Social work ethics: is a moral consensus possible?
Noble, Carolyn ; Briskman, Linda
Introduction
Social Work as a profession is concerned about those people who are
the most isolated, the disenfranchised and the poor in society. Social
workers use their professional activity, skills, information and
resources to address these inequalities and work toward individual and
community empowerment (Holland and Kilpatrick 1991:138). In this task
the social work profession argues that knowledge development,
information and skills are not in themselves enough to carry out this
particular professional and societal responsibility and the practice
decisions which result. Although facts and skills are important, ethical
judgements cannot be made on the grounds of factual information or
professional skill alone. In this sense ethical decision making is
recognised as an important component of practice (Fleck-Henderson 1991).
Guidelines for ethical decision making are set out in the
profession's Code of Ethics and are, in the main, regarded as a
collective expression of agreed upon values which unite the social work
profession nationally and internationally. In the social work curriculum
the study of ethics is an important component of the professional
development of the student.
The social work profession, like most professions, developed a Code
of Ethics in order to set out the ethical standards that professional
social workers are expected to follow. In particular, the Code of Ethics
outlines the philosophy, purpose and standard of practice determined by
the profession. Berliner details the important functions of a Code of
Ethics:
It imparts knowledge of the profession's standards of behaviour
to the laity and to clients, helps socialise aspirants to
the profession, clarifies the demarcation between social work
and other professions, helps define the social worker-client
relationship, supports clients rights and interests and provides
the basis for evaluating whether a violation of ethical
conduct has occurred. (1989:69)
However Rhodes (1985) in analysing the American National
Association of Social Worker's (NASW) Code of Ethics argues that
these guidelines are in fact so general, and at times posit such
contradictory principles, that the result is a set of principles without
any clear ethical framework and only a piecemeal political structure
(Rhodes 1985:13).
Although social work has always had a progressive element within
its ranks, it is only in the last twenty years that important
sociological developments have had a dramatic effect on the social work
knowledge base used for understanding social and political relations.
These developments ultimately challenged the hegemony of conventional
social work theories of 'person reform' and 'social
reform'. The first challenge came from the radical social work
movement informed by the classical Marxian perspective of class
relations (Bailey and Brake 1975; Galper 1975 ; Moreau 1979). This was
followed by the critical theorists (such as Mullaly 1993) and, more
recently, the post modernist perspective (eg Best and Kellner 1993;
Leonard 1994; Yeatman 1994), which has resulted in a direct challenge to
the underlying social and political context of traditional practice. The
major difficulty with these critiques is that so far, they have received
inconsistent treatment in the literature and have been slow to progress
beyond critical analysis of conventional social work. While there have
been some individual attempts to develop an analysis and identify a form
of practice that integrates the individual and structural perspective
(see McNay 1992; Fook 1993; Thompson 1993; Mullaly 1993), in the main
the conventional view and the progressive view stand in opposition to
one another, representing conflicting philosophies and ideologies. The
challenge of this paper is to address the moral and ethical concerns of
the social work profession in the light of these theoretical
developments and identify the dilemmas they pose to the conventional
understanding about moral and ethical consensus. Particular attention is
given to the Australian Code of Ethics.
Principally, this Code of Ethics, in the main, has been set apart
from the emerging social and political debate, from incorporating
notions of difference or specific notions of social justice and from the
competing philosophical world views that characterise these positions.
In fact there is support in the literature and in practice for the
position that ethical codes should be, and are, considered separately
from the social and political contexts of social work activity (Rhodes
1985: 15). For example, Rhodes argues, in relation to the American
National Association of Social Workers (NASW), that their Code of Ethics
is seen primarily as a guide to practice behaviour, as a set of
principles without any clear underlying ethical or political
justification or framework.
This is not to say that some critical thinking with regard to
ethics and ethical issues cannot be found in the literature. Dobrin
(1989), for example, argues that ethics is and should emerge as an
important consideration for the social work profession. However, much of
the recent focus has taken the form of: exploring codes of ethics and
analysing particular moral dilemmas (Siporin 1982, 1983; Abramson 1983;
Rhodes 1992); highlighting the sex difference in ethical judgements
(Gillian 1982; Dobrin 1989); ethics as control for professional
misconduct (Berliner 1989); and ethics and moral reasoning (Fleck-Henderson 1991). However, very little attention has been given to
a critical perspective with regard to moral reasoning and the political
and social context of that activity.
Re-conceptualising ethical debates
The most important work on critical thinking with regard to moral
reasoning can be found in Rhodes' (1985, 1992) work. Her research
provides an overview of key ethical perspectives and the moral
commitments they pre-suppose, confronting the social worker with a
confusing and contradictory array of belief systems (for example,
utilitarianism, duty-based Kantianism, rights theories, Marxian ethics
and relativism and more latterly post-modernist theory) as well as those
of other cultures and religions, which characterise our pluralist society. Ethical judgements are made, she argues, according to our
commitment to one's belief system, which must be understood in its
social and historical context and the 'purpose' it serves. In
addition, her work elaborates on the dilemmas of ethical conflicts
inherent in the human services sector, in the social worker's
various responsibilities to clients, the agency, the profession and
society and in the worker's particular ethical and political
assumptions inherent in this activity. Therefore, given the complexities
of social work decisions and the conflicting choices of various ethical
belief systems, social work could benefit from having systematic
guidelines for resolving ethical issues that reflect the current
concerns of its professional activity (Rhodes 1985,1992).
Rhodes (1985:12,13), also notes that the absence of any explicitly
ethical or political framework comes out most clearly in what is said
about the social worker's responsibilities to society. She argues
that the responsibility to promote social justice and a better society
can only have substance if we are told what makes for social justice and
general welfare. In American society there is, in fact, no general
agreement on these fundamental concepts. The authors would add that by
implication, there is also no clear agreement on the ethical assumptions
informing western society's belief systems.
Rhodes further states that given the existence of competing points
of view, often informed by opposing political perspectives within the
profession, a code of ethics, if it is to have any real value or to be
of any real use, could serve as a focal point for reflecting on these
basic conflicts and invite serious dialogue about these differences.
This should take place, however, without the expectation that this
should, or would, necessarily arrive at a professional consensus about
the sort of society we are trying to create (Rhodes 1985:183). To date
there has been very little response to this challenge.
Social work theory development
Social work theory development, on the other hand, has not stood
still. In the past twenty years there has been a direct challenge to the
underlying social and political context of traditional practice. The
radical social work movement (Bailey and Brake 1975; Galper 1975; Moreau
1979) challenged the psychoanalytical focus of casework as narrow and
politically repressive, and in response concern was turned to the socio-
economic structural inequalities of clients in the capitalist system. In
addition, feminist social workers drew attention to the role of
patriarchal power relations and the nature and form of discrimination in
relation to women (Dominelli and McLeod 1989). The gradual
acknowledgment of the diversity of oppression followed, with black
people, ethnic minorities, gay men and lesbians, people with different
abilities and generational positions highlighting the specifics of
oppression for a large number of citizens. Social work in the 1990s
subsequently became aware of discrimination related to the power
relations associated with class, 'race', gender, sex,
disability and age. This prompted the development of an
anti-discriminatory practice relevant to all spheres of social work
theory and practice (Langan and Day 1992; Mullaly 1993; Fook 1993).
This anti-discriminatory perspective directly challenged the status
quo by positing a theoretical framework for transforming the
profession's understanding of social relations and thereby posing a
direct challenge to traditional theory and practice. This deliberate
move away from the psychological focus to a more sociological
orientation was to herald further intellectual developments. A more
diverse and pluralist notion of social agency and interaction emerged.
The link between identity and oppression became significant.
Identity
Social workers who seek to develop an anti-discriminatory practice
need not only to incorporate the social in relation to the individual
but also to appreciate how the social element has a major impact on
identity, particularly in political, social and economic terms (Thompson
1993). Hudson argues the need for a greater awareness of the structural
aspects of identity. In particular
the ways in which structural factors such as race, class and gender
shape individual personality development and behaviour are
considerable. It is important that these factors are acknowledged
in the curriculum of social work training course and in the
assessment that social workers make of their clients. (Hudson,
quoted in Thompson 1993: 81)
This perspective shifts the debate from a monolithic and/or
spurious notion of 'hierarchy of oppressions' to the
acceptance that 'the dynamics of oppression are like a kaleidoscope where the configuration of, and relationships between, different forms
of oppression are constantly moving and changing' (Thompson
1993:131).
This development introduced the notion of individuals as
dialectically related to the social structure, where the structure and
process interact and reinforce each other, since it is argued that power
is manifested at all levels of people's lives (McNay 1992).
Individuals, then are both the site and subjects of discursive struggle
for identity. The individual is constantly subjected to discourse and
through thought, speech or writing embraces quite contradictory modes of
subjectivity at different moments in history (Weedon 1987). The concept
of 'difference' and the emphasis on diversity has (perhaps
naively) extended social work's theoretical concerns into the
development of a more pluralist notion of theory development that
incorporates some concepts from the postmodernist theories.
Difference
The debate within feminist discourse first highlighted the
difficulties in discussing specific categories of peoples (eg women)
when the traditional left identified serious antagonisms among women in
relation to their class differences (Langan and Day 1992). Black
feminists further challenged the earlier feminist movement's
universal claim that it represented the interests of all women, and the
implicit ethnocentricism and racism of the earlier movement's
assumptions (Langan and Day 1992:4). Further, critique from lesbians,
older women and women with disabilities helped to bury the old
simplicities of a unitary category for women which resulted in the
gradual emergence of a more diverse form of 'pluralistic'
feminism with the assumption that there can be no political project
common for all women (Langan and Day 1992). This was set in the context
of the wider development of the post-structuralist and post-modernist
theories, where there was general agreement in the rejection of the
notion of a unified subject as an agent of social and political change,
with the emphasis on the local, the particular and the different
(Lovibond 1989). Difference becomes important and significant.
Barrett (1987, in Langan and Day 1992) distinguishes two distinct
and to some extent contradictory theories of difference. First, there is
the emphasis on 'experiential diversity', where personal
experience of each woman's experience is assumed to guarantee
authenticity and legitimacy. Second, there is the postmodernist
conception of difference as 'positional meaning' (Barrett
1987). This concept challenges the singular notions of rationalism and
universalism and the kind of democratic order they have informed.
Further, it identifies those people positioned as 'other' to
the status quo who, subsequently, find themselves marginalised in terms
of citizenship status and rights (Yeatman 1994: viii). In this analysis
examples of people being 'othered' are women, people from
non-English speaking backgrounds, Aboriginals and Torres Strait Islander
peoples, lesbians and gay men, children, the elderly, people with
disabilities and ethnic and religious minorities. Their exclusionary
position as 'Other', denies them a politically contested
space, which results in discriminatory practices and the lived
experience of oppression. The acknowledgment of these differently
constructed positions, from a postmodernist perspective, mitigates
against a uniformity of struggle; a jettisoning of the assumption of any
common ground within the layers of oppression including the dangerous
illusion of a commonality in experience (Yeatman 1994).
In other words these various specifications of difference cannot
enunciate a shared narrative of social change and emancipation. In fact,
grouping the different positions of these social actors together can
introduce a 'moral terrorism' practiced on self and others
(Yeatman 1994:7). The argument here is that stigmatised, marginalised
and/or differently positioned social actors cannot be totalised into one
large, broader struggle. Thus the universality of oppression and the
notion of revolution lose cogency, for example, feminist specifications
of agency contrast with masculinist specifications of agency; black and
indigenous peoples with white ethnocentrism; able bodied people with
disabled; and gay and lesbian sexuality with heterosexuality (Yeatman
1994). In accepting differently constructed discourses there is no
privileged position of generality. Postmodern theorists then abandon the
very concept of social system and society for a more fragmentary analysis, for a microanalysis of discrete institutions, discourses and
practices (Best and Kellner 1993). For post-modernists, all 'that
is possible is for differently positioned groups or individuals to come
together to offer their perspective on how they should decide and manage
their shared conditions' (Yeatman 1994:87). The emancipatory assumptions implied in the secular and rational concepts of equality,
justice, empowerment, rights and responsibilities also come into
question.
Impact on social work theory, practice and ethics
These theoretical developments in social work theory represent not
just another addition to ideas, but a fundamental challenge to norms and
values, to the whole process of thinking and moral reasoning, which has
held sway for centuries (Langan and Day 1992). The radical perspective
challenged the simplicity of individual resistance which was gradually
replaced with the recognition and acceptance of a collective, broad
based approach to the resolution of social problems, exposing the need
to create a new value system incorporating the notion of power and
inequality in social justice terms (McNay 1992:55). Initially this
resulted in the marginalisation of radical social work practice from
mainstream thought. However in recent times this critique has gathered
more momentum. For example, the emphasis on combating discrimination has
to some extent been incorporated into the training and practice of
social work which is more evident in the development of recent social
work curriculum in the 'new' universities' social work
programs (see Royal Melbourne Institute of Technology, Victorian
Institute of Technology and University of Western Sydney, Macarthur
curriculum documents). The gradual acceptance of the radical critique in
practice has resulted in various attempts to develop a framework in
which particular forms of oppression could be analysed so that
structural and individual perspectives are integrated in order to
develop an empowering mode of practice (Moreau 1979; McNay 1992; Fook
1993; Thompson 1993).
Aspects of the postmodern challenge, in particular the notion of
identity, difference, fragmentation and the rejection of binary
differentiation (Barrett 1987; Yeatman 1994) are newer concepts that are
developing currency. Further they are creating a tension between the
notions of social group change and the notions of individual difference
and positional meaning, challenging any project of collective resistance
based on the interconnections between people's oppression. In
particular the emerging voices of the indigenous peoples and from within
the multi-cultural debate highlight the almost irresolvable and
irreducibly multiple perspectives of voices and differences within
contemporary western society, challenging the coherence of a shared
experience of discrimination and oppression (Yeatman 1994: 83). Both
these theoretical developments place the profession's code of
practice as the embodiment of ethical and moral behaviour into question,
and introduce tensions between their competing and contradictory
theoretical points of view.
Social work code of ethics: self-determination, individual freedom
and concepts of social justice and social change
The intention in this section is to explore what these developments
in contemporary social theory imply for the Australian Social Work Code
of Ethics and to raise issues for further debate and research. In
particular the focus for analysis will be on the notion of self
determination and individual freedom. Additionally, the generalised
notions of justice, empowerment and social change will be explored as
they relate to ethical behaviour. An examination of other Codes of
Ethics from North America and New Zealand complements this analysis.
These countries were selected as all have recently revised their Codes.
Additionally, each of these countries is familiar with the critique of
the radical perspective as well as the emerging post-modernist
perspective. A review of their revised standards might reveal whether
these theory developments have impacted on the ethical and moral
considerations of the social work profession.
The current Australian Social Work Code of Ethics (1990) was
developed with direct reference to the International Federation of
Social Workers' General Meeting, Puerto Rico, July 1976 and was
undertaken within the aspirations of The Universal Declaration of Human
Rights (U.N. General Assembly, December 10, 1948) both in recognising
its principles and promoting its observance. In 1990 it was revised and
the focus was broadened to include reference to the achievement of
'social justice' while the 'clients' of the social
work profession included societies.
In reviewing the current Code, it is clear that moral and ethical
evaluation in relation to practice issues imply a universality of
ethical claims which are measured by an implied (but not stated) concept
of logic and reason as well as notion of agency. For example, in the
first section it states, 'social workers are dedicated to service
for the welfare and self-fulfilment of human beings as well as the
societies in which they live. The achievement of social justice is thus
co-equal with the attainment of fulfilment for the individual'
(AASW 1990:1).
No definitions of justice and welfare are given, but an assumed
political liberalism is implied. In its value statement the Code
outlines the profession's broad brush commitment to social justice:
Every human being has a unique dignity irrespective of nationality,
ethnicity, social and economic status, gender, sexual preference,
age, beliefs, or contribution to society and regardless of its form
each society has the obligation to pursue social justice, protect
its members from harm and provide maximum benefits for all.
(AASW1990:1)
Finally, in the section on Standards of Practice, the
profession's commitment to social justice is stated by delivering a
global statement:
The social worker will act to prevent and eliminate discrimination
against any per son or group on the basis of race, gender, sexual
orientation, age, religion, national origin, marital status,
political belief, mental or physical disability or any other
preference or personal characteristic, condition or status.
(AASW 1990: 3)
These principles, while simplistic and vague, could suggest a
pluralistic society which encourages diversity of belief (Rhodes
1992:13). But what are the shared values that it is premised upon? Is it
that social workers should always act to bring about the greatest amount
of good or happiness, or the least amount of harm in the world as a
whole? Or is it the acceptance of the intrinsic value of freedom itself,
freedom to act in particular ways and/or freedom to be protected from
the arbitrary acts of others? These represent two quite different
ethical positions, suggesting different political assumptions, even
within the notion of a pluralistic society.
Other principles and standards in the document reiterate the more
traditional concepts pertaining to the individuality of the client.
"The social worker will make every effort to foster maximum self
determination and social responsibility on the part of the clients and,
the social worker will apprise clients of their rights and the
implication of services available to them" (AASW 1990: 2, 5).
The rest of the Code refers to more traditional aspects of practice
such as developing social work knowledge, integrity of the profession,
service and professional conduct But is there agreement about what
reflects contemporary social work practice issues? Again there is an
assumption that there is general agreement about the basic requirements
a society must meet in order for individuals to be treated with respect
and dignity. For differing political perspectives this is not the case.
For example a Marxian perspective would imply working towards more
reciprocal relations between client and worker and for a more democratic
decision-making as well as for more resource allocation to the poor and
disadvantaged. This position would conflict with more rights based
theories where society is viewed as a battleground of different
interests, where individual interests must be balanced against those of
others and where, in the main, the dominant view takes precedence
(Rhodes 1992:33,37). The post-modernist perspective would reject any
possibility of 'transcendental' meaning or purpose,
emphasising 'meanings constructed through necessarily fragmented
discourses' (Barrett in Langan and Day 1992:4). Let's now look
elsewhere for other perspectives.
The Code of Ethics of the Canadian Association of Social Workers,
formulated in 1983, has a similar commitment to social justice
principles as its Australian counterpart. It states that social work
itself is founded on humanitarian and egalitarian ideals and is
committed to the values of acceptance, self determination and respect of
individuality and
to the development and disciplined use of scientific knowledge
regarding human and societal behaviours; to the development of
resources to meet individual, group, national and international
needs and aspirations; and to the achievement of social justice
for all. (CASW 1983:2)
In addressing social justice, social workers are
pledged to serve without discrimination on any grounds of race,
ethnicity, language, religion, marital status, gender, sexual
orientation, age, abilities, economic status, political affiliation
or national ancestry. (CASW 1983:2)
As to the 'how' it states,
Social work is a profession committed to the goal of effecting social
changes in society and the ways in which individuals develop within
their society for the benefit of both. Advancement towards this
purpose is achieved through the complementarity of social reform
and therapeutic approaches premised in the belief that social
conditions of humanity can be
bettered. (CASW 1983:2)
In the Social Work Declaration section, point 10 states 'I
will act to effect social change for the overall benefit of
humanity' (CASW 1983: 2). The last section, on Responsibility to
Society, refers (in part) to the prevention and elimination of
discrimination on the basis of race, ethnicity, gender, sexual
orientation and to such activities as advocating for policy and
legislative change to improve social conditions and to improve social
justice and the expansion of choice and opportunity for disadvantaged
and oppressed groups. However the bulk of the Code discusses such
factors as integrity, quality service, social worker-client
relationship, confidential information, outside interests,
responsibility to the workplace and responsibility to the profession in
respect to individuals. The latter implies an agency for the individual
as if the person (as a singular category) is afforded full participatory
rights with a socially provided position designated with specific
privileges. This is surely a paradoxical position for those persons
defined as marginal, disenfranchised, excluded and 'other'.
The 1990 Code of Ethics of the National Association of Social
workers (USA) is probably the most 'conservative' of those
reviewed. The overall focus in regard to ethical behaviour relates
social work actions towards clients in terms of competence, personal
development, integrity, scholarship and research. It states that
'the social worker should serve clients with devotion, loyalty,
determination, and the maximum application of professional skill and
competence' (NASW 1990:2). In relation to colleagues,
organisations, and the profession as a whole 'the social worker
should uphold and advance the values, ethics, knowledge and mission of
the profession' (NASW 1990:2). The last section, The Social
Worker's Ethical Responsibility to Society, makes reference to the
elimination of discrimination (acknowledging specifics of race, colour,
sex and sexual orientation), as well as the promotion of conditions
which encourage respect for the diversity of cultures, the improvement
of social conditions and the promotion of social justice. However, again
there is no clear notion of what sort of social justice, what sort of
relationships and what form of general welfare is being referred to.
In this brief overview of the values and principles governing
social work practice as outlined in the Code of Ethics in Australia,
Canada and the United States of America, it is evident that each of
these countries is informed by and places a high value on individual
independence and on the homogeneity of the client, characterised by the
liberal democratic philosophy. This is despite espousing some
anti-discriminatory concepts. This is particularly evident in the focus
on self determination and the goal of personal autonomy and personal
liberation as defined in each of these countries' Code of Ethics.
In essence then, each Code of Ethics, it can be argued, implies a
liberal construction of group identity where all persons (clients and
workers) are regarded as having full and active participation in all
aspects of the society and polity to which they belong (Yeatman 1994).
This is contradictory to the progressive critique that recognises
oppression, discrimination and exclusion of certain social groupings.
There is no recognition of structural disadvantage and marginalisation
from society as the clients are accorded a clearly bounded integrity,
viability and citizenship in which they are assumed to have equal and
full participation. This is a classic liberal premise, one which does
not easily accommodate ambiguities, contradictions, multiplicities of
intention and purpose that vulnerable groups represent. This liberal,
methodological individualism treats the group in question as an
individual, more specifically a corporate individual with a homogeneity
of purpose and perspective (Yeatman 1994:81). This notion of
individuality also supports the middle class notion of professions in
their role of assuring status, individuality, resources, access to
decision making, social mobility and more life choices to those who are
members of this particular group. But is there a consensus on the notion
of individuality and its concept of social justice and social change?
What implications then would there be for a progressive form of
practice?
Discussion: Australian code of ethics
1. Self-determination and individual freedom
In asserting the value of the individual in relation to freedom and
autonomy the Australian Code of Ethics implies a specific notion of the
person and of agency with a mutual recognition and existence. This could
mean one of two concepts. First, it could represent what Porter defines
as a 'static autonomy', that is, one that pursues knowledge
and being by severing subject from object and emanates from an impetus
to control knowledge, possessions or persons (1991:116,181). This notion
of individual is based on the utilitarian view of individual freedom
where all individuals are entitled to a minimum of freedom and where all
other individuals be restrained from depriving anyone of this right. By
implication the model citizen is represented as a rationally-orientated,
freely contracting subject However, the progressive critique would
disagree. For example, when focusing on the issue of gender, the
feminist critique would argue that in this context human agency would
systematically equate with male nature, rights and expressions, leaving
woman as a disembodied subject, unanchored in history (Porter 1991).
This concern about exclusion would also be expressed by the elderly, the
differently abled and people with different sexual preferences and
cultural backgrounds to the dominant norm.
Second, it could represent an acceptance of a 'dynamic
autonomy' in the Frankfurt School tradition where 'it is only
in conjunction with other self actualising selves that freedom can be
assumed to be a principle of communal life' (Porter 1991:117). The
concept of agency in this sense stresses a mutuality of interests and
well being which incorporates an autonomy that repudiates separateness,
control or domination and 'provides scope for radical consequences
in relationships in the private and public domains' (Porter
1991:117). This perspective emanates from the idea of personal strength
facilitated through interaction with others, that prompts a general
re-evaluation of personal capacities for creating and choosing
alternatives that neither oppress others, nor are intrinsically
oppressive (Porter 1991:181). Everyone should have the freedom to think
and act differently from others.
No systematic evaluation of the notion of individuality mentioned
in the context of the Australian Code's principles and practices
has been articulated or evaluated. The meaning of individual agency is
thus left unaddressed and the contradictions and ambiguities for
interpretations emerge. What can be implied is that the use of the
'dynamic autonomy' is probably what guides the Code's
principles in that it would be consistent with the notion 'all and
equally different'. In experiencing a positive relationship between
one's own individuality and that of others, this autonomous self
chooses in ways that involve his or her understanding of his or her
connectedness and of how the capacity to choose is enhanced by the
wealth (the social capital) which he or she shares with the
political community of selves to which he or she belongs. (Yeatman
1994:79)
This position situates individuals within a self-determining
political community of self determining individuals (Yeatman 1994:79).
However if we accept the postmodernist notion of differently positioned
subjects rather than the liberal respect for the 'difference'
of the 'minority voice' (which it is argued can only be
expressed as one voice), then the marginalised, stigmatised, poor and/or
differently positioned social actors cannot be totalised into one big
collective struggle or assumed to share a unified value and moral
perspective. The transparency of 'good intentions' hides a
dangerous illusion of collective good bounded by a community which
clearly defines those included and those to be excluded (Yeatman 1994).
2. Social justice and social change
In accepting the post-modernist perspective of
'difference' as differently constructed discourses by
differently positioned actors, then, a privileged position of generality
cannot exist. In accepting the notion that western societies are
differentiated, especially in the sense that there are various axes of
oppression which group people as either oppressed or dominant in
relation to race, ethnicity, gender, disability, age, sexuality and
class, it then seems inevitable that these principles of social grouping
work to generate distinct perspectives on what justice should look like,
and how it might operate (Yeatman 1994:87). In contesting their
oppression these groups posit a rethinking of justice and social change
in relation to their heterogeneity and differentiation. There is
evidence for this occurring. Black groups in America, for example, in
repositioning themselves in relation to their oppression (eg Black is
Beautiful), have directly contested their oppression. They have
re-valued and positively reclaimed what makes them different in relation
to the dominant norm. In human service work, for another example,
advocates of a multi cultural service incorporate cultural/ethnic
difference 'orientated to the substantive particularity of
individual and groups needs, where this orientation is a function of
ongoing dialogue between service users and service deliverers',
including cross-cultural dialogue (Yeatman 1994:86). Justice is assumed
to exist as a result of a negotiation as these differently positioned
groups or individuals come together to 'offer their perspective on
how they should decide and manage their shared life conditions'
(Yeatman 1994:87) and the provisional settlements they achieved as a
result. In other words, if people from the dominant group are to know
something about those from the oppressed group then we need to listen to
how they represent themselves, as there is no reason that permits us to
know the representation of those groups to which we do not belong, other
than from their self-representations (Yeatman 1994).
In accepting this perspective, what seems possible is to seek to
make connections, to build bridges between the various struggles for
self determination, to explore similarities, and to acknowledge
differences,
If there are to be legitimate connections made between differently
positioned representations these have to arise out of negotiated
agreements constructed by the differently positioned social actors
coming together to work on the terms of their coexistence.
(Yeatman 1994:7)
The question now is, how to achieve negotiated agreements with
those people who are traditionally discriminated against,
disenfranchised and oppressed in society as well as incorporating a
progressive view of justice and social change and have that reflected in
the Code of Ethics?
Starting point: the New Zealand code
The starting point, for any discussion on this issue must be based
on the assumption of specificity of perspective (Yeatman 1994). The New
Zealand Association of Social Workers (NZASW) Code of Ethics,
re-formulated in 1993, stands out as being important in this regard. It
attempts to accommodate difference in an emancipatory and social justice
sense which in turn offers some direction and hope. One of the three
parts of the Code of Ethics includes the Bicultural Code of Practice of
the NZASW. In particular it acknowledges that the legal, cultural and
governmental identity of Aotearoa should be based upon the Treaty of
Waitangi. (One of the Objects of the NZASW is to ensure that social work
in New Zealand is conducted in accordance with the articles contained in
this Treaty) (NZASW 1993:3).
The inclusion of The Treaty of Waitangi in the development of the
NZASW's Code of Ethics, where the significance of the Maori point
of view is to be negotiated in relation to a Pakeha point of view, is
evidence of the possibility of:
a partnership in which irresolvable different Maori and Pakeha
conceptions of justice are to find a voice, and in -which a shared
conception of justice must represent, not a rational consensus, but
some kind of negotiated compromise in relation to these different
conceptions of justice. (Yeatman 1994:88)
In addition to this incorporation of difference, the NZASW'S
Code of Ethics clearly commits itself to the radical notion of social
justice. Section A, Principles, is drawn from the International
Federation of Social Workers' Declaration of Ethical Principles
1990, and includes such headings as Liberation through Solidarity, Non
Discrimination, Democracy and Human Rights and Dismissal of Brutality.
Section B on the Social Workers Ethical Responsibilities has some
traditional individual focus although it places it in the context of
non-discrimination, gender, race, sexual orientation as well as advocacy
for social justice and inclusion. However Section C which includes the
Bicultural Code of Practice is the most ambitious, applying the
Principles in Section A to Maoris and giving a positive valuation of
difference. In its introductory statements to this Section, there is
recognition that power over resources and decision-making is at present
held by Pakehas, and acknowledgment that 'bicultural practice must
occur at a structural as well as an individual level to achieve social
justice for Maori' (NZASW 1993:1617).
In acknowledging that power is diffuse and not simply located in
one place, comes the recognition of the 'anti-determinist idea of
multiple and interacting subjectivities which connect to the
political' (Leonard 1994:19). In practice it is the articulation of
a Maori point of view, a Pakeha point of view and, in Australia, this
would incorporate an Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander point of
view. In so doing, it is argued a negotiated position would follow.
This example of oppressed groups coming together to offer their
different perspectives on how they should decide and manage their shared
life conditions is encouraging. The NZASW, in accommodating positional
difference of the Maori, illustrates that in attaining social justice
for oppressed groups and individuals a pragmatic wisdom is feasible. It
also indicates that in order to achieve social justice and full
participatory citizenship, oppressed groups in contesting their
oppression have to revalue and reclaim what is different in relation to
the dominant norm. As Yeatman argues, in order to do this e.g. to claim
a Maori position, 'they (oppressed groups) have had to contest the
norm itself and to reconceptualise a res publica in a manner that makes
it adequate to difference in a positive sense' (1994:87). This is
not simply liberal respect for 'difference' of the minority
voice but respect for 'difference' by articulating and
preserving differences to avoid potential repression and manipulation of
the stronger by imposing their will on the weaker, via the Eurocentrism
and androcentrism of modern thinking (Leonard 1994:19). The question now
is where does this argument lead to?
Where to now? issues for further research We argued earlier that,
despite theoretical developments, "progressive" social work
has been slow to make a significant impact in Australia and that a
structural examination of professional ethics has largely been ignored.
The challenge for the profession, it seems to us, is to ensure that
emerging perspectives in theory development contribute to a widening of
ethical and value frameworks by conceiving a way to incorporate
'difference' so that a pathway is found for social work ethics
to join with political considerations. There is clearly a tension
between the perceived need for a universal code to inform professional
practice and to reflect its value base, and the need to acknowledge
difference and to engage in anti-discriminatory practice.
It is our contention that the current AASW Code of Ethics does
little to reflect both theory development and the current realities of
Australian social work practice. The next challenge, as we see it, is
the exploration of the relationship between the professional Code of
Ethics and what might exist if it was developed and based on the radical
or progressive ideological/philosophical tenet, where progressive social
workers working with people experiencing discrimination were consulted
in the reworking of the Ethical Code and for this Code to be tested
against 'hard' cases from practice.
To this end, it would be our intention to adopt an action research
framework and explore with such workers in services such as women's
services, services for people from non-English speaking backgrounds, gay
and lesbian rights groups, Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander
peoples' organisations and disability services, the following
pertinent issues: What kind of society would you and your clients like
to live in? What is your and your client's concept of social
justice? Are they the same? What are the values underpinning your
practice and why? What is the service philosophy of the organisation
where you work? To what extent does the current Code inform your
practice? To what extent does the current Code reflect the unique nature
of the target group with which you work? and, What sort of Code of
Ethics should we have, if any at all?
If social work as a profession is genuine in its concern for
empowerment and with concepts of social justice, then a reworking of the
current Code of Ethics, in the light of this kind of research, is
urgently needed. Social work may then achieve a moral consensus
currently lacking within the profession.
References
Abramson, M. (1982) Ethical dilemmas in social work practice,
Social Work, Vol. 28, pp.31-35.
Australian Association of Social Workers (1990) Code of Ethics
Bailey, R. and Brake, M. (eds) (1975) Radical Social Work, Edward
Arnold, London.
Berliner, A. K. (1989) 'Misconduct in social work
practice', in Social Work, January, Vol. 34, pp.69-89.
Best, S. and Kellner, D. (1993) Postmodern Theory-Critical
Interrogations, The Guildford Press, New York.
Crook, S., Pakulski, J., Waters, M. (1992) Postmodernization:
Changes in Advanced Society, Sage, London
Dobrin, A. (1989) 'Ethical judgements of male and female
social workers', Social Work, September, Vol. 34(5), pp.451-455.
Canadian Association of Social Workers (1983) Code of Ethics.
Dominelli, L. and McLeod, E. (1989) Feminist Social Work,
Macmillan, London.
Fleck-Henderson, A. (1991) Moral reasoning in social work practice,
Social Service Review, June, pp. 185-202.
Fook, J. (1993) Radical Casework: A Theory of Practice, Allen &
Unwin, Melbourne.
Galper, J. (1975) The Politics of Social Services, Prentice Hall,
New Jersey.
Gilligan, C. (1982) In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and
Women's Development, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Holland, T. P. and Kilpatrick, A. C. (1991) 'Ethical issues in
social work: toward a grounded theory of professional ethics',
Social Work. Vol 36, No 2, March, pp. 138-144.
Langan, M. and Day, L. (eds) (1992) Women, Oppression and Social
Work: Issues in AntiDiscriminatory Practice, Routledge. London.
Leonard, P. (1994) 'Knowledge/power and postmodernism,
implications for the practice of a critical social work education',
Canadian Social Work Review, Vol 11, No 1, Winter, pp.11-26.
Lovibond, S. (1989) 'Feminism and postmodernism', New
Left Review, No, 179.
McNay, M (1993) 'Social work and power relations: toward a
framework for an integrated practice', in M. Langan, L. Day (eds)
(1992) Women, Oppression and Social Work: Issues in AntiDiscriminatory
Practice, Routledge, London.
Moreau, M. (1979) 'A structural approach to social work
practice', Canadian Journal of Social Work Education, vol 5, no 1,
pp 78-94.
Mullaly, R. (1993) Structural Social Work: Ideology, Theory and
Practice, McClelland and Stewart, Toronto.
National Association of Social Workers (1980) Code of Ethics (U.S.)
New Zealand Association of Social Workers (1993) Code of Ethics
Porter, E. J. (1991) Women and Moral Identity. Allen & Unwin,
Sydney.
Rhodes, M. L. (1985), Ethical Dilemmas in Social Work Practice,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
Rhodes, M. L. (1992) 'Social work challenges: the boundaries
of ethics', Families in Society, January, pp.40-47.
Siporin, M. (1982) 'Moral philosophy in social work
today', Social Science Review, 56, 516-537
Siporin, M. (1983) 'Morality and immorality in working with
clients', Social Thought, 9, Fall, pp.10-28
Thompson, N. (1993) Anti-Discriminatory Practice, Macmillan,
London.
Weedon, C. (1987) Feminist Practice & Poststructuralist Theory,
Basil Blackwell, New York.
Yeatman, A. (1994) Postmodern Revisionings of the Political,
Routledge, New York.
Carolyn Noble is a senior lecturer, University of Western Sydney,
Macarthur, Linda Briskman is a senior lecturer, Deakin University.