous
production functions, and the differences in factor intensities. The
following equation shows the Jacobian matrix and its determinant for the
Samuelson's 2 x 2 case:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (6')
In equation (6), the f" and c" are the second derivatives
of the food and clothing production functions, respectively, they are
also negative because the production functions exhibit diminishing
returns. Prices and quantities are positive, and clothing is more labor
intensive, making the square bracket items positive. Because the
Jacobian determinant did not vanish, Samuelson therefore concluded that
"the equilibrium is unique" (Ibid., 880).
In his 1953 article, however, Samuelson recognized A. Turing for
informing him that the equilibrium condition is not true globally or
"in the large" (Ibid., 909). Global conditions are more
complicated than local conditions because local conditions deal with the
value of a function in the neighborhood of a point, whereas global
conditions deal with the behavior of a function over the domain (i.e. an
interval). For instance, between two points, b > a on the x-axis, a
function can rise or fall many times with varying amplitudes. Locally,
many maximums and minimums may exist in the interval. Globally, over the
whole interval, b - a, only one highest peak or one lowest trough is
likely to exist (Frisch, 1965, 4).
In the 1953 article, Samuelson began to address more general cases
beyond the 2 x 2 trade model. This meant that he had to look for global
conditions for a unique solution of relationships between commodity and
factor prices. He began by relating these prices with equations of the
following form:
[P.sub.i] = [A.sub.i]([w.sub.1] .... [w.sub.r]) and [[partial
derivative][p.sub.i]/[partial derivative][w.sub.j]] = [[a.sub.ij]] (7)
Where p is the commodity price with i = 1 ... n, w is the factor
price with j = 1 ... r, and the coefficient, [a.sub.ij], represents the
required amount of input, j, to produce a unit of the good, i (Ibid.,
889-890).
Samuelson considered three cases in interpreting equation (7). Case
(i): Equal goods and factors (n = r). This case deals with the situation
where the number of factors and goods are equal, (the n x n case). The
conclusion is that "... if two countries have the same production
functions, and if they do produce in common as many different goods as
there are factors, and if the goods differ in their "factor
intensities," and if there are no barriers to trade to produce
commodity price differentials, then the absolute returns of every factor
must be fully equalized" (Ibid., 893).
Case (ii): More Goods than Factors (n > r): In this case, the
number of factors is less than the number of goods, resulting in more
commodity equations than factors to be determined. This may be called an
over determined system. Samuelson argued that if prices are arbitrarily
fixed, then certain industries will shut down, reducing Case (ii) to
Case (i). If the market determines prices, however, r factor prices will
adjust to the market price, and the (n-r) prices will require factor
endowments to be determined.
Case (ii) can be looked at from the point of view of the
least-square problems in regression analysis where the number of
observations is greater than the coefficients to be determined. In such
a case, the best solution can be determined. As in this statistical
over-determined system, we project the observation onto a line, and
similarly we can imagine projecting the factor prices space into the
commodity price space. We can think of the price space as the four walls
of a room, and the factor space as just one wall. The projection is
therefore a projection of the w-space to a subspace of the p-space. This
projection restricts the commodity space from its (n-r) dimension, to be
compatible with the r-dimension of the factor space.
Case (iii): More Factors than Goods (n < r): This is an
under-determined system characterized by less equations than unknowns to
be solved. Samuelson proposed the adding of an equation for endowments
to enable a solution.
Solution for ease (i) where the number of commodity and goods
prices are the same Essentially, equation (7) is a mapping between
commodity prices and factor prices, namely:
f : p [right arrow] w or [p.sub.i] = [f.sub.i](w) (8)
If [J.sub.f](w) = [partial derivative][f.sub.i](w)/[partial
derivative][w.sub.j], then we can find w = [f.sup.-1.sub.j] p for j = 1
... n (McKenzie, 1967, 272).
For n = r = 2, the global association between wages and prices were
kept in alignment by their factor intensity. For instance, we could
argue that a rise in the price of a good that was produced by a
labor-intensive technique will lead to an increase in the price of labor
to produce that good. The non-vanishing of the Jacobian determinant
discussed in equation (7) satisfied that factor intensity condition. In
general, Alan Turing pointed out to Samuelson that the determinant of
the Jacobian may not vanish. The reason for non-vanishing Jacobian
determinants in the large includes the occurrence of factor-intensity
reversal. But as Ivor Pearce put it, "A 3 x 3 determinant can
easily be zero for a great many reasons totally unconnected with factor
intensities" (Pearce, 1979, 496).
In 1953, Samuelson refocused his attention on the Jacobian
determinant of the [a.sub.ij] of equation (7) to satisfy the inverse
requirements of equation (8). Samuelson wrote: "Fortunately, the
economics of the situation was clearer than my mathematical analysis;
because all the elements of the Jacobian represented inputs or a'
s, they were essentially one-signed; and this condition combined with
the non-vanishing determinant, turns out to be sufficient to guarantee
uniqueness in the large" (Samuelson, 1966, V. 2, 903). He proceeded
to give sufficient conditions for a unique solution for the global case.
He first renumbered the p' s and w' s in the differentiable
equation (7), such that the successive principal minor of the partial
derivatives are non-vanishing for all w' s (Ibid., 903). To refresh
the terminology, given an element of a matrix, a minor is a matrix form
by deleting the row and column that is associated with the given element
(Strand, 1988, 226). Let A be an m x n matrix, where i = 1 ,..., m and j
= 1,..., n. If i = j, [A.sub.ij] is called a principal minor. These
minors always involve the successive members on the principal diagonal,
which is the diagonal running from the northeast to the southwest.
Equation (9) below lists all the principal minors for the 2 x 2 case.
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (9)
According to Kenneth Arrow and Frank Hahn (1971, 242),
Samuelson's 1953 proposition "... paid insufficient attention
to the domain of the mappings" between the p' s and w' s
of equation (7). Gale and Nikaido (1965, 82), provided a counter example
to illustrate this point. Given a mapping by the equations f(x, y) =
[e.sup.2x] - [y.sup.2] + 3, and g(x, y) = 4[e.sup.2x,] y - [y.sup.3],
then [D.sub.1] = 2[e.sup.2x], and [D.sub.2] = 2[e.sup.2x] (4[e.sup.2x] +
5[y.sup.2]) (which are both positive). But for the domain points (0,2)
and (0,-2) the functions are mapped to the origin which is zero.
Gale and Nikaido (Ibid., 681) provided the domain element by
arguing that "... if all principal submatrices of the Jacobian
matrix have positive determinants, the mapping is univalent in any
rectangular region." Formally speaking, the Gale-Nikaido theorem
can be stated as follows:
Given a map F : [R.sup.n] [right arrow] [R.sup.n]. Let the domain
of the map be rectangular, i.e., [omega] = {x [member of] [R.sup.n] :
[p.sub.i] [less than or equal to] x [less than or equal to] [q.sub.i],
(i = 1,2,...,n)}. Let the components of the map in that domain, F(x) =
[f.sub.i](x) be differentiable ([C.sub.1]) (i.e. its total differential exist at each point x of [omega]). Then the mapping F: [omega] [right
arrow] [R.sup.n] is univalent (one-to-one) if the Jacobian matrix, J(x)
has strictly positive principal minors, strictly negative principal
minors, or is positive quasi-definite everywhere in a convex set [omega].
In the Gale-Nakaido Theorem, the Jacobian matrix is called a P -
matrix. Positive quasi-definite means that for each vector, x [not equal
to] 0 and x' Ax > 0. Univalence of the mapping means that for
each element in the domain there can be only one element (image) in the
range. As a practical matter, one can test this concept in the plane by
using a vertical line on the graph to see if the line cuts the graph at
only one point. But a function defined globally may not refer to a point
on a graph such as when the graph is sketched, or find its extrema over
the real numbers, or when we look for undefined points for each element
in the domain.
The 1965 Samuelson postscript proceeds to accommodate Gale and
Nikaido's findings through "... a naturally ordered set of
principal minors ... everywhere in the Euclidean n-space, bordered by
two positive numbers" (Samuelson, V. 2, 1966, 908). What is new
here is that the sequence of principal minors has determinants that are
bounded away from zero. This condition was earlier foreshadowed by
McKenzie's dominant diagonal (DD) matrix (1960, 49). He argued that
"... an n x n matrix A is said to have a dominant diagonal if
[absolute value of [a.sub.ij]] > [[summation].sub.i [not equal to] j]
[absolute value of [a.sub.ij]] for each j." In simple terms, the DD
condition states that in each row of the [a.sub.ij] matrix, the main
diagonal element must be greater than the sum of the other row elements
when the comparison is in absolute value terms. A dominant diagonal
"... means that each good can be identified with a factor that is
uniquely important in the production of that good" (Ibid., 54).
Gale and Nikaido provided a P-matrix that includes the DD matrix as a
special case. "If a matrix with a dominant diagonal has positive
diagonal entries, then it is a P-matrix (Gale and Nikaido, 1965, 84).
One problem with the Gale Nikaido theorem is that it is "over
sufficient". According to Pearce, "... for each condition of a
rectilinear region satisfying the Gale-Nikaido condition, and hence
possessing an inverse, it is possible to construct an infinity of
mapping not satisfying the conditions which nevertheless posses an
inverse also" (Pearce, 1970, 525). Andreu Mas-Collel has also given
two propositions in the direction of weakening the strong assumptions on
the univalence condition of the Gale-Nikaido theorem. His two
propositions are considered as a generalization of the Gale-Nikaido
theorem discussed above. The two propositions are listed as follows:
Proposition I (Samuelson-Nikaido-Mas-Collel): The restriction on
the principal minor of the w 0f'(w) is irrelevant. All input share
function, w/[f.sub.i](w) x [partial derivative][f.sup.i](w)/[partial
derivative][w.sup.j], that matters is that the determinant of the
function be uniformly bounded away from zero in order to attain global
univalence within the strictly positive orthant, [[R.sup.l].sub.++].
Proposition II (Gale-Nikaido-Mas-Collel): The condition of the cost
function within the [R.sup.l.sub.+] domain can be weakened, based on the
general [C.sup.1] function on compact polyhedral (MasCollell, 1979b,
324).
Following his 1965 postscript, Samuelson answered a question raised
by Jagdish Bhagwati regarding the difference between the rental rate on
capital and the interest rate, which is a capitalization of the rental
rate on capital. Working with the equation that GNP = NNP +
Depreciation, he rewrote the price-cost equation for each industry
(capital goods, food, and clothing) as [p.sub.i] = [a.sub.i]w +
[b.sub.i]r [p.sub.o] + [m.sub.i] [b.sub.i] [p.sub.0], where the
a's, b's and m's are labor, capital, and depreciation
coefficients respectively, and [p.sub.0] is the price of capital goods.
Samuelson then proceeded to apply the method of his modified
Gale-Nikaido ideas in his postscript to discuss the solution (Samuelson,
1966, V. 2, 912-915). The result indicated that the rate of interest is
inversely related, and the real wage directly related to the wage-rental
ratio (Ibid., 916).
In 1967, Samuelson summarized the factor-price equalization
literature. He then pursued the development of the use of factor
endowments to bring about a solution. The model was now convened to a
maximization problem using Lagrange multipliers (Samuelson, V. 3, 1972,
351). The Hessian matrix formed for the partials of the Lagrangian
equations does not satisfy the Gale-Nikaido conditions. "The fact
that its principal minors formed from crossing out any r < [n.sup.2]
of the first [n.sup.2] rows and columns are of the sign needed for the
maximum suffices, I believe, to assure univalence of the equation
set" (Ibid.,).
Regarding the factor price equalization theorem, John Hicks considered two sets of equations for two countries, namely, ar + bw =
ar'+ bw', and cr + dw = cr' +dw'.
The prime is used to distinguish the equation for the other
country. A simultaneous solution of both equations yields r' - r =
a/b (w - w') = d/c(w - w'), where the ratios indicate
capital-intensities. Since capital-intensities can differ, they can only
differ if (w - w') is the same, yielding, r = r' (Hicks, 1983,
226). Hicks concluded that "... the analysis which emerges does not
sound to be so unrealistic. It sounds to me like ringing tree"
(Ibid., 233).
According to Findlay (1995, 7), although the Factor-price model is
also credited to Abba Lerner, it was Samuelson who first introduced it
to the economic profession. Findlay quoted a rare citation of Samuelson,
pointing out another of Samuelson's novel contribution in regards
to the H-O model as well. "Already in 1924 Ohlin has melded
Heckscher and Walras. But neither then, nor in 1933 and 1967, did Ohlin
descend from full generality to strong and manageable cases--such as two
factors of production and two or more goods. What a pity. Not only did
Ohlin leave to my generation these easy pickings, but in addition he
would for the first time have really understood his own system had he
played with graphable versions" (Ibid., 7).
Microeconomics
Samuelson's major contribution to microeconomics is in the
area of consumer choice. Traditional theory predicts a consumer choice
from assumptions about their tastes and preferences. Samuelson began
with the assumption of choice (i.e., let the consumer select one item
over another). This has become the theory of "revealed
preference" (Varian, 2006, 99). Preferences are deduced for the
choices consumers make in the market place, based on commodity prices
and consumer's income, thereby moving the analysis from the realm
of the unobservable taste and preference to the world of observable
choices.
In his original paper, Samuelson gave three postulates: (1) A
single-value function on prices and income, subject to a budget
constraint; (2) Homogeneity of order zero so as to make consumer
behavior independent of the units of measurement of prices. (Given
vectors of two goods, [PSI] and [PSI]', with their respective price
vectors, p and p', forming their inner product yields: [[PSI]p],
and [[PSI]'p'] [[PSI]'p']), and (3) "if this
cost [[PSI]'p] is less than or equal to the actual expenditures in
the first period when the first batch of goods [[psi]p] was actually
bought, then it means that the individual could have purchased the
second batch of goods with the price and income of the first situation,
but did not choose to do so. That is, the first batch ([psi]) was
selected instead of ([psi]')" (Samuelson, 1966, V. 2, 7).
In making choices, Samuelson assumed consumers need to be
consistent. "If an individual selects batch one over batch two, he
does not at the same time select two over one" (Ibid.,). In a
latter note, Samuelson integrates the first two propositions with the
third concluding that "postulates 1 and 2 are already implied in
postulate 3, and hence may be omitted" (Ibid., 13).
With those assumptions, Samuelson pronounced that "... even
within the framework of the ordinary utility- and indifference- curve
assumptions, it is believed to be possible to derive already known
theorems quickly, and also to suggest new sets of conditions.
Furthermore ... the transitions from individual to market demand
functions are considerably expedited" (Ibid., 23). But the revealed
preference theory matured into an even more powerful rival research
paradigm.
In 1950, Samuelson wrote "I suddenly realized that we could
dispense with almost all notions of utility; starting from a few logical
axioms of demand consistency; I could derive the whole of the valid
utility analysis as corollaries" (Samuelson, 1966, V. 1, 90). He
proceeded to make the following axioms:
* "Weak Axiom: If, at the price and income of situation A you
could have bought the goods actually bought at a different point B and
if you actually chose not to, then A is defined to be 'revealed to
be better than' B. The basic postulate is that B is never to reveal
itself to be also 'better than' A" (Samuelson, 1966, V.
1, 90).
* "Strong Axiom: If A reveals itself to be 'better
than' B, and if B reveals itself to be 'better than' C,
and if C reveals itself to be 'better than' D, etc...., then I
extend the definition of 'revealed preference' and say that A
can be defined to be 'revealed to be better than' Z, the last
in the chain. In such cases it is postulated that Z must never also be
revealed to be better than A" (Ibid.,).
In 1953, Samuelson then elevated the revealed preference theory to
the empirical domain: "... consumption theory does definitely have
some refutable empirical implications", or we can "score the
theory of revealed preference" (Ibid., 106). Samuelson required a
benchmark to allow refutation/scoring, for which he postulated this
fundamental theorem: "Any good (simple or composite) that is known
always to increase in demand when money income alone rises must
definitely shrink in demand when its price alone rises" (Ibid.,
107). He then proceeded "to show that within the framework of the
narrowest version of revealed preference the important fundamental
theorem, stated above, can be directly demonstrated (a) in commonsense
words, (b) in geometrical argument and (c) by general analytic
proof" (Ibid., 108).
Hildenbrand, a modern mathematical economist, appraised the
revealed preference theory as follows: "Instead of deriving demand
in a given wealth-price situation from the preferences, considered as
the primitive concept, one can take the demand function (correspondence)
directly as the primitive concept. If the demand function f reveals a
certain 'consistency' of choices ... one can show that there
exists a preference relation ... which will give rise to the demand
function f" (Hildenbrand, 1974, 95).
Conclusions
Many attempts to look at Samuelson's contribution to economics
have only been able to examine his findings. Writers pick the fruits of
his erudition but ignore the tree that generated them. Elsewhere, we
have looked at various ways to know Samuelson by looking at his
character. We have also looked at him as a Wunderkind, and what of his
views will survive in the 21st century. Here, we went behind his major
topical contributions to feel the depth of his thoughts, particularly in
the areas of capital and trade, and to use a Newtonian expression,
leaving the sea of his discovery for others to investigate.
This memoriam took a peek at some trunks of the tree, not going off
on its many branches. We looked at trade because Samuelson thought that
it is the one theory that is true but cannot be proved. We looked at
capital theory because it has engaged some of the best minds in
economics for the last half a century on both sides of the Atlantic.
Research into trade and capital theory is still ongoing, leaving room
for more research and debate. No one will doubt that from the touch of
Samuelson's hand, economics has become highly transparent and
knowledge elevated, more so in some areas than in others.
References
Arrow, Kenneth J., and F. H. Hahn, General Competitive Analysis,
(San Francisco, CA: Holden-Day, 1971).
Bhagwati, Jagdish, Essays in International Economic Theory: The
Theory of Commercial Policy, edited by Robert C. Freenstra, Vol. I,
(Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1983).
Burmeister, E., and A. R. Dorbell, Mathematical Theories of
Economic Growth, (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1970), Chapter 4.
Dorfman, Robert, Paul A. Samuelson and Robert M. Solow, Linear
Programming and Economic Analysis, (New York: Dover Publication, Inc.,
1958).
Ferguson, C. E., "Transformation Curve in Production Theory: A
Pedagogical Note," Southern Economic Journal, Vol. 29, No. 2 (Oct.,
1962), 96-102.
Ferguson, C. E., The Neoclassical Theory of Production and
Distribution, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1975).
Findlay, Ronald, Factor Proportions, Trade, and Growth, (Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press, 1995).
Frisch, Ragnar, Maxima and Minima: Theory and Economic
Applications, in collaboration with A. Nataf, (Chicago, Ill.: Rand
McNally and Company, 1966).
Gale, David and Hukukane Nikaido, "The Jacobian Matrix and
Global Univalence of Mappings," Mathematische Annalen, 1965, 68-80,
reprinted in Peter Newman, edited, Readings in Mathematical Economics,
(Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1968), 81-93.
Garegnani, P., "Heterogeneous Capital, the Production function
and the Theory of Distribution," Review of Economic' Studies,
Vol. 37, 1970, pp. 407-436.
Hayek, F. A., Collected Works, Vol. 4, (University of Chicago
Press, 1992).
Hicks, John, Collected Essays on Economic Theory: Classics and
Moderns, Vol. III, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983).
Hildenbrand, Werner, Core and Equilibria of A Large Economy,
(Princeton University Press, 1974).
Krugman, Paul, "Increasing Returns, Imperfect Competition and
The Positive Theory of International Trade," in Handbook of
International Economics: Vol. 3. Edited by Gene M. Grossman and Kenneth
Rogoff, (North Holland: Elsevier, 1995), 1243-1277.
Lutz, F. A, "The Essentials of Capital Theory," in
Friedrich Lutz and D. C. Hague, edited, The Theory of Capital, (New
York: Macmillan 1961), 3-17.
Marshall, Alfred, The Correspondence of Alfred Marshall: Vol.
Three: Towards the Close, 1903-1924, Edited by John K. Whitaker, (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
Mas-Collel, Andreu, The Theory of General Economic Equilibrium: A
Differentiable Approach, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
Mas-Collel, Andreu, "Homeomorphism of Compact, Convex Sets and
the Jacobian Matrix," Siam Journal of Math. Anal., Vol. 10, No. 6,
November 1979a, 1105-1109.
Mas-Collel, Andreu, "Two Propositions on the Global Univalence
of Systems of Cost Functions", in General Equilibrium Growth and
Trade, J. Green and J. Scheinkman, editors, (New York: Academic Press,
1979b), 323-331.
McKenzie, "Matrices with Dominant Diagonals and Economic
Theory," in Kenneth J. Arrow, Samuel Karlin, and Patrick Suppes,
edited, Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, (Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 1960), 47-62.
McKenzie, Lionel W., "The Inversion of Cost Functions: A
Counter-Example," International Economic Review, Vol. 8, No. 3
(Oct., 1967), 271-278.
Morishima, Michio, Equilibrium, Stability and Growth: A
Multi-Sectoral Analysis, (Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press, Inc.,
1964).
Lerner, Abba, "Factor Prices and International Trade," in
Abba P. Lerner, Essays in Economic" Analysis, (London: Macmillan,
1953, 67-84).
Mas-Colell, A. 1979. "Two propositions on the global
univalence of systems of cost functions" in General Equilibrium,
Growth, and Trade, J. Green and J. Scheinkman, editors, (New York:
Academic Press, 1979), 323-311.
Nell, E. J., "Theories of Growth and Theories of Value,"
Economic Development and Cultural Change, Vol. 16, 1967, 15-26.
Pasinetti, Luigi L., "Paul Samuelson and Piero Sraffa-Two
Prodigious Minds at the Opposite Poles," in Michael Szenberg, Lall
Ramrattan, and Aron A. Gottesman, editor, Samuelsonian Economics and the
Twenty-First Century, (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006) 146-164.
Pearce, I. F., International Trade: A Survey of Principles and
Problems of the International Economy, (New York: W. W. Norton and
Company, 1970).
Ramsey, F. P., "A Mathematical Theory of Saving," The
Economic" Journal, Vol. 38, No. 152 (Dec., 1928), 543-559.
Robinson, Joan, "The Measure of Capital: The End of the
Controversy," The Economic Journal, Vol. 81, No. 323 (Sep., 1971),
597-602.
Robinson, Joan, "Capital Theory up to Date," The Canadian
Journal of Economics, Vol. 3, No. 2 (May, 1970), 309-317.
Samuelson Paul A. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
Samuelson, edited by Joseph E. Stiglitz. Vols. 1 and 2, (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1966).
Samuelson Paul A. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
Samuelson, edited by Robert C. Merton. Vol. 3, (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1986).
Samuelson Paul A. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
Samuelson, edited by H. Nagatani and K. Cowley. Vol. 4, (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1986).
Samuelson Paul A. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
Samuelson, edited by Kate Crowley. Vol. 5, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1986).
Samuelson Paul A. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Harvard
Economic Studies, Vol. 80 (1947), References are to the Seventh Reprint,
(New York: Atheneum, 1974).
Samuelson Paul A. "My Life Philosophy: Policy Credos and
Working Ways." In Eminent Economists, edited by Michael Szenberg,
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
Samuelson. Paul A., Economics, (New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company,
1980).
Samuelson, Paul A., and William D. Nordhaus. Economics. 15th ed.,
(New York: McGraw Hill, 1995).
Solow, Robert, "Overlapping-Generation" in Michael
Szenberg, Lall Ramrattan, and Aron A. Gottesman, edited, Samuelsonian
Economics and the Twenty-First Century, (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2006) 35-41.
Szenberg, Michael, Lall Ramrattan and Aron A. Gottesman,
Samuelsonian Economics and the Twenty-First Century, edited, (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2006a).
Szenberg, Michael and Lall Ramrattan, Paul A. Samuelson, Dictionary
of American Economists, (Devon: Thoemmes Press, 2006b).
Szenberg, Michael, Aron Gottesman, and Lall Ramrattan, On Being an
Economist, (New York: Jorge Pinto Books, New York, 2005).
Szenberg, Michael, Lall Ramrattan and Aron Gottesman, "Ten
Ways to Know Paul Samuelson, in Economics of Education Review, (Spring
2006).
Szenberg, Michael, Lall Ramrattan and Aron Gottesman, "Paul A.
Samuelson: Philosopher and Theorist," International Journal of
Social Economics", Vol. 32, No. 4, 2005, 325-338.
Takayama, Akira, International Trade: An Approach to the Theory,
(New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1972).
Varian, Hal R. "Revealed Preference", in Michael
Szenberg, Lall Ramrattan, and Aron A. Gottesman, edited, Samuelsonian
Economics and the Twenty-First Century, (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2006).
Walras, Leon, Elements of Pure Economics, trans. William 1 Jaffe,
(New York: Augustus M. Kelley, Reprints, 1926 [1969]).
Wicksell, Knut, Lectures on Political Economy, Vol. I, (London:
George Routledge, 1911 [1934]).
Wicksell, Knut, "Letter to Alfred Marshall, June 1,
1905," in The Correspondence of Alfred Marshall, Volume Three:
Towards the Close, 1903-1924, edited by John K. Whitaker, (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), 102.
Lall Ramrattan, University of California, Berkeley Extension
Michael Szenberg, Corresponding author: Lubin School of Business,
Pace University, mszenberg@pace.edu