Economic theory and the interpretation of GATT/WTO.
Bagwell, Kyle ; Staiger, Robert W.
1. Introduction
Over the post-war period, the General Agreement on Tariffs and
Trade (GATT) has sponsored eight rounds of trade-policy negotiations.
The most recent round of negotiations, which was completed in 1994,
resulted in the creation of the World Trade Organization (WTO). The WTO
includes the text of GATT, but it also goes further and embodies a set
of agreements that build on and extend GATT principles to new areas. The
central role played in the world economy by GATT/WTO is widely accepted.
Indeed, through the eight rounds of GATT negotiations, the average ad
valorem tariff on industrial goods has fallen from over 40% to below 4%.
Over this period, GATT/WTO membership has also grown in number from 23
to now over 140 countries.
Given the significant influence of GATT/WTO on the world economy,
it is of special importance to assess the progress that economists have
made in providing a theoretical interpretation of GATT/WTO. This is the
focus of the present paper. [1] Our discussion proceeds in three broad
steps. First, we consider the theory of trade agreements. We organize
our discussion here around a simple but fundamental question: What is
the problem that a trade agreement might solve? Second, we briefly
describe the history and institutional design of GATT/WTO. Finally, we
draw on the recent theoretical literature and interpret the design of
GATT/WTO. Our discussion examines two key features of GATT/WTO:
reciprocity and enforcement.
The work described here cuts across two fields of Economics. The
first is International Trade. In this field, there is the famous result
that unilateral free trade is optimal, whenever a government maximizes
national income and presides over a small country. For an economist
seeking a theoretical interpretation of GATT/WTO, this result is
initially discouraging. Apparently, in some circumstances, governments
have no reason to pursue reciprocal tariff liberalization through
GATT/WTO negotiations, since each already has the unilateral incentive
to eliminate its own tariff. But in fact this result has important
constructive value. It suggests that a trade agreement might solve a
problem that arises because the negotiating governments (i) have
political motivations and do not maximize national income, or (ii)
preside over large countries.
Of course, there is little doubt that real-world governments have
political motivations. Actual governments are interested not just in the
size of national income but also in its distribution. As a consequence,
the optimal unilateral policy for a government with political
motivations may not be free trade. A positive tariff, for example, may
be the means through which such a government steers surplus toward its
import-competing firms. But it is quite another matter to say that
political considerations constitute a problem that two governments might
solve with a trade agreement. As we explain, in the leading
political-economy models of trade policy, if the negotiating governments
preside over small countries, then the governments can do no better with
a trade agreement than without one. In these models, at least, politics
itself fails to explain the appeal of a trade agreement.
The other possibility is that governments preside over large
countries. What does this mean? In a standard general-equilibrium model
of trade in two goods, a country is said to be large if a change in its
trade policy alters the terms on the world market at which its export
good is traded for its import good. For example, if the government of a
large country were to depart from free trade and select a positive
import tariff, then the import good would become more plentiful on the
world market, and so the world price of this good would drop. The
government has then engineered a terms-of-trade gain for its country: a
unit of its export good can be exchanged on world markets for a greater
volume of its import good. By the same logic, the trading partner then
experiences a terms-of-trade loss. Since a government does not
internalize the terms-of-trade externality that its import tariff
imposes upon its trading partner, the optimal unilateral tariff for a
national-income maximizing government of a large country is positive. If
both governments behave this way and set positive import tariffs, a
Prisoners' Dilemma situation is created. In the Nash equilibrium,
tariffs are too high and trade volumes are too low; hence, a trade
agreement that facilitates a reciprocal reduction in tariffs could be
mutually beneficial.
Governments of large countries thus may gain from a trade
agreement. This insight is hardly new. The terms-of-trade theory of
trade agreements was identified by Mill (1844) and Torrens (1844), and
Johnson (1953-54) provides a famous and elegant formalization.
Nevertheless, many trade economists have objected to this theory as a
foundation from which to interpret actual trade agreements. One
objection is that this theory leaves out the important political
constraints under which real-world governments labor. A second objection
is simply that real-world governments just don't think this way. It
is difficult, for example, to find any mention of the "terms of
trade" in actual policy disputes. As we show, these objections are
less worrisome than they might initially appear. The terms-of-trade
theory is easily generalized to include political considerations, and it
may be directly interpreted in the context of the market-access language
that trade-policy negotiators use.
This theoretical perspective offers a means by which to interpret
the rules of GATT/WTO. For instance, it suggests that a government may
hesitate to liberalize unilaterally, since it does not want to face the
terms-of-trade loss that such behavior would imply. If the governments
were to liberalize reciprocally, however, then the terms of trade could
be preserved, and the impediment to liberalization thereby would be
removed. An interpretation of reciprocity is thereby facilitated.
Likewise, a government would hesitate to liberalize as part of a
reciprocal negotiation, if it were concerned that its negotiating
partner might later "cheat" and raise its tariff. We argue
that the GATT/WTO enforcement provisions can be interpreted in this
light.
The second field to which this paper contributes is Applied Game
Theory. Within this field, there is a rich theoretical literature that
examines how players that interact repeatedly might construct
self-enforcing agreements, so as to overcome a Prisoners' Dilemma
problem and achieve a more efficient outcome. The theory of collusion among firms, for example, falls into this category. As there are no
GATT/WTO police, agreements between governments achieved through
GATT/WTO negotiations must be self-enforcing. Indeed, the rules of
GATT/WTO may be interpreted as a codification of supergame strategies.
This paper thus also may be of interest to Applied Game Theorists, since
it describes the creation and interprets the design of a successful
self-enforcing agreement.
The paper proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we discuss the theory
of trade agreements. Next, in Section 3, we discuss the history and
design of GATT/WTO. Section 4 contains our interpretation of
GATT/WTO's reciprocity and enforcement features. Concluding
thoughts are offered in Section 5.
2. The Theory of Trade Agreements
A theory of trade agreements must explain the purpose of a trade
agreement. To this end, we first present a standard two-good general
equilibrium model of trade between two countries. Next, we specify a
general family of government preferences. Our representation follows the
political-economy literature and allows that governments are concerned
with the distributional consequences of their trade-policy decisions.
With these ingredients, we then identify and discuss the problem that a
trade agreement can solve.
The General Equilibrium Model
We consider a standard general equilibrium model of trade. There
are two countries, home and foreign, that trade two goods, where these
goods are normal goods in consumption and produced in perfectly
competitive markets under conditions of increasing opportunity costs.
(2) With x (y) denoting the natural import good of the home (foreign)
country, we define p [equivalent to] [p.sub.x]/[p.sub.y] ([p.sup.*]
[equivalent to] [p.sup.*.sub.x]/[p.sup.*.sub.y]) as the local relative
price facing home (foreign) producers and consumers. We denote the home
(foreign) ad valorem import tariff as t ([t.sup.*]), and we assume that
this tariff is not prohibitive. Letting [tau] [equivalent to] (1 + t)
and [[tau].sup.*] [equivalent to] (1 + [t.sup.*]), we then have the
following relationships among prices: p = [tau][p.sup.w] [equivalent to]
p([tau],[p.sup.w]) and [p.sup.*] = [p.sup.w]/[[tau].sup.*] [equivalent
to] [p.sup.*]([[tau].sup.*],[p.sup.w]), where [p.sup.w] [equivalent to]
[p.sup.*.sub.x]/[p.sup.*.sub.y] is the "world" (i.e., untaxed)
relative price. (3) The foreign (domestic) terms of trade is given by
[p.sup.w] (1/[p.sup.w]). We interpret [tau] > 1 ([tau] < 1) as an
import tax (import subsidy) and similarly for [[tau].sup.*]. (4)
How are production and consumption determined? Within a given
country, production is given by the point on the production
possibilities frontier at which the marginal rate of transformation
between x and y is equal to the local relative price. We may thus
represent domestic and foreign production functions as [Q.sub.i] =
[Q.sub.i](p) and [Q.sup.*.sub.i] = [Q.sup.*.sub.i]([p.sup.*]) for I =
{x,y}. Consumption is also influenced by the local relative price, since
this price defines the trade-off faced by consumers and implies the
level and distribution of factor income in the economy. In addition,
consumption is dependent upon tariff revenue R ([R.sup.*]), which is
distributed lump-sum to domestic (foreign) consumers and measured in
units of the local export good at local prices. Therefore, we may
represent domestic and foreign consumption as [D.sub.i] = [D.sub.i](p,R)
and [D.sup.*.sub.i] = [D.sup.*.sub.i]([p.sup.*],[R.sup.*]) for i =
{x,y}. Next, we observe that tariff revenue is implicitly defined by R =
[[D. sub.x](p,R) - [Q.sub.x](p)][p - [p.sup.w]] or R = R(p,[p.sup.w])
for the domestic country and by [R.sup.*] =
[[D.sup.*.sub.y]([p.sup.*],[R.sup.*]) -
[Q.sup.*.sub.y]([p.sup.*])][1/[p.sup.*] - 1/[p.sup.w]] or [R.sup.*] =
[R.sup.*]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]) for the foreign country. Under the
assumption that goods are normal, each country's tariff revenue
increases with its terms of trade. Having now expressed tariff revenue
as a function of local and world prices, we may also express national
consumption as a function of local and world prices:
[C.sub.i](p,[p.sup.w]) [equivalent to] [D.sub.i](p,R(p,[p.sup.w])) and
[C.sup.*.sub.i]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]) [equivalent to]
[D.sup.*.sub.i]([p.sup.*],[R.sup.*]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w])) for I = {x,y}.
We consider next the determination of imports and exports. For the
home country, imports of x and exports of y are respectively defined by
[M.sub.x](],[p.sup.w]) [equivalent to] [C.sub.x](p,[p.sup.w]) -
[Q.sub.x](p) and [E.sub.y](p,[p.sup.w]) [equivalent to] [Q.sub.y](p) -
[C.sub.y](p,[p.sup.w]). Likewise, for the foreign country, we represent
imports of y and exports of x as [M.sup.*.sub.y]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w])
and [E.sup.*.sub.x]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]), respectively. For any prices
home and foreign budget constraints imply that
[p.sup.w][M.sub.x](p,[p.sup.w]) = [E.sub.y](p,[p.sup.w]), and (2.1)
[M.sup.*.sub.y]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]) =
[p.sup.w][E.sup.*.sub.x]([p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]).(2.2)
Making explicit the dependence of the local price upon the tariff
and the world price, we may now determine the equilibrium world price,
[p.sup.w]([tau],[[tau].sup.*]), by the requirement of market-clearing
for good y:
[E.sub.y](p([tau],[p.sup.w]),[p.sup.w]) =
[M.sup.*.sub.y]([p.sup.*]([[tau].sup.*],[p.sup.w]),[p.sup.w]). (2.3)
Market clearing for good x is then implied by (2.1), (2.2) and
(2.3).
We place some modest structure on the equilibrium prices.
Specifically, we assume that the Metzler and Lemer paradoxes are ruled
out, so that dp/d[tau] > 0 > d[p.sup.*]/d[[tau].sup.*] and
[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][tau] < 0 <
[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][[tau].sup.*]. The latter inequalities
ensure that each country is "large," since a country can
improve its terms of trade by increasing its tariff.
In summary, equilibrium values are implied by a given pair of
tariffs in the following manner. First, given the tariffs, the
equilibrium world price is determined by (2.3). Second, the equilibrium
world price and the given tariffs determine the local prices. Third, the
world and local prices imply values for the production, consumption,
import, export and tariff revenue levels.
Government Preferences
In representing government preferences, the traditional approach is
to impose the assumption that governments maximize national income. By
contrast, the political-economy approach emphasizes that governments are
motivated by distributional concerns. Here, we follow Bagwell and
Staiger (1999, forthcoming) and adopt a general representation for
government preferences that (i) allows for both the terms-of-trade
externality and political motivations, and (ii) facilitates the
identification of the respective roles played by the terms-of-trade
externality and political motivations in explaining the purpose of a
trade agreement.
Formally, we represent the objectives of the home and foreign
governments with the general functions W(p,[p.sup.w] and
[W.sup.*],[p.sup.*],[p.sup.w]) respectively. In expressing the welfare
functions in this way, we break with the usual game-theoretic custom,
under which payoffs (welfare values) are expressed directly in terms of
actions (tariffs). Instead, we find it convenient to represent welfare
in terms of the prices that the tariffs induce. As will become clear,
this representation enables us to disentangle the separate roles played
by the terms-of-trade externality and political motivations.
Allowing for a wide range of political motivations, we place no
restrictions on government preferences over local prices. In fact, we
impose only one assumption on the welfare functions (aside from standard
assumptions to ensure that second-order conditions are globally met in
each of the optimization problems considered below). We assume that,
holding its local price fixed, each government achieves higher welfare
when its terms of trade improve:
[W.sub.p.sup.w] < 0 and [W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.w]] > 0 (2.4)
This assumption can be understood using Figure 1. Point A
[equivalent to] ([tau],[[tau].sup.*]) represents an initial tariff pair.
This pair is associated with a domestic iso-local-price locus p(A)
[right arrow] p(A), and an iso-world-price locus, [p.sup.w](A) [right
arrow] [p.sup.w](A). (5) A Point C [equivalent
to]([[tau].sup.1],[[tau].sup.*]) denotes the tariff pair that obtains
following an increase in the home tariff. This pair is associated with a
second set of prices, corresponding to the domestic iso-local-price
locus, p(C) [right arrow] p(C), and the iso-world-price locus,
[p.sup.w](C) [right arrow] [p.sup.w](C). The world price is lower at C
than at A, reflecting an improved terms-of-trade for the domestic
country. A reduction in the world price that maintains the domestic
local price is thus achieved with the movement from A to B. This
movement corresponds to a higher (lower) domestic (foreign) import
tariff. The meaning of condition (2.4) is thus simply that the domestic
government values the int ernational income transfer that is implied by
the movement from A to B.
In both the traditional and the leading political-economy
approaches to trade policy, governments maximize a welfare function of
this form. Important formalizations of the traditional approach are
offered by Dixit (1987), Johnson (1953-54), Kennan and Reizman (1988)
and Mayer (1981). These models proceed under the assumption that the
national welfare of a country improves when it experiences a
terms-of-trade improvement. Within the political-economy literature,
several specific models are entertained. As Mayer (1984) shows, if the
government arises from a representative democracy, then the government
sets its trade policy to promote the interests of the median voter,
whose utility can be represented as a function of this form. Other major
approaches to the political economy of trade policy are explored by
Olson (1965), Caves (1976), Brock and Magee (1978), Feenstra and
Bhagwati (1982), Findlay and Wellisz (1982) and Hillman (1982). As
Baldwin (1987) observes, all of these approaches can also be represented
in this form. Finally, the framework presented here also includes the
lobbying models of Grossman and Helpman (1994, 1995).
Unilateral Trade Policies
In order to determine the problem that a trade agreement might
solve, we must first characterize the unilateral trade policies that
would arise in the absence of a trade agreement. We therefore derive the
home and foreign tariff reaction functions. To this end, we suppose that
each government sets its tariff policy to maximize its welfare, taking
as given the tariff choices of its trading partner. These optimization
problems determine the reaction functions, which are defined implicitly
by
[W.sub.p][dp/d[tau]] +
[W.sub.[p.sup.w]][[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][tau]] = 0 (2.5)
[W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.*]][d[p.sup.*]/d[[tau].sup.*]] +
[W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.w]][[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][T.sup.*]] = 0.
(2.6)
Let [lambda] [equivalent to]
[[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][tau]/[dp/d[tau]] < 0 and
[[lambda].sup.*] [equivalent to]
[[partial][p.sup.w]/[partial][[tau].sup.*]]/ [d[p.sup.*]/d[[tau].sup.*]]
< 0. We may rewrite (2.5) and (2.6) as
[W.sub.p] + [lambda][W.sub.[p.sup.w]] = 0, (2.7)
[W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.*]] + [[lambda].sup.*][W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.w]] =
0. (2.8)
As these expressions make clear, the best-response tariff of each
government reflects the combined effect on welfare of the induced local
and world price movements.
Figure 1 offers further insight. Beginning at the initial tariff
pair A [equivalent to] ([tau],[[tau].sup.*]), suppose that the domestic
government unilaterally increases its tariff and thus induces the new
pair C [equivalent to] ([tau],[[tau].sup.*]). As (2.7) suggests, we can
disentangle the overall movement from A to C into separate movements in
the local and world prices. The movement from A to B isolates the change
in the world price, and the corresponding welfare effect for the
domestic government is captured in (2.7) with the term
[lambda][W.sub.[p.sup.w]]. This term is strictly positive by (2.4). The
movement from B to C isolates the induced increase in the local price,
holding fixed the world price, and the associated change in the domestic
government's welfare is represented in (2.7) with the term
[W.sub.p.sup.*].
The welfare implications of the local-price movement from B to C
are domestic in nature: they reflect the balance for the domestic
government between the costs of the associated economic distortions and
the benefits of any induced political support. By contrast, the welfare
implications of the world-price movement from A to B are international
in kind: they reflect the benefits to the domestic government of
shifting the costs of its policy onto the foreign government. The cost
shifting occurs, since this movement corresponds to an improvement
(deterioration) in the domestic (foreign) country's terms of trade.
Due to this terms-of-trade externality, if the domestic government seeks
to implement a local price corresponding to the isolocal-price locus
p(C) [right arrow] p(C), then a unilateral increase in the domestic
import tariff serves to shift a portion of the costs of this outcome
onto the foreign government.
In a Nash equilibrium, both governments are on their reaction
curves. A Nash equilibrium tariff pair, ([[tau].sup.N],[[tau].sup.*N]),
thus satisfies (2.7) and (2.8). We assume that this equilibrium
represents the trade-policy decisions that governments would make if
there were no trade agreement.
The Value of a Trade Agreement
Governments seek a trade agreement in order to achieve mutually
beneficial changes in trade policy. If governments set Nash tariffs in
the absence of a trade agreement, it follows that a trade agreement is
valuable to governments if it results in tariff changes that generate
Pareto improvements in government welfare beyond that achieved in the
Nash equilibrium. This is possible, of course, if and only if the Nash
equilibrium is inefficient (relative to government preferences). We
therefore next discuss the efficiency frontier and its relationship to
the Nash equilibrium.
We make three observations. (6) The first observation is that the
Nash equilibrium is inefficient. This is intuitive. When a government
sets its trade policy unilaterally, it is able to shift some of the
costs of its policy onto its trading partner, through the change in the
terms of trade that its policy implies. In the absence of a trade
agreement, therefore, governments do not have the incentive to set trade
policies in an efficient manner. The second observation is that both
governments can experience welfare gains relative to the Nash
equilibrium only if they both agree to set tariffs below their Nash
levels. The necessity of reciprocal trade liberalization is intuitive,
too. In a Nash equilibrium, governments set tariffs that are higher than
is efficient, since they each recognize that some of the costs of a
higher tariff can be passed on to the trading partner. Not surprisingly,
then, if both governments are to benefit from a trade agreement, then
each must lower its tariff below its Nash level. Evide ntly, governments
are attracted to trade agreements that result in reciprocal trade
liberalization, whether or not the governments maximize national
welfare.
The terms-of-trade externality is clearly one reason that the Nash
equilibrium is inefficient. But are there also political externalities that create an additional reason for a trade agreement? To answer this
question, we consider a hypothetical world in which governments are not
motivated by the terms-of-trade implications of their trade policy
choices. (7) If unilateral tariff choices would be efficient in such a
world, then it follows that the terms-of-trade externality is the only
rationale for a trade agreement. We therefore define politically optimal
tar ifs as any tariff pair ([[tau].sup.PO], [[tau].sup.*PO]) that
satisfies the following two conditions:
[W.sub.p] = 0 and [W.sup.*.sub.[p.sub.*]] = 0.
In the special case where governments maximize national welfare,
politically optimal tariffs correspond to reciprocal free trade. More
generally, government objectives may also reflect political world
considerations, and then there is no expectation that politically
optimal tariffs correspond to reciprocal free trade.
We come now to our third observation: politically optimal tariffs
are efficient. To gain some intuition, suppose that each government sets
its trade policy in order to achieve its preferred local price, so that
tariffs are set at their politically optimal levels, and consider a
small increase in the domestic tariff. The tariff increase has three
effects. First, it causes a small increase in the local price in the
domestic country. Given that the domestic government initially has its
preferred local price, however, this effect has no first-order impact on
the domestic government's welfare. Second, the domestic tariff
increase generates a small decrease in the local price of the foreign
country. The foreign government, however, also initially has its
preferred local price, and so this effect has no first-order impact on
the foreign government's welfare. Third, the small increase in the
domestic tariff induces a decrease in the world price. This
terms-of-trade change, however, represents a pure international tr
ansfer in tariff revenue and thus cannot generate an efficiency gain. We
may conclude that, if the terms-of-trade motivation is eliminated from
the trade-policy choices of governments, then there is no potential for
further Pareto improvements.
We pause now to remark on our large-country assumption. For the
moment, suppose that the politically motivated governments preside over
small countries. In this case, the terms-of-trade motivation would be
eliminated from the trade-policy decisions of each government, simply
because each government would recognize that it is unable to alter the
terms of trade with its tariff selection. The governments of small
countries would thus select the politically optimal tariffs, and their
policies thus would be efficient. Consequently, in the leading
political-economy models of trade policy, there is no reason for the
governments of small countries to form a trade agreement among
themselves, regardless of the political motivations that these
governments may possess. The value of trade agreements thus stems not
from political motivations but rather from the terms-of-trade
externality that is associated with the trade-policy choices of large
countries.
To gain additional intuition, we return to Figure 1. Once again,
suppose that tariffs are initially at point A and that the domestic
government evaluates a tariff increase that would generate the point C.
Consider first the possibility that the domestic government is motivated
by the terms-of-trade consequences (i.e., the movement from D to C) of
its tariff policy. The domestic government then recognizes that some of
the costs of achieving the higher local price at C are shifted onto its
foreign trading partner, through the reduced world price, and this makes
the tariff increase especially attractive. For this reason, Nash tariffs
are always inefficient, with tariffs (trade volumes) that are too high
(low). Consider second the possibility that the domestic government is
not motivated by the terms-of-trade implications of its trade policy. In
this case, it would prefer point C to point A if and only if it also
prefers point D to point A. The potential appeal of point C is now
separate from any cost-shifting b enefits that derive from the
consequent world price change; therefore, the domestic government now
has the "right" incentives when evaluating the tariff
increase. (8) When both governments reason in this manner, the resulting
consistent set of tariffs is politically optimal and efficient.
Figure 2 offers a compact summary of the observations. (9) In
agreement with the first observation, the Nash tariffs (point N) lie off
of the efficiency locus (depicted by the curve E [right arrow] E). The
figure also represents the Nash iso-welfare curves and thereby
illustrates the second observation: a trade agreement can give both
governments greater-than-Nash welfare only if the agreement results in a
reduction in both tariffs. Finally, as the third observation requires,
the politically optimal tariffs (point PO) rest on the efficiency locus.
Of course, the iso-welfare curves are tangent at every point along the
efficiency locus. At the politically optimal tariffs, however, the
iso-welfare curves are also tangent to the iso-world-price locus (the
locus [p.sup.w.sub.PO] The contract curve is represented by the bold
portion of the efficiency locus.
Figure 2 illustrates the basic task facing governments that seek to
design a trade agreement. Non-cooperative governments would set trade
policies unilaterally and obtain the Nash outcome N. A trade agreement
is then appealing to governments as a means to facilitate cooperation,
so that tariffs may be moved from the inefficient Nash point to some
alternative point on the contract curve. Among the tariffs on the
contract curve, the politically optimal tariffs are focal: these tariffs
remedy the terms-of trade inefficiency in a direct way. As Figure 2
illustrates, the efficiency locus need not pass through the free-trade
point, when governments have political concerns. But while
governments' political motivations affect their preferences over
tariffs (e.g., the location of the efficiency locus), it is the
terms-of-trade externality that creates a problem that a trade agreement
might solve.
The Interpretation of the Terms-of-Trade Externality
The discussion above confirms a simple idea: governments can gain
from a cooperative trade agreement, if otherwise each would attempt to
shift costs onto the other and thus adopt inefficient unilateral
policies. In this context, the terms-of-trade externality is simply the
means through which such cost shifting would occur.
As explained in the Introduction, however, many economists are
skeptical of the practical relevance of the terms-of-trade argument for
trade agreements. One objection to this argument is that it is
traditionally advanced in the company of the counter-factual assumption
that governments maximize national income. We have just established,
however, that the essential elements of the terms-of-trade argument are
maintained whether or not governments have political motivations. A
second objection is that the argument is based on abstract general
equilibrium reasoning that seems to emphasize a logic that would not
likely weigh heavily in the practical minds of policy makers.
We now address this second objection. The key point is that the
terms-of-trade argument also may be interpreted in other ways, which are
less abstract and thus suggest greater practical relevance. First, the
theory may be developed in a partial-equilibrium framework. Cost
shifting then occurs via the terms-of-trade externality if foreign
exporters bear some of the incidence of the import tariff. Unilateral
tariffs are now inefficient for an immediately plausible reason: the
domestic government fails to internalize the harm to foreign exporters
that its import tariff implies. (10) Second, the terms-of-trade theory
is easily translated into the market-access language that dominates
real-world, trade policy negotiations. To see the point, suppose that
the home government raises its import tariff and thereby shifts in its
import demand curve. Notice that the resulting "price effect"
(i.e., the home country's terms-of-trade improvement) then has a
corresponding "volume effect" (i.e., the foreign
country's reductio n in access to the home market). Viewed in this
light, it is natural that trade-policy negotiators emphasize the
market-access implications of trade policy.
Rules versus Power
Our discussion to this point indicates that the purpose of a trade
agreement is to provide an escape from a terms-of-trade driven
Prisoners' Dilemma. In essence, we have supposed that a trade
agreement enables governments to move from the inefficient Nash
equilibrium, as depicted by the point N in Figure 2, to a point on the
contract curve. This discussion, however, leaves open two important
questions. First, how might governments best structure their
negotiations in order to successfully navigate their way from the Nash
equilibrium to the contract curve? Second, once governments leave the
Nash equilibrium, each has some incentive to cheat (deviate to its
reaction curve), and it therefore becomes important to ask: How is a
trade agreement enforced? We begin our discussion of the first question
here, and we consider both questions in some detail in Section 4.
A broad distinction can be made between two approaches to the
structure of trade-policy negotiations. In particular, following Jackson
(1997, pp. 109-112), we draw a distinction between
"power-based" and "rules-based" approaches to
negotiation. Under a power-based approach, governments would bargain
over tariffs in a direct fashion that is not constrained by agreed-upon
principles of negotiation. For example, the negotiation between
governments might be characterized by the Nash Bargaining Solution. Such
a negotiation would deliver a point on the contract curve; however, the
exact location of the negotiated outcome would depend upon the Nash
payoffs (i.e., the "threat point"). Consequently, the
negotiated outcome would reflect existing "power asymmetries"
across negotiation partners.
By contrast, under the approach to negotiations embodied in
GATT/WTO, governments identify and agree upon certain principles by
which subsequent negotiations must abide. The negotiation approach used
in GATT/WTO is thus better described as a rules-based approach. Of
course, to gain some understanding of the trade-policy negotiated
outcome that might be induced by GATT/WTO rules, it is first necessary
to identify the specific rules by which member governments must abide.
We may then consider whether these rules can serve to reduce, or even
eliminate, existing power asymmetries across negotiating partners. From
the perspective of the terms-of-trade theory, if these rules induce
large countries to behave as if they were small countries, and thereby
guide the outcome of trade negotiations toward the political optimum,
then we may conclude that GATT/WTO rules indeed do reduce power
asymmetries.
3. The History and Design of GATT/WTO
Having discussed the theory of trade agreements, we now present a
brief overview of the history and design of GATT/WTO. This overview
provides an institutional context that guides our discussion in the next
section.
The Origin of GAIT and the WTO
GATT arose in response to the protectionist trade policies of the
1920s and 1930s. As is well known, trade barriers became increasingly
restrictive following World War I. The situation worsened when the U.S.
enacted the Smoot-Hawley Tariff Act in 1930. Average U.S. tariffs then
increased from 38 to 52%. U.S. trading partners were, of course, not
pleased, and a spate of retaliatory tariffs were imposed. Ultimately,
the major powers imposed tariff rates that were generally on the order
of 50%.
As Hudec (1990, p. 5) explains, "the postwar design for
international trade policy was animated by a single-minded concern to
avoid repeating the disastrous errors of the 1920s and 1930s." In
terms of Figure 2, we may think of the Nash point N as corresponding to
the "tariff war" that is associated with the Smoot-Hawley
tariffs. The challenge before governments was then to find some means by
which to implement a more cooperative trade-policy relationship, such as
represented in Figure 2 by the efficiency locus.
During the 1920s and 1930s, there were, in fact, many multilateral
attempts to achieve such a cooperative trade-policy relationship. The
World Economic Conference of 1927 is one prominent example. These
attempts were not successful, however. The interesting point here is
that a general awareness among governments that mutual gains from
cooperation were possible did not, by itself, result in the spontaneous
emergence of cooperative behavior. In this regard, it is notable that
the inter-war attempts proceeded without an institutional structure that
provides a set of rules under which governments could conduct
negotiations, understand clearly their obligations and enforce
compliance. Without this structure, the initial multilateral efforts
among governments, while well intentioned, failed to get traction.
Over the interwar period, trade-policy cooperation instead took
place through bilateral trade agreements. In the U.S., Secretary of
State Cordell Hull's efforts led to the U.S. Reciprocal Trade
Agreement Act of 1934. An important advocate of reciprocity, Hull
proposed that the U.S. offer import tariff reductions in exchange for
reciprocal reductions in foreign import tariffs. Hull also offered
support for the principle of non-discrimination: when the U.S. lowered a
tariff in a bilateral negotiation, that tariff cut would extend without
discrimination to all trading partners of the U.S. that had been granted
MEN status.
Encouraged by its success in the bilateral arena, the U.S. sought
to build upon the key components of the Reciprocal Trade Agreements Act
and establish a multilateral institution. In 1946, negotiations began
for the creation of an International Trade Organization (ITO). Under the
ITO, negotiations between governments would result in reciprocal and
mutually advantageous reductions in tariffs, and the principle of
non-discrimination would then ensure that the reduced tariffs would be
extended to all member countries. An interim agreement, known as the
General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (1947), was reached in 1947.
While GATT was intended as an interim agreement, the ITO was never
ratified by the U.S. Congress.
What is the purpose of GATT? According to the Preamble of GAIT, the
objectives of the contracting parties include "raising standards of
living, ensuring full employment and a large and steadily growing volume
of real income and effective demand, developing the full use of the
resources of the world and expanding the production and exchange of
goods." The Preamble also states the contracting parties'
belief that "reciprocal and mutually advantageous arrangements
directed to the substantial reduction in tariffs and other barriers to
trade and to the elimination of discriminatory treatment in
international commerce" would contribute toward these goals.
Importantly, "free trade" is not the stated objective of GAIT.
There have been eight rounds of GAIT negotiations. The primary
focus of the earlier rounds was the reduction of import tariffs on
goods. In the most recent round, known as the Uruguay Round, governments
ventured into a number of new issues (e.g., investment and intellectual
property) and formed the WTO. This organization embraces the rules and
agreements made in GAIT negotiations, but it is also a full-fledged
international organization, with an explicit organizational charter and
a unified dispute-settlement system. In effect, with the creation of the
WTO, participating governments fulfilled their original quest with the
ITO for an official international organization.
The Rules of GATT/WTO
GATT/WTO membership carries with it an obligation to abide by a set
of rules. GAIT listed these rules in a series of 39 articles. The WTO
has incorporated these GAIT articles, and as well extended the
principles embodied in them to a variety of new issues. Here, we simply
offer an overview of the GAIT/WTO legal structure by focussing on the
principles embodied in these articles.
To understand this structure, it is useful to distinguish between
three elements: substantive obligations, exceptions and dispute
settlement procedures. The substantive obligations of a GATT/WTO member
refer to tariff commitments, MFN treatment and a set of other
commitments that together comprise a "code of conduct" in the
international-trade arena. Broadly speaking, these provisions define an
obligation to concentrate national protective measures into the form of
tariffs, to apply them on a non-discriminatory basis, and to honor any
tariff bindings made in a GAIT/WTO negotiation.
GAIT/WTO also provides for exceptions to these obligations. One
class of exceptions is for "original" actions, such as when a
member seeks to withdraw a previous concession through renegotiation.
The rationale for including exceptions is that a government is more
likely to make a substantial tariff commitment, if the government knows
that the legal system has "safeguards" so that its concessions
can be withdrawn under appropriate conditions. Of course, a tariff
commitment is meaningful only if exceptions for original actions are
subject to some disciplining structure. For this reason, GATT/WTO rules
also permit a second class of exceptions for "retaliatory"
actions. In particular, if a government seeks to withdraw a previous
concession, then GATT/WTO rules recognize the cost borne by its trading
partner. This partner may seek "compensation" from the
government (e.g., a tariff reduction on some other good), and if this
fails it is allowed to achieve compensation through retaliation. The
meaning of retaliation is that the trading partner can then reciprocate by withdrawing a concession of a "substantially equivalent"
nature.
But how are these rules enforced? This question leads to the third
element mentioned above: the GATT/WTO dispute settlement procedures. In
GAIT/WTO disputes, a central issue is whether the actions by one country
serve to "nullify or impair" the benefits expected under the
agreement by another country. Nullification or impairment includes
actions taken by one country ". . . which harmed the trade of
another, and which 'could not reasonably have been
anticipated' by the other at the time it negotiated for a
concession" (Jackson, 1997, P. 115). The typical case is a
"violation complaint." This occurs when a country is alleged
to have failed to carry out its GATT/WTO obligations, as when a tariff
binding is broken.
It is important to distinguish between the procedures associated
with safeguard exceptions and those that are associated with
nullification or impairment. The safeguard procedures provide for the
lawful withdrawal of negotiated concessions and specify the permissible retaliatory responses of trading partners. The dispute settlement
procedures govern retaliation against a country that takes a harmful
action which its trading partners could not have anticipated under
GATT/WTO rules. In the typical case, the offending country has violated
GATT/WTO rules, and retaliation here is more directly concerned with the
enforcement of rules.
The procedure for settling disputes involves three stages:
consultation among the involved parties; investigation, ruling and
recommendation by a GATT/WTO panel (or Appellate Body); and as a last
resort, authorization of retaliation. Resolution may be achieved in the
first stage or it may follow the panel ruling. If the panel finds that
nullification or impairment has occurred, then it recommends that the
offending country correct any illegal measures. The offending country
may be unwilling to do so, however. In this case, it may seek a
negotiated resolution by offering the harmed country compensation via
MFN tariff reductions on some other goods. If compensation is not
offered, or rejected, then the harmed country may follow through with
the last-resort response: an authorized and discriminatory suspension of
tariff concessions. In practice, the number of authorized retaliations
has been small. (11) As Rhodes (1993, p. 109) argues, however, the
threat of authorized retaliation is often the catalyst that ens ures
resolution in the earlier stages.
Reciprocity in GATT/WTO
As the preceding discussion confirms, the enforcement provisions of
GATT/WTO are elaborate. The representation of reciprocity in GATT/WTO,
however, may be less apparent. In GATT/WTO, the principle of reciprocity
refers to the ideal of mutual changes in trade policy which bring about
changes in the volume of each country's imports that are of equal
value to changes in the volume of its exports. The preceding discussion
contains two instances in which a reference to reciprocity arises.
First, when governments negotiate in GATT/WTO rounds, they do so with
the presumed goal of obtaining mutually advantageous arrangements
through reciprocal reductions in tariff bindings. In particular, it is
often observed that governments approach negotiations seeking a
"balance of concessions," whereby the tariff reduction offered
by one government is balanced against an "equivalent"
concession from its trading partner. Second, when a government seeks to
renegotiate and withdraws a previous concession as an original action,
GAT T/WTO rules allow that substantially affected trading partners may
retaliate in a reciprocal manner, by withdrawing "substantially
equivalent concessions."
4. The Theory of GATT/WTO
We now consider the theoretical interpretation of two key GATT/WTO
features: reciprocity and enforcement.
Reciprocity
We begin with the principle of reciprocity. While we describe above
the ideal of reciprocity, our first task here is to offer a formal
definition of reciprocity. Utilizing the general equilibrium model of
trade presented above and following Bagwell and Staiger (1999), our next
task is to show that the concept of reciprocity can be given a very
simple formal characterization. Finally, we consider in further detail
the application of reciprocity in GATT/WTO.
How might the concept of reciprocity be formally defined? Suppose
that a tariff negotiation results in a change from an initial pair of
tariffs, ([[tau].sup.0],[[tau].sup.*0]), to a subsequent pair of
tariffs, ([[tau].sup.1],[[tau].sup.*1]. The initial world and domestic
local prices may be denoted as [p.sup.w0] [equivalent to]
[p.sup.w]([[tau].sup.0],[[tau].sup.*0] and [p.sup.0] ([p.sup.w]
([[tau].sup.1],[[tau].sup.*1]; likewise, the subsequent world and
domestic local prices may be represented as [p.sup.w1] [equivalent to]
[p.sup.w]([[tau].sup.1],[[tau].sup.*1]) and [p.sup.1] [equivalent to]
p([[tau].sup.1],[p.sup.w1]. We may now say that the tariff changes
conform to the principle of reciprocity provided that
[FORMULA NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (4.1)
where changes in trade volumes are valued at the existing world
price.
We next use the trade balance condition (2.1) and offer a
characterization of reciprocity. Given balanced trade at the initial
tariffs, we know that [p.sup.w0][M.sub.x] ([p.sup.0], [p.sup.w0]) =
[E.sub.y]([p.sup.0],[p.sup.w0]); thus, (4.1) may be rewritten as
[p.sup.w0][M.sup.x]([p.sup.1], [p.sup.w1]) =
[E.sub.y]([p.sup.1],[p.sup.w1]).
Balanced trade at the subsequent tariffs means that
[p.sup.w1][M.sub.x]([p.sup.1], [p.sup.w1]) = [E.sub.y]([p.sup.1],
[p.sup.w1]); therefore, with this further application of the trade
balanced condition, (4.1) may be rewritten as
[[p.sup.w1] - [p.sup.w0]][M.sub.x]([p.sup.1], [p.sup.w1]) = 0 (4.2)
We thus come to a striking characterization: mutual changes in
trade policy conform to the principle of reciprocity if and only if the
world price is unchanged.
The potential significance of this characterization is apparent,
when it is recalled from Section 2 that a government sets its tariffs in
an inefficient manner if and only if it is motivated by the change in
the world price that its tariff choice implies. To gain further insight,
we consider the application of reciprocity within GATT/WTO practice. As
discussed above, reciprocity arises in GATT/WTO practice in two ways.
The first application of reciprocity reflects the balance of
concessions that governments seek through a negotiated agreement. This
informal principle of reciprocity contrasts with a standard economic
argument that free trade is a country's optimal unilateral policy.
As we now demonstrate, however, the terms-of-trade theory offers a
simple interpretation of this application of reciprocity.
Suppose that governments begin at the Nash equilibrium point. At
the Nash point, we may use (2.4), (2.7) and (2.8) to conclude that
[W.sub.p] < 0 < [W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.*]]. If governments were to
reduce tariffs in a reciprocal manner that preserved the world price,
then the domestic local price p would fall and the foreign local price
p' would rise; consequently, the domestic-government welfare would
rise (since [W.sub.p] < 0) and the foreign-government welfare would
also rise (since [W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.*]]>0). Intuitively, at the Nash
equilibrium, both governments would prefer more trade, if the increase
in trade volume could be obtained without a terms-of-trade loss. Neither
government is willing to liberalize unilaterally, since its country
would then experience a decline in the terms of trade. But if the
liberalization occurs under the principle of reciprocity, with one
country's tariff reduction balanced against that of the other, then
the terms of trade are held constant. Each government can then gain from
an expansion in trade volume without experiencing a terms-of-trade loss.
The central ideas are summarized in Figure 3. In Figure 3a, the
case of symmetric countries is illustrated. The iso-world-price locus
that runs through the Nash point N then also extends to the politically
optimal point PO. As governments liberalize under reciprocity, they move
down the Nash isoworld-price locus, and each experiences welfare gains
along the way until the political optimum is reached. Once the political
optimum is obtained, the governments are on the efficiency locus and
have no incentive for further negotiations. The case of asymmetric countries is depicted in Figure 3b, wherein the Nash iso-world-price
locus does not run through the politically optimal point. Liberalization
under reciprocity that begins at the Nash point still raises the welfare
of each government; however, the mutual benefits from further
liberalization are extinguished before the efficiency frontier is
reached. For example, in Figure 3b, the mutual benefits from further
liberalization terminate at point Z where the home government has
achieved its preferred local price (i.e., at the Nash world price,
[W.sub.p] = 0 at point Z).
The second application of reciprocity in GATT/WTO concerns the
rules under which trade agreements may be renegotiated. GATT Article
XXVIII allows that a country may propose to withdraw a concession agreed
upon in a previous round of negotiation. If the country and its trading
partner are unable to agree upon a renegotiated tariff structure, then
the country may carry out its proposed change anyway, with the
understanding that the trading partner may then reciprocate with its own
change. In this context, the notion of reciprocity is used to moderate
the response of the trading partner, who is allowed to withdraw
substantially equivalent concessions of its own.
This discussion suggests that GATT/WTO negotiations may be
understood as a multi-stage game. Governments first agree to an initial
set of tariffs in a round of negotiations. Second, each government
considers whether it would prefer to raise its tariff, given that the
outcome of any renegotiation must conform to reciprocity and thus
preserve the world price.
A figure can capture the key ideas. Figure 4 depicts three possible
tariff pairs, A, B and PO, that might represent an efficient initial
agreement. The iso-world-price loci for each tariff pair are also
depicted. As well, the loci for which [W.sub.p] = 0 and
[W.sup.*.sub.[p.sup.*]] = 0 are represented. For simplicity, these loci
are assumed downward sloping. As Bagwell and Staiger (1999) show, each
locus intersects the efficiency frontier only at the politically optimal
point PO.
Now consider an initial agreement at point A. The foreign
government would prefer to move up the iso-world-price locus to the
point A', where it achieves its preferred local price. It would
thus request a renegotiation to raise its tariff to the value
corresponding to point A', with the understanding that the domestic
government would then withdraw a substantially equivalent concession
that would preserve the world price and therefore deliver the tariff
pair at point A'. The efficient tariff pair at point A thus fails
to be robust against the type of renegotiation that GATT/WTO allows. A
similar argument applies for the efficient tariff pair associated with
point B. At this tariff pair, it is the domestic government that
withdraws its original concession in order to induce the point B'.
In fact, there is only one efficient tariff pair that is robust to the
possibility of renegotiation. The politically optimal tariff pair is the
only point on the efficiency locus at which both governments achieve
their prefer red local prices given the associated world price.
It is interesting to compare the hypothetical world which led to
the definition of politically optimal tariffs with what governments
achieve under reciprocity. In the hypothetical world, governments were
assumed not to value the terms-of-trade movements caused by their tariff
choices, and they were thus led to select politically optimal tariffs.
Reciprocity corresponds to a related experiment, in which governments
ignore the terms-of-trade movements associated with their tariff
increase, because the mutual changes in tariffs under reciprocity
guarantee that the terms of trade are, in fact, fixed. Reciprocity thus
induces governments to act as they did not value the terms-of-trade
movements caused by their tariff selections. (12)
In effect, governments are "penalized" under the GATT/WTO
reciprocity rule if they attempt to negotiate an efficient tariff pair
other than the political optimum. Consider, for example, point A in
Figure 3. At this point, the home government enjoys greater welfare than
it would at the political optimum; however, some of the benefit to the
home government of point A would be lost in the subsequent renegotiation
to the point A'. The home government therefore may be less desirous of pushing negotiations away from the political optimum and toward point
A. As illustrated by this example, the reciprocity rule helps to
mitigate the power asymmetries that governments might otherwise wield at
the bargaining table. As a consequence, it encourages governments to
select the politically optimal tariffs.
Enforcement
In the context of Figure 2, suppose that governments have formed a
trade agreement that specifies rules under which they negotiate from the
Nash point N to a point on contract curve, such as the political
optimum, P0. How is this agreement enforced?
Unfortunately, the temptation for a government to select a high
tariff and shift costs does not evaporate just because an agreement is
signed. Each government has a short-term incentive to deviate to a
higher-than-is-efficient tariff and enjoy the associated terms-of-trade
gain. Unlike many agreements reached under domestic law, a trade
agreement is not enforced through the threat of incarceration. There is
no "world jail" into which government leaders are thrown if
they violate a trade agreement. Rather, a trade agreement must be
"self-enforcing": a government will be dissuaded from
violating the agreement only if the short-term gains lead to long-term
losses, once other governments retaliate in kind. Viewed this way, the
tariffs that governments can achieve as part of a self-enforcing trade
agreement reflect a balance between the short-term benefit of protection
and the long-term cost of retaliation. The "most-cooperative"
tariffs that governments can enforce may not be fully efficient, but the
most-coopera tive tariffs are more efficient than Nash tariffs.
As McMillan (1986, 1989), Dixit (1987) and Bagwell and Staiger
(1990) emphasize, the theory of repeated games may be used to analyze
the enforcement issues that are associated with trade agreements.
Formally, we may regard the static framework described above as the
stage game of an infinitely repeated game. As governments cooperate by
imposing low tariffs that rest below the tariff reaction functions, each
government perceives a short-run benefit from a unilateral tariff
increase. Each government, however, may be concerned that such a
deviation, once discovered, could lead to retaliation. At the extreme,
recalcitrant behavior could undermine the entire agreement and
ultimately lead countries back to the inefficient Nash outcome. This
long-term cost may serve as an effective deterrent, provided that the
short-term incentive to cheat is not too great. Thus, even if
governments cannot cooperate fully, some cooperation can be sustained.
We now argue that this repeated-game perspective is consistent with
the GATT/WTO enforcement provisions as described in Section 3. The
creation of GATT and its nullification-or-impairment procedures may be
interpreted as an attempt to replace the Nash outcome with a more
efficient equilibrium outcome. To accomplish this, governments agreed
through GATT to limit the use of retaliation along the equilibrium path
and reposition it as an off-equilibrium-path threat that enforces rules.
It must be stressed, however, that a limited role for retaliation indeed
does arise along the equilibrium path. This occurs, for example, when a
government seeks a retaliatory exception to obtain compensation for an
original tariff modification by its trading partner, where the original
modification is a legal exception such as allowed under GATT Article
XXVIII (renegotiation). The role of retaliation in GATT/WTO is thus more
subtle than a standard application of repeated-game theory might
suggest.
The distinction between the on- and off-equilibrium-path roles of
retaliation may be further clarified with the consideration of two
situations. First, suppose that a foreign government raises its tariff
above its bound rate and justifies its behavior as a legal exception
under the rules for renegotiation. If the parties are unable to reach an
agreement on compensation, then the home government may take its own
retaliatory exception, with a "substantially equivalent"
tariff hike. Here, retaliation is best interpreted as an
on-equilibrium-path event. It serves to discipline the use of legal
exceptions, so that their application reflects a legitimate purpose
(e.g., changed circumstances) rather than an opportunistic desire to
shift costs onto a trading partner.
Second, suppose that the home government complains that the foreign
trade policy has changed in a manner that nullifies or impairs the
access to the foreign market that the home government initially
expected. Suppose further that the case is brought before a dispute
panel, the panel finds in favor of the foreign government, and the home
government nevertheless imposes unauthorized retaliatory tarifs. Such
defiant behavior is best interpreted as an off-equilibrium-path
deviation. What deters this deviant behavior?
Of course, the foreign government then may be authorized to
retaliate against the unauthorized retaliatory tariffs. But this may
only extend the cycle: the home government may respond with yet another
unauthorized retaliatory response. The fundamental deterrent to such
contumacious behavior, and the deterrent that rests at the foundation of
all others, is the fear of initiating a breakdown in the entire
cooperative arrangement and thereby causing a "trade war"
(i.e., a return to the Nash point, N). As in the repeated-game model,
this breakdown threat is the ultimate off-equilibrium-path retaliation,
and it discourages deviant behavior of this second kind.
5. Conclusion
In the discussion above, we offer two main conclusions. First,
whether or not governments have political motivations, the purpose of a
trade agreement is to offer a means of escape from a
terms-of-trade-driven Prisoners' Dilemma. Second, GATT/WTO's
reciprocity and enforcement rules are well designed to facilitate such
an escape.
Given space restrictions, there are a number of further issues that
are not treated here. We refer the reader to our book (Bagwell and
Staiger, forthcoming) for a more thorough treatment of the topics raised
above, an analysis of the efficiency properties of other GATT/WTO rules
(e.g., the MFN rule and those rules that concern the treatment of
preferential trading agreements and agricultural subsidies), a
discussion of several new trade-policy issues that currently confront
the WTO (e.g., the treatment of labor and environmental standards as
well as competition policy), and a variety of important modeling
extensions (e.g., many goods, multiple trading partners). Instead, we
use this concluding section to highlight three important areas for
future research.
A first area concerns the purpose of a trade agreement. Our
representation of government preferences includes those used in the
leading political-economy models of trade policy. Nevertheless, an
alternative formulation might point to a novel problem that a trade
agreement could solve. One approach is to allow that governments face a
time-consistency problem, in which case a government might use a trade
agreement to facilitate its commitment to a liberalization process.
Recent analyses that emphasize this possibility are offered by Maggi and
Rodriguez (1998), McLaren (1997) and Staiger and Tabellini (1999). A
second approach is to relax the market-clearing assumption that
underlines our general equilibrium model. For example, in line with
Keynesian theory, if markets are characterized by rigid markups, then
the externalities from trade policy are not channeled through changes in
the terms of trade; rather, an import tariff harms foreign exporters by
reducing the trade volume on which they enjoy fixed markups. It remains
to be seen if these alternative approaches offer an interpretation of
the rules of GATT/WTO. This is an important direction that should be
pursued in future research.
A second area concerns the role of the GATT/WTO institution in
achieving a cooperative trade-policy outcome. At a theoretical level,
given the efficiency-enhancing properties of the rules of GATT/WTO, it
is not obvious why governments could not come to a tacit understanding
to follow these rules. Why is it necessary to have an actual
institution? The natural response to this question emphasizes the
coordination difficulties in achieving a common and cooperative
understanding between multiple participants over a complex set of
issues. In particular, while GATT/WTO rules may be understood as the
codification of supergame strategies, in the real world, it may be
difficult for a large number of countries trading thousands of goods to
come to a common and tacit understanding of such strategies. The failed
attempts at cooperation in the 1920s and 1930s are indicative of this
formidable coordination problem. An actual institution, with a set of
rules that makes explicit the obligations of governments and the manner
in which these obligations are enforced, may be necessary to get
traction in the multilateral journey from a non-cooperative relationship
toward the efficiency frontier. Ambitious future work would provide a
theoretical framework on the basis of which this response might be
affirmed or rejected. (13)
Relatedly, it is not obvious why governments should favor a
rules-based institution like GATT/WTO over a power-based approach. While
we argue that the existing rules-based approach has an attractive
design, could not governments do better by eliminating the constraints
that rules imply and negotiating directly over tariffs on the efficiency
frontier? This question suggests that future work might look for a
problem that arises under power-based negotiations and is moderated or
eliminated under a rules-based approach. One such problem may be
associated with equity considerations: a power-based approach favors the
strong, and this may be objected on equity grounds. Another approach is
to argue that power-based negotiations lead to inefficiencies. Building
on McLaren's (1997) ideas, we argue in Bagwell and Staiger (1999,
forthcoming) that power-based negotiations may lead to inefficient
participation, since weaker governments may fear being "held
up" in subsequent negotiations with stronger governments. Power-bas
ed negotiations also may lead to inefficiencies, if governments
dissipate rents (e.g., through signaling activities) in order to become
(or seem) stronger, so as to enjoy the greater benefits that stronger
parties enjoy in a power-based system. A rules-based approach may limit
such inefficiencies. Important future work would explore a broader game,
with potential inefficiencies for power-based negotiations, and
determine the equity and efficiency differences between rules- and
power-based approaches to trade-policy negotiations.
A third area for future research is empirical. Our discussion
emphasizes the terms-of-trade externality as the reason for a trade
agreement. In Bagwell and Staiger (forthcoming), we argue that there is
strong support for the presumption that trade policies generate
important terms-of-trade externalities. But this area of work is still
quite new, and there is much more to be learned about the size and
pattern of terms-of-trade externalities across trading partners.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 3a OMITTED]
[FIGURE 3b OMITTED]
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
Notes
(1.) This paper draws heavily from our book (Bagwell and Staiger,
forthcoming).
(2.) Throughout, we follow convention and distinguish domestic and
foreign variables by placing an asterisk on the latter.
(3.) Henceforth, p denotes the function p([tau],[p.sup.w]), and p
indicates the function [p.sup.*]([[tau].sup.*],[p.sup.w]).
(4.) In this two-sector general equilibrium setting, the Lerner
symmetry theorem ensures that trade taxes and subsidies can be
equivalently depicted as applying to exports or imports.
(5.) Given our assumption that the Metzler and Lerner Paradoxes are
ruled out, the iso-world-price locus takes a positive slope while the
iso-local-price locus takes a negative slope.
(6.) For formal proofs of these observations, see Bagwell and
Staiger (1999, forthcoming).
(7.) Our assumption here is not that governments fail to understand
the terms-of-trade effects of their tariff choices. Instead, we consider
a hypothetical situation in which governments are not motivated by these
effects. In the context of (2.7), we allow that governments understand
that [lambda] < 0, but we now suppose that their welfare functions
are such that [W.sub.p] [equivalent to] 0. After p. identifying the
tariffs that would be selected by governments with these hypothetical
preferences, we evaluate the efficiency of these tariffs with respect to
actual government preferences.
(8.) A movement from A to D in Figure 1 induces no externality
through the terms of trade. It does cause a change in the foreign local
price; however, if the foreign government also selects politically
optimal tariffs, then a small change of this kind has no first-order
effect on foreign welfare.
(9.) In this figure, we assume that a unique Nash equilibrium
exists, a unique political optimum exists, and that the political
optimum lies on the contract curve (i.e., it is on that portion of the
efficiency locus at which each government obtains greater-than-Nash
welfare). The political optimum rests on the contract curve, provided
that countries are sufficiently symmetric.
(10.) This interpretation is developed further in Bagwell and
Staiger (2001), where we use a partial equilibrium model and derive the
three observations mentioned above. In Bagwell and Staiger
(forthcoming), we refer to empirical studies and argue for the
presumption that foreign exporters are unable to "pass
through" an import tariff.
(11.) Under GATT, retaliation was authorized in only one case,
concerning the U.S. and the Netherlands, and even then the Netherlands
never acted on that authorization (Jackson, 1997, p. 116). The dispute
settlement procedures under the WTO are considerably strengthened. Under
the WTO, further eases have emerged in which retaliation has been
authorized-and used. These include the well-known banana and
beef-hormone cases. Further discussion is offered by Mavroidis (2000)
and WTO (2001, p. 28).
(12.) Formally, as (2.7) indicates, if [lambda][W.sub.[p.sup.w]] =
0, then the domestic government's preferred tariff satisfies
[W.sub.p] = 0. In turn, if the government were hypothesized not to value
a change in the terms of trade (i.e., if [W.sub.[p.sup.w]] [equivalent
to] 0), then [lambda][W.sub.[p.sup.w]] would be zero. Likewise, if the
government were to expect a reciprocal tariff adjustment from its
trading partner that would result in no change in the terms of trade
(i.e., if [lambda] = 0), then [lambda][W.sub.[p.sup.w]] would be zero.
(13.) One thought is that an explicit multilateral institution
enhances cooperation by facilitating the exchange of information. For
example, as Maggi (1999) suggests, GATT/WTO may provide a forum in which
deviations may be publicized, so that third-party punishments may be
brought forth. Likewise, as Athey and Bagwell (2001) argue in the
context of collusion theory, actual meetings may be necessary, if the
form of optimal cooperation requires the (incentive-compatible)
communication of private information.
References
Athey, Susan and Kyle Bagwell (2001), "Optimal Collusion with
Private Information," The Rand Journal of Economics, 32.3, Autumn,
428-65.
Bagwell, Kyle and Robert W. Staiger (1990), "A Theory of
Managed Trade," American Economic Review, 80, September 1990,
779-95.
Bagwell, Kyle and Robert W. Staiger (1999), "An Economic
Theory of GATT," American Economic Review, March, 89.1, 215-248.
Bagwell, Kyle and Robert W. Staiger (2001), "Reciprocity,
Non-Discrimination and Preferential Agreements in the Multilateral
Trading System," European Journal of Political Economy, 17,
281-325.
Bagwell, Kyle and Robert W. Staiger (forthcoming), The Economics of
the World Trading System, Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Baldwin, Richard (1987), "Politically Realistic Objective
Functions and Trade Policy," Economic Letters, 24, 287-90.
Brock, William A. and Stephen P. Magee (1978), "The Economics
of Special Interest Politics," American Economic Review, 68, May,
246-50.
Caves, Richard A. (1976), "Economic Models of Political
Choice: Canada's Tariff Structure," Canadian Journal of
Economics, 9, May, 278-300.
Dixit, Avinash (1987), "Strategic Aspects of Trade
Policy," in Truman F. Bewley, ed., Advances in Economic Theory:
Fifth World Congress, Cambridge University Press: New York.
Feenstra, Robert and Jagdish Bhagwati (1982), "Tariff Seeking
and the Efficient Tariff," in Jagdish Bhagwati, ed., Import
Competition and Response, University of Chicago Press: Chicago.
Findlay, Ronald and Stanislaw Wellisz (1982), "Endogenous Tariffs, the Political Economy of Trade Restrictions and Welfare,"
in Jagdish Bhagwati, ea., Import Competition and Response, University of
Chicago Press: Chicago.
Grossman, Gene M. and Elhanan Helpman (1994), "Protection for
Sale," American Economic Review, 84, September, 833-50.
Grossman, Gene M. and Elhanan Helpman (1995), "Trade Wars and
Trade Talks," Journal of Political Economy, 103, August, 675-708.
Hillman, Arye L. (1982), "Declining Industries and
Political-Support Protectionist Motives," American Economic Review,
72, 1180-87.
Hudec, Robert E. (1990), The GATT Legal System and World Trade
Diplomacy, Second Edition, Praeger Publisher: New York.
Jackson, John (1997), The World Trading System, 2nd edition, The
MIT Press: Cambridge.
Johnson, Harry G. (1953-54), "Optimum Tariffs and
Retaliation," Review of Economic Studies, 1.2, 142-53.
Kennan, John and Raymond Reizman (1988), "Do Big Countries Win
Tariff Wars?," International Economic Review, 29, 81-85.
Maggi, Giovanni (1999), "The Role of Multilateral Institutions
in International Trade Cooperation," American Economic Review,
March, 89.1, 190-214.
Maggi, Giovanni and Andres Rodriguez-Clare (1998), "The Value
of Trade Agreements in the Presence of Political Pressures,"
Journal of Political Economy, 106.3, 574-601.
Mavroidis, Petros C. (2000), "Remedies in the WTO Legal
System: Between a Rock and a Hard Place," European Journal of
International Law, 11.4, 763-813.
Mayer, Wolfgang (1981), "Theoretical Considerations on
Negotiated Tariff Adjustments," Oxford Economic Papers, 33, 135-53.
Mayer, Wolfgang (1984), "Endogenous Tariff Formation,"
American Economic Review, 74, 970-85.
McLaren, John (1997), "Size, Sunk Costs, and Judge
Bowker's Objection to Free Trade," American Economic Review,
87, 400-20.
McMillan, John (1986), Game Theory in International Economics,
Harwood: New York.
McMillan, John (1989), "A Game-Theoretic View of International
Trade Negotiations: Implications for Developing Countries," in John
Whalley, ed., Developing Countries and the Global Trading System: Volume
1.
Mill, John Stuart (1844), Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of
Political Economy, Parker: London.
Olson, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action, Harvard
University Press: Cambridge.
Rhodes, Carolyn (1993), Reciprocity, U.S. Trade Policy, and the
GATT Regime, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York.
Staiger, Robert W. and Guido Tabellini (1999), "Do GATT Rules
Help Governments Make Domestic Commitments?," Economics and
Politics, July, XI.2, 109-44.
Torrens, Robert (1844), The Budget: On Commercial Policy and
Colonial Policy, Smith, Elder: London.
WTO (2001), Annual Report 2001, Geneva.
Kyle Bagwell * and Robert W. Staiger **
* Columbia University: Department of Economics (Kelvin J. Lancaster
Professor of Economic Theory) and School of Business (Professor of
Finance and Economics).
** University of Wisconsin, Madison: Department of Economics. This
is scheduled to appear in Michael Szenberg and Lall Ramrattan, eds.,
Shifting Paradigms, New Directions in Economics for Cambridge University
Press.