THE DEMISE OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY?
Lewis, Paul H.
Political Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Authors and
Arguments, edited by Catherine H. Zuckert (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011)
Are political theorists becoming an endangered species? Pierre
Manent, a French philosopher and frequent contributor to Modern Age and
other ISI publications, thinks that "the twentieth century has
witnessed the disappearance, or withering away, of political
philosophy." In this volume Professor Zuckert has put together a
collection of essays about eighteen thinkers "to demonstrate the
richness and vitality of philosophical reflection on political issues in
the twentieth century in response to the many observations of its
weakness, if not death." Each essay summarizes a political
philosopher's career and discusses his principal works.
The volume is divided into four parts. Part 1 is intended to
provide examples of the "three basic alternatives in the early
twentieth century." John Dewey represents liberal democracy; Carl
Schmitt, a Nazi, represents fascism; and Antonio Gramsci is perhaps the
most notable Marxist theorist of that time. So far, so good; but why
only three basic alternatives? Conservatism also had its defenders in
the early twentieth century. Vilfredo Pareto, Hilaire Belloc, and Jose
Ortega y Gasset come immediately to mind, yet not one of them makes an
appearance in this collection.
Part 2 is called "Emigre Responses to World War II" and
covers four continental European philosophers who fled to America or
Britain to escape communism and Nazism: Leo Strauss, Eric Voegelin, Yves
Simon, and Hannah Arendt. Of these four, Arendt became the best known
through her path-breaking work on totalitarianism, which outraged the
Left by arguing that Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia were essentially
alike. Voegelin came to much the same conclusion, although he used the
more confusing term Gnosticism instead of totalitarianism. Indeed, much
of Voegel in's writing is incomprehensible. Here is an example from
The New Science of Politics: "The attempt at constructing an eidos
of history will lead into the fallacious immanentization of the
Christian eschaton." Translation: the totalitarians' goal of
constructing an earthly utopia is a corruption of the Christian belief
in heaven. Strauss, in contrast to Arendt and Voegelin, reacted against
the totalitarians' ideological propaganda by retreating into
philosophical detachment and skepticism. For him, ideology seeks to move
the masses, while philosophy is only for the rational few. Simon was a
liberal French Catholic who refused to live under the Vichy regime.
Though undoubtedly a worthy figure, I don't think that he was as
important as Raymond Aron, who ought to have been included in this
section.
Part 3, on "the revival of liberal political philosophy,"
serves to illustrate how easily abused the term liberalis in modern
America. In its classical sense, which is still used in Europe and Latin
America, it meant essentially limited government and free enterprise.
That is how Friedrich Hayek and Michael Oakeshott used the term, and
what Isaiah Berlin meant by "negative liberty" (freedom from
coercion). "Positive liberty," for Berlin, meant securing the
means to do what one wishes. He opposed this because he thought it would
easily degenerate into collectivism and social engineering, which is
more or less what "progressive liberals" like H. L. A. Hart,
John Rawls, and Richard Rorty advocate. Hart, a legal theorist, rejected
traditional morality based on Christianity in the name of liberating the
individual to pursue his personal desires. Rawls sought to revive
seventeenth-century social contract theory to justify income
redistribution. Rorty attacks the Enlightenment belief in universally
valid natural rights based on reason as being bourgeois and out of date,
especially property rights. For him, what is right depends on the
historical context, which is to say that "justice" is whatever
contemporary "progressives" say it is.
Part 5, "Critiques of Liberalism," carries the attacks on
bourgeois society and capitalism far beyond the progressives into the
wastelands of nihilism, Stalinism, and Catholic communitarianism.
Jean-Paul Sartre first gained fame as an exponent of existentialism,
which encouraged individuals to preserve their humanity by rejecting the
values of corrupt bourgeois society. Unfortunately, his experience with
the Nazi occupation of France also converted him to communism. For most
of his adult life, he tried to reconcile these contradictory beliefs by
refusing to recognize that Stalin's Russia was dedicated to
stamping out any sign of individuality.
He never succeeded in squaring this circle but always insisted that
communism would end individual alienation by creating a just society.
Michel Foucault and Jurgen Habermas offer a post-Marxist, New Left
approach to replacing the bourgeois order. Like Gramsci, they see its
downfall coming most likely through a displacement of the old culture
rather than an economic collapse. Foucault saw capitalist society as
permeated at all levels with power hierarchies but thought they could be
overthrown by a countercul-tural offensive. It is unfortunate that this
collection of essays does not include any neo-Machiavellians such as
Vilfredo Pareto, Gaetano Mosca, or Roberto Michels as an antidote to
such utopian pleading. The reader would learn that all politics is
essentially a struggle for power in which success depends on
organization, that organization means hierarchy, and therefore that all
revolutions result in the rise of a new ruling elite. That is certainly
more realistic than what Foucault proposed.
Habermas looks to the new professional, educational, and managerial
classes created by modern communications and information systems to
gradually overcome capitalism. These new classes are more cosmopolitan
in their outlook and allegiances. They reject traditional values in
favor of global standards of ethics and, Habermas thinks, will
eventually create a world government that will impose those more humane
standards. Readers who have been following the current turmoil in the
European Union may have some doubts about these predictions.
Lastly, there are the Catholic communitarians, Charles Taylor and
Alasdair MacIntyre. Both are practicing Roman Catholics and both reject
the individualistic, materialistic outlook of Enlightenment liberalism.
Both were attracted to Marxism in their youth and still identify with
the "humanistic" Left. MacIntyre has a more developed concept
of communitarianism, although he rejects the label as applied to
himself. Opposing modern capitalism and its appetitive consumer society,
he wants people to revert to small local communities that would opt out
of the nation-state and the market economy. Taylor, who does call
himself a communitarian, would presumably agree. For non-communitarians,
in which party I include myself, this sounds like a reactionary arcadia
reminiscent of the early medieval hamlet--you know: before the obnoxious
bourgeoisie appeared with their deplorable secularism, tawdry commerce,
and vulgar tastes.
So, is political philosophy withering away? Professor Zuckert
admits in her Introduction that the natural sciences' prestige has
made social scientists want to imitate them. Normative questions--the
meat and drink of philosophy--are ruled out in favor of topics that lend
themselves to empirical analysis and quantification. The philosophers
discussed in this collection insist that, because human beings can
choose how to act, or not act, they can't be studied like rocks,
molecules, or planets. What is more, the social scientist himself has
opinions and values, so he cannot be completely objective about his
research. So far those arguments have failed to reverse the positivist trend. Most social scientists would reply that the standards of the
"hard sciences" are the correct ones, even if the "soft
sciences" can only approximate them. The alternative is to write
polemics and promote some ideology, which is what many of the political
philosophers in this volume have done. That's unobjectionable if
your goal is to change the world, and who would deny that Gramsci,
Hayek, and Foucault have influenced politics in the West? But, as Leo
Strauss reminds us, ideology and philosophy are very different things.
Perhaps, as he argued, political philosophy is suitable only for a
few skeptical intellectuals. In that case we can say that it isn't
dying out; it's just settling down to its natural, restricted
constituency.
Paul H. Lewis is a retired professor of political science from
Tulane University.