The limits of law: how formal rules undermine human relations.
Frohnen, Bruce P.
We live in a time of law, in which there seem to be statutes,
rules, and regulations regarding virtually every aspect of our lives.
The battle cry of the disaffected, "there ought to be a law,"
has been heeded with a vengeance. Whereas not so long ago people had to
work out for themselves what kinds of benefits employers would provide
employees and how a business owner would respond to a potential customer
when he discovers something morally problematic about that customer (or
vice versa), the law now provides guidelines and potential punishments.
Proponents of our current system argue that these laws make us
freer. Laws now may make people free from potential bankruptcy caused by
the cost of contraceptives. They also may make people free from the
insult of being denied services, or having to find a different service
provider. Thus, in a manner directly in line with Franklin
Roosevelt's "Four Freedoms" (of speech, of worship, from
want, and from fear), our government is providing us with more freedoms.
And it is doing so not merely in its role as social welfare state but
also in its role as law-state. (1)
There is a long tradition espousing the rule of law as necessary
for human freedom. Predictable rules long have been seen as providing
people with the certainty they need to plan and go about their lives.
Such certainty is needed if people are to have the confidence to forge
their own lives rather than rely on the government, and this is the
essence of ordered liberty. As Montesquieu noted, political liberty
embraces "a tranquility of mind arising from the opinion each
person has of his safety." In order to have this liberty, "it
is requisite the government be so constituted as one man need not be
afraid of another."
Discussing the necessity of a separation of governmental powers,
Montesquieu was arguing that people living under arbitrary
governments--in which one person might write, enforce, and adjudicate
law--were consigned to the rule of men rather than the rule of law.
Under such conditions, Montesquieu argued, the rulers would be able to
violate their own laws with impunity. As a result, there would be a
constant fear of being subject to the arbitrary will of a ruler, and
people could never enjoy that "tranquility of mind" essential
for liberty. (2)
My argument here is that, while the rule of law is an essential
public good, the actual number and extent of laws also are important
factors in determining whether there will be liberty--and, indeed, the
rule of law itself. In effect, too much law undermines not just freedom
but also certainty, which is necessary for the rule of law. As the realm
of "law" expands, it crowds out human liberty, including the
freedom provided by law, understood as properly promulgated rules that
can be understood and followed by the governed. Moreover, as too much
law undermines freedom and its own proper character, it also tears apart
the very fabric of the community in which we must live our lives.
Montesquieu defended the rule of law as necessary for tranquility
of mind and, with it, the ability to plan and to build a life of ordered
liberty. His point, however, goes to the form rather than to the extent
of lawmaking. Such laws as there are, he argued, should result from a
system embodying the rule of law, lest there be arbitrary rule. As to
the quantity of laws, it seems clear that too many particular laws hem
in our actions to such an extent that they may make us no longer free.
There is no precise, mathematical calculus by which to determine
when a definite line between "free" and "unfree"
regimes has been crossed. But at some point on the spectrum--between a
society without law and one in which all aspects of life are subject to
statutory regulation--society becomes recognizably unfree. (3) Too
little law may leave us at the mercy of the strong and ruthless. Too
much law eventually eliminates that "sphere of autonomy" that
classical liberals refer to as the heart of liberty. I prefer to term
this space a zone of prudence, because we remain under a duty (and
natural impulse, when it is not diverted by sin or other bad incentives)
to act in accordance with the broad but fundamental norms of natural law
(for example, the Golden Rule). But the point is that the absence of
formal law leaves an area within which we may interact with one another
and with the associations in which we lead most of our lives. In this
zone we may act according to rules and customs worked out with our
fellows, consistent with our understanding of our own circumstances,
needs, duties, and desires.
A regime that reduces social relations and our duties to one
another to a set of laws and legal principles reduces this zone of
prudence, potentially to the vanishing point. One may consider, here,
recent outcries over wedding cakes and photographs. In several cases,
those who bake or take photographs for a living have been penalized by
the government for their religiously based decision not to participate
in same-sex marriage ceremonies. Whether one sees such refusal as rude,
hurtful, or an understandable desire to live one's professional
life in accordance with one's deepest beliefs, the increasing fact
of legal sanctions for decisions regarding interpersonal relations
clearly narrows the zone within which one may act according to
one's own conscience. These bakers and photographers have been
"legally" made unfree in a very important sense, in that they
are being forced to act in a way forbidden by their own moral judgment
as they seek to choose for whom they should work. That the unfreedom is
imposed and enforced via legal process makes it no less an important
reduction of liberty.
Proponents of such laws argue that they are freeing our society, or
at least particular people, from certain forms of discrimination. But
such laws are not concerned with promoting freedom; they constrain
freedom in pursuit of the different goal of equality. They demand, under
penalty of law, that certain categories of person (for example,
employers, those renting accommodations, those providing business
services) treat a given description of person the same as others
putatively qualified for some service, membership, or benefit, despite
possessing some characteristic or behavior pattern with which others do
not wish to associate.
The justification is that said characteristic or behavior pattern
is not, in fact, morally or otherwise blameworthy and therefore deserves
government protection against private discrimination. Debate may be
appropriate as to whether such laws are necessary, just, and actually
serve the ends their proponents claim, as well as whether they do so at
too great a cost. But we should not be confused about the goal and the
effect--more laws producing less freedom in the interest of more
equality.
One can extend this logic into any number of areas of
legislation--from those concerning employment, to regulation of property
rights (for example, for environmental purposes or to regulate
agricultural markets) and even marriage. My point is not that all laws
are oppressive. Rather, it is that all laws restrict choices. Thus, free
societies tend to insist that laws regulate substantive activities only
where there exists broad consensus on the need to do so, and where such
laws can be enacted and enforced in accordance with, rather than in
opposition to, preexisting norms and customs. In this way, as little
disruption as possible will be caused to the people's reasonable
expectations concerning what will be demanded of them by their laws.
This last point raises the concern of law--or too much law--with
certainty. We need our laws to be predictable if we are to follow them.
Lon Fuller argued that the law, if it is to have a moral claim on our
allegiance (as opposed to the sheer power to force our obedience), must
meet certain basic criteria. These criteria make up, in essence, the
rule of law, for they describe a system according to which the people
are ruled by settled laws, rather than the dictates of those who are in
power. Fuller set down these criteria in the form of eight
"canons": there must be general rules; the rules must be
promulgated; the rules must typically be prospective, rather than
retroactive; the rules must be clear; the rules must not require
contradictory actions; the rules must not require actions that are
impossible to perform; the rules must remain relatively constant over
time; and there must be a congruence between the rules as declared and
the rules as administered. (4)
It is not necessary to go through Fuller's canons in detail to
see their powerful import: a regime of law must rule according to
settled, known rules that clearly signal to the people what is expected
of them, as well as ensuring that the rules actually can be followed.
Here I have focused on the notion of certainty because it sums up a
great deal of that which concerned Fuller. It also highlights an aspect
of the rule of law that is too little noted in democracies. These
regimes pride themselves on their humane attitude toward rule, but too
often impose requirements on the citizenry that, while perhaps not
overly onerous in any specific instance, combine to form a web of
regulation that is as confusing as it is confining.
Democracies have a particular problem with law. Because democratic
lawmakers are assumed to act for the sovereign people, they tend to
believe (and be supported in their belief) that whatever laws they
promulgate are by nature just. And, as shown by the example of
antidiscrimination legislation, democratic laws have a tendency to aim
at instantiating some conception of justice. The result is a tendency of
democratic governments to overreach. They attempt to impose justice by
statute where custom and private judgment are better situated to find
solutions to potential disputes that meet the reasonable expectations
and needs of all parties concerned. The result is law formulated to such
an extent and in such detail that mere mortal citizens often cannot
divine its purposes, let alone what it requires of them.
Certainty requires that the rules we are to follow be known to us.
It also requires that the laws be predictable, not just in their
language and requirements, but also in their effect, and in their
interaction with preexisting rules. More laws mean more surprises. New
laws continue to be promulgated such that people--especially those who
run businesses and those who work in various parts of those
businesses--have to keep a constant eye out to avoid running afoul of a
law they did not know existed.
An abundance of new laws generates business for lawyers. But such
malleability in the legal and regulatory system is not a good thing for
a society. When people in economic life have to hire professionals to
keep an eye on ever-changing statutory developments and check to see
whether basic policies--like, say, the company health care plan--have to
be changed both to fit old laws and to fit the new law, the result is
constant uncertainty and fear of government sanctions. This is
especially troublesome, of course, when the new law is so onerous and
overly complicated as to be unworkable. Under such circumstances
(including, for example, those operative under the current program of
government-mandated health insurance), we may look for an extra added
"bonus," in that those with enough money and political clout
can win "waivers" from the rules the rest of us must follow,
further undermining certainty as well as generality and other
characteristics essential to the rule of law.
Too much law may produce a system that undermines our ability to
follow that law while also living up to our duty to lead decent, moral
lives. One might mention here Milton Friedman's notion of an
"invisible foot." This metaphor is intended to balance, shall
we say, Adam Smith's notion of an invisible hand that guides actors
within the market to behave in a manner that serves the public interest
even as they focus on serving their own. (5) Unlike the benign invisible
hand, however, the invisible foot reflects the unintended consequences
of governmental actions.
When the government chooses to pass a law, instituting a program
aimed at a particular end, it generally focuses on something it
considers in the public interest. Let us say, for example, that the
government wishes to protect children from hunger. In pursuing this
goal, the government might institute a program of payments to mothers of
young children who do not have a working husband in the home. The
program clearly will get money into the hands of caregivers who need it
to feed their children. Simple, no?
Unfortunately, as we found out under Aid to Families with Dependent
Children (AFDC), such a well-intentioned program is not a laser narrowly
aimed at eliminating a specific problem. Like the vast majority of laws,
it constitutes a change in the incentives provided to people to act in a
variety of ways. In the case of AFDC, the program provided an incentive
for men to abandon the mothers of their children and even for young
women to see out-of-wedlock pregnancies as a means of establishing a
kind of independence from their families through dependence on the
government. (6)
Should we marry and raise our children to be responsible adults? Or
should we have children out of wedlock and depend on the government to
support our "independence" from family, church, and local
association? President Clinton claimed to have "ended welfare as we
know it." But the fact is that other laws, including those
establishing wildly expanded, indiscriminate food stamp and disability
insurance programs, continue to undermine the clearly preferable moral
choice. People are not "freer" when they depend on the
government rather than more natural, more human relations. Instead, the
law chains them to dependency and to a way of life that undermines their
moral sense.
None of this is to argue against the moral necessity of assistance
for the poor. My goal here is to question the value of reducing such
assistance to law. When the moral rights of the poor (which are very
real) were reduced to legal rights, something important was lost: human
relationships. Numerous public programs in the United States, including
a wide variety of local charity boards, once received assistance from
state and local governments. Reduction of these once highly personal
loci of charitable funds and relationships to sets of administrative
criteria and procedures certainly cut down substantially on the
political use of charity by various corrupt local governments. Even so,
it is open to serious question whether the result was an increase in
respect for human dignity. The claim was that such procedures guaranteed
fairness, efficiency, and full coverage. Whether this is true or not,
these procedures also ensured dehumanization and inattention to
destructive habits and "lifestyles" that destroy people's
physical and spiritual well-being. (7)
Even our schools once were embedded within communities rather than
public policy and law. Schools in America well into the nineteenth
century by and large were independent local institutions that received
public funding--instead of being creatures of the government itself,
bound by law. But over the course of the nineteenth century, a series of
conflicts and visions of progress caused us to leave behind local boards
of charity and education for detailed legal programs of regulation and
assistance.
As an example, one might consider public education in the state of
New York during the first half of the nineteenth century. Local
governments would grant monies to organizations that ran the public
schools. Of interest, in a nation once committed to the free exercise of
religion, these schools, though publicly funded, did not sanitize God
out of their curriculum. Indeed, conflicts arose because the schools
were pervasively Protestant and overtly anti-Catholic. The
Catholics' response? They did not sue; they lobbied. And in a
number of important instances, they secured public funding for their
own, Catholic schools.
A typically American solution to the plural structure of society
was beginning to form. The character of local schools would depend on
the character of the local people themselves. Protestant, Catholic, and
Jewish neighborhoods would have their own schools. And their tax dollars
would be available for them to run these schools according to the
dictates of their own faiths. The state would leave the fundamental
moral decisions regarding issues like the teaching of religion to the
more fundamental moral associations acting within local communities.
Unfortunately, the response from a number of quarters to this
development was to seek to outlaw such funding on the grounds that
Catholics, owing allegiance to that "foreign prince" known as
the pope, were violating the Constitution by receiving public funds for
their schools. We know where all this ended up. New laws established
government-run schools openly hostile to any form of religious
expression. The law, in the form of a misreading of our Constitution,
won. Human relations and good education lost. (8)
This tragedy was the product of prejudice. It also was the product
of law. Laws are by nature neutral; they are generally applicable rules.
All laws make distinctions, of course. A law against murder
"privileges" nonmurderers over those who commit murder. But
laws embody and announce the moral precepts of a people. So a law
favoring one religious group over another is making a public statement
about those religions. If a people does not want to make such a
"privileging" statement and policy, it must not make a law.
If a people chooses to make a law and insists on its being neutral,
then it will have to institutionalize equality between the groups
subjected to the law. A law that says nothing about religion in the
schools may, in fact, be neutral toward all religions, in the sense that
it allows local communities to make their own decisions on this critical
issue. But a law that attempts to see that all religions are treated
equally must interfere with these local associations, forcing them to go
against the wishes of their members, allowing them to be held hostage to
dissenters--particularly litigious dissenters--of all kinds in their
midst.
And this is what happened in regard to education. Rather than leave
decisions regarding religion in schools to the local school boards
themselves, the government chose to "solve" the problem
through law. States increasingly took over the schools, originally with
the intention of maintaining a kind of weak Protestantism or abstract
deism in the curriculum. Inevitably, given the demands of
"neutrality," government schools quickly began a never-ending
cycle in which they have become ever more strident in attempts to
eliminate religion from this, as most other, areas of the public square.
(9)
Laws always have unintended consequences, and in their very
instantiation they crowd out important, informal incentives for right
conduct, as well as social institutions, beliefs, and practices critical
for the formation of good character and the maintenance of a decent
public life. Perhaps this is why Saint Thomas Aquinas, by no means a
moral relativist, actually voiced opposition, following Saint Augustine,
to laws against prostitution. (10) Obviously, Aquinas and Augustine knew
that fornication and adultery are sins, and would rather they could be
made less common. But they also knew that the world they lived in was
one in which prostitution was sadly common, and sadly ingrained into
community life owing to the use of courtesans by powerful people and the
sheer number of brothels and unruly, unattached males.
We should not, of course, overlook the very practical circumstances
faced in medieval Europe, where this particular bad practice was
concerned. Not even cities had police forces of any note--they relied on
"the watch," a paramilitary force, for what little policing
they had, and had almost no ability to tell people where they could have
what kind of business. Cities tended to burn down in this era, as well
as succumb to riots and other disasters, because much of the
infrastructure of public order had yet to develop. Under such conditions
an attempt at social reform like the ending of prostitution was more
likely to produce violence than any beneficial result.
We today live in a society that, despite its many worse faults (for
example, official approval for abortion), has improved the situation to
a certain extent with regard to the trafficking in women for sex. But
this was made possible by a long train of reforms and changes in our
social structures. Aquinas and Augustine both knew that, while the moral
dictates of natural law are unchanging, the proper role of law in
furthering them is not. And, in their times, they judged that any
attempt to stamp out prostitution would involve too much disruption of
social life, and so many demands for police action in a time when there
really were no police, that it would be best not to attempt the feat
through governmental means.
Now, this is no apology for prostitution. But it is, I hope, a
useful example of the limits of law, even in the minds of saints and
doctors of the Church, to change human behavior without risking dire
adverse consequences. This problem situation can be seen more generally
in our own era. Where once ours was a nation of custom and common law,
we increasingly have become a nation in which law is considered the
answer to social problems. Sadly, the result is less respect for the law
and, as important, an undermining of the customs and personal relations
on which real, functioning communities rely.
George Carey argues that the primary support government can give to
communities is space. Communities, he points out, must have a reason to
exist if they are to survive. They must have both "room," or
administrative freedom to maneuver, and purpose, some genuine set of
practical needs to fulfill. (11) And this means, more than anything,
that the central government must not take over the primary role of local
communities in helping their members order their lives if those citizens
are to be self-governing, free, and possessed of at least the
possibility for virtue.
Alexis de Tocqueville painted a picture of a functioning community
in America's early republic that evinces the kind of community life
with which I am concerned here.
The free institutions of the United States and the political rights
enjoyed there provide a thousand continual reminders to every citizen
that he lives in society. At every moment they bring his mind back to
the idea, that it is the duty as well as the interest of men to be
useful to their fellows. Having no particular reason to hate others,
since he is neither their slave nor their master, the American's heart
easily inclines toward benevolence. At first it is of necessity that
men attend to the public interest, afterward by choice. What had been
calculation becomes instinct. By dint of working for the good of his
fellow citizens, he in the end acquires a habit and taste for
serving them. (12)
Tocqueville here notes the importance of freedom and rights. But
the sentiment of mutual respect and public service was not fostered by
simple abstract notions of freedom. Rather, that sentiment was fostered
by freedom in the sense of a community public space free from laws and
rules emanating from the center. Long accustomed to looking out for
themselves and those with whom they shared their everyday lives,
Americans developed habits of public service and civil, even friendly,
interaction. They also conceived a high (even "exaggerated")
opinion of themselves and their own capacities. As a result,
suppose that an [American] individual thinks of some enterprise,
and that enterprise has a direct bearing on the welfare of society;
it does not come into his head to appeal to public authority for its
help. He publishes his plan, offers to carry it out, summons other
individuals to aid his efforts, and personally struggles against all
obstacles. No doubt he is often less successful than the state would
have been in his place, but in the long run the sum of all private
undertakings far surpasses anything the government might have done. (13)
To see the importance of this local "space" one need only
look to Tocqueville's own discussion of the decline of communities
in France over the course of the early modern era on account of
increasing administrative centralization. The expanding role of orders
coming from the center, whether as law or rules laid down by
administrative intendants appointed by the crown, meant the demise of
earlier social relations. These relations were far from optimal; they
were feudal and so highly "inegalitarian," to use a
contemporary word of great opprobrium, and they clearly allowed for
substantial abuses.
But these customary relations also bound people to one another,
imposing obligations on both the high- and the low-born.
"Reforms" from the center tore apart these relationships and,
with them, whole communities. They left peasants in particular without
hope of succor in bad times, and with increasing resentment toward those
who, freed from their duties, retained some of their "rights"
to things like monetary payments.
Now that [the aristocrat] had ceased to hold a dominant position,
he no longer was at pains...to help "his" peasants, to further their
interests, and to give them good advice This led to what might be
called a spiritual estrangement more prevalent and more pernicious in
its way than mere physical absenteeism. For in his dealings with his
tenants the landowner who lived on his estate often developed
sentiments and views that would, were he an absentee, have been those
of his agent. Like an agent he came to regard his tenants as mere
rent-payers and exacted from them the uttermost farthing to which the
law, or ancient usage, still entitled him, the result being that the
collection of such feudal dues as still existed was apt to seem even
more galling to the peasants than it had been in the heyday of
feudalism. (14)
Tocqueville was not pining for feudalism. His point was that the
rule of intendants and of various laws emanating from Paris tore apart
the customary social relations in French communities. Nor is
Tocqueville's lament any kind of screed against public action,
broadly conceived. Rather, it is a recognition of the need for local
communities to rest on social (and economic) relations rooted in local
custom and tradition. And this means that the prevalence of uniform laws
emanating from the center--meaning the federal government in
particular--is enervating to fundamental human relationships in a way
local action is, or at least was, not. As Tocqueville observed,
There was provision for the poor from the beginning in the states of
New England; there were strict regulations for the maintenance of
roads, with officials appointed to supervise them, the township had
public registers recording the conclusions of public deliberations and
the births, deaths, and marriages of the citizens; there were clerks
whose duty it was to keep these records; officials were appointed,
some to look after intestate property, others to determine the
boundaries of inherited lands, and many more whose chief function was
to maintain public order.
Thus, in Tocqueville's view, in the United States "the
law anticipates and provides in great detail for a multitude of social
needs of which in France we are still now but vaguely
conscious."(15) Two aspects of this passage stand out. First,
Tocqueville is noting the existence of laws and regulations at the state
level and administered, by and large, at the very local level. Second,
and perhaps more important, the list he gives of "provisions"
is, by contemporary standards, extremely modest. Roads, public records,
property relations, and public order: these were the essential elements
of governance that the French monarchy and even its successors failed to
address. While essential, rules and enforcement actions in these areas
hardly threatened to crowd out customary social relations or dissolve
any meaningful zone of prudence.
None of this is to say that there is no threat from excessive law
so long as it is local. Even the most local laws and regulations may be
frankly oppressive. One need mention only some of the more draconian
rules of local governments and even homeowners' associations (with
their minute regulation of signage, paint colors, and the like) to call
to mind the possibility of petty tyranny. But localism tends to produce
standards of behavior that maintain the essential relations of public
life. It does so in significant measure because these standards, being
the product of local associations themselves, have their roots in local
conditions and consent. At least as important, however, local standards
tend, or at least once tended, not to be statutory. They were the
product not of legislation but of custom. Custom, too, can be
restrictive, but it generally is preferable to legislation because of
its roots in the rational expectations of the people governed by it.
In this light it becomes clear what we have lost with the crowding
out of custom by detailed statutes emanating from Washington. Local
customs under our old common law tradition might have prescriptive
power--even in court. But it was power of a particular, limited sort.
Within the common law tradition it was recognized--even by judges--that
justice in court generally should be defined as vindicating the
reasonable expectations of the parties. This, in turn, meant that the
role of law was, wherever possible, to apply customary usage to the
particular facts of particular cases. The judge would look to previous
cases and to common practice in the locality to determine the general
understanding of the people in an area regarding what was right. If, for
example, pigs in a number of American colonies had been allowed to run
free for generations, then it would be up to farmers to fence out those
pigs. But if one lived in a colony in which the pigs had been fenced in,
while the crops had not, then it was up to the one raising pigs to pen
them. Violation of either custom would mean paying damages, as one
should expect in light of local practice.
New laws--statutes--clearly had an important role to play within
such a system. When a custom came to be recognized as outdated, no
longer workable, or simply wrong, the people acting through their
legislature had the power to overrule that custom. They also could
simply change their customary practices. Of course, such change
generally is slow, resting on consensus. But customs would change, grow,
and even die, to be replaced by newer, more fitting customs. Whether by
statute or by customary development, change could be accomplished
without necessarily producing radical alterations in the more general
customs of the community.
The invisible foot existed in customary as well as statutory life,
but that foot was smaller and less liable to do great damage in a
community attentive to the need for continuity. The stability gained in
communities respectful of common, customary law provided for social
relations fostering a confidence (or, to revert to Montesquieu, a
tranquility of mind) conducive to peaceful relations--and to conflicts
liable to adjudication and otherwise unlikely to escalate to dangerous
levels.
Alas, such a system is not conducive to governance within a system
dependent on detailed codes of conduct. If the people and/or their
government has become hostile to custom, or fearful lest people choose
the "wrong" custom in particular instances, or simply
determined that everyone must act alike and according to the
"best" rule determined by the lawmakers, the common law
becomes more a nuisance than anything else. Custom becomes something
judges may use to "fill in the gaps" of a statutory scheme in
a way that may be too retrograde, too traditional, too customary, for
the tastes of the drafters of statutory schemes. Then the law must stamp
out custom altogether with written rules of decision. (16) The power of
custom is then lost, and with it an essential defense of community and
ordered liberty. We are finally left with only statutes--expressions of
the lawmakers' will--to rule us. And there will be no reliable way
to limit the reach of these laws and the restriction of our liberty, our
certainty, and our ability to live in stable, decent communities.
(1.) Some readers may find the parallel with the German notion of
rechtsstaatto be obvious here. However, an examination of the inclusive
and expansive nature of that ideal, or its impottation into the United
States by Progressive scholars, is beyond the scope of this article.
(2.) Baron de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, trans. Thomas
Nugent (New York: Hafner Publishing, 1949), 151, 351-52.
(3.) I leave aside various indices "ranking" nations in
regard, for example, to the level of freedom they enjoy. Such indices
inevitably do, in fact, use mathematical calculations concerning issues
from violence to corruption, but rarely in regard to the simple extent
of regulation. Thus, social democracies like those in Sweden routinely
score at the top of the lists.
(4.) Lon Fuller, Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1964), 46-49.
(5.) Probably the most important quotation on this point is from
Smith's Wealth of Nations:
By preferring the support of domestic to that oi foreign industry, he
intends only his own security; and by directing that industry in such a
manner as its produce may be of the greatest value, he intends only his
own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an
invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention.
Nor is it always the worse for the society that it was not part of it.
By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the society
more effectually than when he really intends to promote it. I have
never known much good done by those who affected to trade for the
public good. It is an affectation,indeed, not very common among
merchants, and very few words need be employed in dissuading them from
it.
(6.) The classic work providing such a critique is Charles Murray,
Losing Ground (New York: Basic Books, 1984).
(7.) See Marvin Olasky, The Tragedy of American Compassion
(Washington, DC: Regnery, 1994).
(8.) See Philip Hamburger, Separation of Church and State
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 2004).
(9.) Again, this is Hamburger's argument in Separation of
Church and State.
(10.) Summa Theologiae, 1-2.91.4.
(11.) See "The Constitution and Community," in Community
and Tradition: Conservative Perspectives on the American Experience, ed.
George W. Carey and Bruce P. Frohnen (Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Littlefield, 1998).
(12.) Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, trans. George
Lawrence (New York: Harper, 2000), 512-13.
(13.) Ibid., 95
(14.) Alexis de Tocqueville, The Old Regime and the Revolution,
trans. Stuart Gilbert (New York: Anchor, 1955), 121-22.
(15.) Ibid., 44-45.
(16.) For decades now the Supreme Court has upheld federal statutes
purporting to regulate interstate commerce that in fact are aimed at
some purely local, intrastate activity. The rationalization proffered
has been that such regulations will be upheld when the regulation of
noncommercial, intrastate activity in question is an "essential
part of a larger regulation of economic activity, in which the
regulatory scheme could be undercut unless the intrastate activity were
regulated." See United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 561 (1995).
Bruce P. Frohnen is professor of law at Ohio Northern University.