The Foraging Spectrum: Diversity in Hunter-Gatherer Lifeways.
Bird, Douglas W. ; Bliege Bird, Rebecca L.
'The scientific principle produces abstractions, the
anti-scientific principle destroys them on the grounds that such and
such has not been considered. The scientific principle establishes
strict concepts, the anti-scientific principle makes them ambiguous on
the pretext of thus revealing their true variety.'
ALEXANDER ZINOVIEV (in Boyer 1995: 175)
Anthropologists will always struggle to understand diversity - in
fact, this should be our ultimate purpose. But how do we begin?
Postmodernist critique has left us more willing to recognize the
political and historical context of both ethnographers and the people
they study, while at the same time cultivating the anti-science notion
that such historical and political contingencies make our observations,
at best, indelibly infected with our own biases, and at worst, useless
as data. Obviously, rejecting the role of observational data-gathering
in anthropology will spell the death of the discipline and transform us
into 21st-century versions of armchair Victorian speculators. If we
accept the role of ethnographic observation in the science of doing
anthropology, we are then faced with methodological dilemmas about how
we make observations, what kinds of observations we make, and how we use
and interpret those observations to serve the goal of understanding
human diversity. The explicit aim of both Kent's and Kelly's
volumes is to provide a better understanding of behavioural differences
within and between populations of contemporary foragers. In our view,
the degree to which this goal is served is a function of how the authors
utilize ethnographic description. Where questions are clear and
descriptions are aimed at testing the predictions of hypotheses to
explain variation, the authors provide an important contribution to our
understanding of contemporary hunter-gatherer societies. We will first
focus on the different approaches illustrated in Susan Kent's
volume and then turn our attention to Robert Kelly's monograph.
One of Kent's goals in compiling Cultural diversity among
twentieth-century foragers is to document variability within and between
African foraging groups. She and the contributing authors accomplish
that goal splendidly, providing us with detailed descriptions of
variability in forager lifeways which give greater depth to our general
ideas about forager subsistence and socio-political organization. Given
that Africa has been the geographic centre for many of the most
influential ethnographic studies of foragers and debates about their
significance, we could be forgiven for accepting Kent's descriptive
aim and chalk up the volume as another nicely detailed empirical
contribution to the literature.
In her preface, however, Kent makes the case that detailing the
diversity of cultural behaviours among groups of Basarwa, Hadza, Okiek
and west African foragers is the key to understanding the cause and
significance of variability in their lifeways (pp. 3-6). She suggests
that because all aspects of behavioural variability ultimately condition
each other, specifics can only be understood in relation to the whole
and have no particular meaning beyond their context. Description thus
serves as both a source of interpretation and as a cautionary tale for
those who might nominate any single group as 'typical' of
hunter-gatherers. While Kent claims that this is not 'a call to
return to the Boasian school of providing detailed descriptive
information devoid of theory and interpretation' (p. 4), she
indicates that observations of the range of variability in forager
culture are the sources for behavioural explanations. Cultural
diversity, for Kent, is the result of cognitive and cultural flexibility
and mobility. Foragers are inherently more diverse than others because
they are more flexible and mobile. She argues that recent approaches to
understanding and explaining the variability in subsistence strategies
among foragers have contributed to the homogenization of all foragers by
limiting their focus toward 'economics or material culture'
and labelling all other aspects of culture as epiphenomenal. She hopes
that this book will help to redress the issue (pp. 6-9).
Kent's primary purpose in compiling the volume, then, is to
detail (and interpret from all possible theoretical perspectives)
differences in African foragers as a means of isolating similarities
(such as flexibility and mobility) which can in turn serve as a basis
for constructing general models to better understand all foragers, past
or present (p. 2). The description will serve as its own explanation
because the specifics are meaningless outside their context. For us,
this is problematic.
While in principle Kent's goals seem reasonable, if our aim is
to understand the 'why's of human behaviour, we have serious
reservations about the actual utility of her approach. Why should
aspects of behaviour that foragers have in common be more important for
general models than their differences? Those contributors to the volume
that seek explanation in terms of the variability they describe may
contribute to a descriptive database of human behaviour, but their
explanations are post-hoc and must be extracted from a mire of empirical
complexity. For example, when Barnard & Widlok conclude their
comparison of diversity in socio-spatial organization between the
Hai//om and Nharo with the statement that the causes of diversity
'can be found in a complex of environmental, economic, political
and cultural factors' (p. 106), they provide us with no hypotheses
whose predictions might sort out which of these environmental, economic,
political and cultural factors constrains and influences which aspect of
behaviour. Likewise, Silberbauer concludes that while our task is
ultimately to explain variability (p. 47), endogenous factors and
external influences shape culturally specific learning among Kalahari
Basarwa groups in such complex ways that appropriate generalizations can
only be generated with more accurate and precise descriptions of
variability, with special consideration of both emic and etic assumptions about the logic of behaviour.
The problem with such approaches is that any description is
inherently synthetic, subject to tremendous bias, and never complete.
Silberbauer suggests that the full range of cultural variability among
the G/wi may only be manifest over a period of two or more generations
(p. 30). We might suggest that two generations is enough time for the
production of a tremendous amount of new variability. If the explanation
of diversity can be found only in the articulated pattern of the whole,
what pieces (if any) of a cultural puzzle are most important for
composing a picture, and what aspects of cultural variability should we
begin describing? Likewise, whose empirical picture of the world should
we utilize if all versions of history or synchronic variability are not
(or are) equally valid? While Silberbauer suggests that the task of
anthropology does not end with descriptive typology, he would have us
believe that more and better description is critical for a complete
understanding of diversity, which will in turn establish a foundation
for generalization and comparison: '. . . it would be an empty or
misleading ethnography which recorded only what the anthropologist
considered to be significant differences . . .' (p. 29). Is it
possible, or even useful, to attempt a more complete description by
including variability that the ethnographer feels is insignificant?
Clearly outlining specific questions and deductive methods seems to be
the only way to decide what observations are relevant. Whether the
questions and methods are relevant, interesting or appropriate is
another matter.
Lewis Binford (1967) pointed out three decades ago that
archaeological descriptions do not speak for themselves in explaining
variability. After reading this volume we suggest that studies of
contemporary foragers face the same dilemma: increased precision in
illustrating diversity, new correlations between social factors and
aspects of subsistence behaviour, a better understanding of the
dialectical nature of ethnography, recognition of the importance of emic
perspectives - all these may serve as important sources of cautionary
tales, but they are not sources in and of themselves for explanations of
why behaviour varies. Why not admit that our descriptions are always
inherently incomplete and that we always impose on data by assigning to
them values we think are significant, and turn our focus toward
utilizing details of diversity as sources to falsify hypothetical
predictions? This is a fundamentally different approach from the
inductive endeavour of seeking 'appropriate' abstractions
(emic, etic or otherwise) for comparison and generalization, and it is,
we argue, more sensitive to the post-modernist critique that bias
infects everything we observe. The scientific approach minimizes bias by
sacrificing holism for analytical precision.
An approach like Kent's that appeals to all-inclusive
theoretical orientations fails to generate any testable hypotheses about
why behaviour might vary between groups. Analyses of diversity best
begin with simplifying (and explicit) theoretical assumptions and move
toward explanation by focusing on predicted relationship between one or
two particular economic, political, cultural, historical or
environmental factors and one or two aspects of behavioural variability.
We can draw upon a theoretical foundation of behaviour (lacking in
Kent's 'holistic description' approach) for hypotheses to
clarify how we might expect these external factors to influence
behavioural outcomes, and test our predictions against observations.
This is not to say that predicted relationships are more important than
others in affecting patterns of behaviour. Obviously, by isolating
aspects of behavioural variation and extracting them from their contexts
for examination, we can only hope to explain a fraction of the whole
complex of cultural traits at any one time. But by proposing many
different explanatory hypotheses to account for variability in many
different aspects of behaviour, we may be able to piece together a more
coherent explanatory picture of the whole. Reading Kent's volume
only offered us more encouragement that it is this
'reductionist' approach (as Silberbauer terms it),
cumulatively applied and grounded in some sort of theory of behaviour,
which offers genuine utility for deductively explaining diversity.
These two approaches, testing explanations vs holistic description,
are well represented in the volume and differences in the utility of
each can be illustrated by contrasting Kent's contribution (pp.
125-56) with the chapter provided by Blurton Jones, Hawkes &
O'Connell (pp. 159-87). Kent demonstrates a finding with regards to
hunting variability among the Kutse: that consumption returns per hunter
are conditioned by post-acquisition sharing. Skilful Kutse hunters give
more than they acquire, while less skilful hunters receive more than
they acquire. She then suggests that this is a product of the inherent
flexibility (resulting from mobility) required to maintain an
'atmosphere of egalitarianism', the essential ethos of Basarwa
culture (p. 155). We are left with questions of infinite regress: if
mobility conditions flexibility which requires egalitarianism that in
turn promotes sharing to even out hunting variability, then why one type
of mobility as opposed to another? Noting that hunting variability is
conditioned by sharing does not explain the pattern, it explains it
away. Predicting this specific relationship with a hypothesis would be
another matter.
How can we begin to sort out what factors are important in
conditioning variability when we know that not all are of equal
importance? As opposed to Kent, Blurton Jones et al. suggest we cannot
begin by continuing to seek more correlations to interpret. The utility
of their approach (regardless of whether or not one agrees with the
tenets of their theoretical framework) is self-evident: by clearly
delineating hypotheses with competing predictions we can evaluate how
well each can account for behavioural variability, in this case
differences between the !Kung and Hadza in children's foraging,
fertility, parental investment, and hunting strategies. A similar
approach by Hewlett (pp. 215-44) to understand variability between west
African hunting practices is also productive. As Bird-David notes
(p.302), strict hypothesis testing may trade-off 'ethnographic
flesh' for clarity, yet the sacrifice can be of tremendous
heuristic value.
This brings us to Robert Kelly's ambitious monograph, The
foraging spectrum. Kelly provides a useful resource for students and
researchers who are looking for syntheses of conceptual approaches to
hunter-gatherer studies, a framework of theory to explain variability,
and empirical diversity in the life-ways of foragers. While the data he
uses to assess his and other's ideas about factors that condition
diversity are limited to addressing specific questions, they are drawn
from an astonishingly wide range of studies. In attempting to
'review some of what anthropology has learned about variability
among ethnographically known hunter-gatherers' (p. 6) '. . .
and [provide] some idea of what might account for it' (p.7),
Kelly's goal is not dissimilar from Susan Kent's. However,
Kelly's limited analyses of specific questions and his focus on
hypothesis testing greatly enhances the overall clarity of the work and
sets a precedence for future syntheses of foraging studies.
Kelly begins the book with two chapters on the role of
hunter-gatherer studies in anthropology and the paradigms that have
structured anthropological thought about their importance. While brief,
his outline of the history of hunter-gatherer studies sets an
appropriate background for his discussion of contemporary approaches. In
chapter 2 he details theory in behavioural ecology which, for the most
part, sets up his treatment of subsistence, mobility, reproduction, sex
differences, social organization and prehistory throughout the rest of
the book. While much of Kelly's discussion of behavioural ecology
is critical for the rest of his book, in some ways he undercuts the real
advantage of the theory (and theory in general). At times, Kelly seems
to confuse theory with the hypotheses it generates, and in so doing may
misidentify the strengths and overplay the limitations (the same
limitations that have been dealt with time and again over the last 15
years) of behavioural ecology.
For example, while he is correct in stating that behaviour is assumed
to be linked to fitness, it is not the case that behavioural ecologists
do (or can) test this assumption. This leads Kelly to surmise that
'behavioural ecologists are interested in the mean fitness of some
class of organisms' (p. 52), and that they attempt to measure the
fitness consequences of particular variants of behaviour by using proxy
measures of fitness. This would be a fruitless task: inclusive fitness is a measure of lifetime reproductive success and genetic contribution
to future generations, the cumulative product of innumerable trade-offs
and decision-making strategies about food, sex, social interaction,
parental investment - anything which impinges upon inclusive fitness.
Our goal as behavioural ecologists is not to measure the fitness
components of particular behavioural strategies, but to test hypotheses
about how those strategies, as opposed to others, are maintained by
selection. That the cumulative effect of behaviour over the lifetime of
an individual is designed to maximize inclusive fitness is the
assumption provided by evolutionary theory, an assumption we cannot test
if we explicitly adopt the theory as the framework from which we derive
testable hypotheses. We have the feeling that sometimes, failure to
recognize this undercuts the strength of 'isolating different
factors and idealizing away from reality . . .' (Boyer 1995: 175)
for doing science. Kelly's discussion of culture (pp. 58-64) seems
to indicate that he does not always appreciate the power of well
established theoretical assumptions as a source for falsifiable and
competing hypotheses. In some ways this leaves some dissatisfaction,
especially when Kelly discusses issues like food sharing and the sexual
division of labour.
Depending on the extent to which the reader is concerned with how
well behavioural ecology, as opposed to other frameworks, can generate
hypotheses to explain human variability, this may (or may not) be a
relatively minor quibble. Despite this, we enjoyed Kelly's book
immensely. His book is for the most part a lucid example of the
advantage of explicit appeal to theory as a guide for questions,
hypotheses and data, and as such it should be an ideal teaching tool to
introduce students of anthropology to science. We agree with Kelly
wholeheartedly when, in his concluding chapter on how we might
understand past variability in hunter-gatherers, he writes, '. . .
the construction of methods to make inferences from archaeological
remains is inextricably linked to an understanding of the variability in
behaviour. One cannot reconstruct the past without simultaneously trying
to explain the past' (p. 343). This is especially important in
issues where more accurate reconstructions require us to explain why
behaviour in the past may have varied and should be of equal importance
in dealing with contemporary diversity. As Kelly notes, the only way
effectively to deal with this is by utilizing hypotheses that are
independent of the empirics at hand.
The utility of answers to questions about why human behaviour varies
depends on how well we can avoid explaining away variation. It may often
be tempting to explain away behavioural diversity as the result of
historical and proximate cultural processes. This, however, begs the
question of interest: why is behaviour patterned in one way as opposed
to another? Our understanding of variability will suffer if the answer
to this question can only appeal to historical processes. Evolution is
of course a historically contingent process: current variability is
constrained by the trajectory of past change. Many phenotypic features
exist not for functional reasons, but as a result of unique, sometimes
stochastic, histories. As a result, any adaptation is seriously
constrained by phylogeny (Williams 1992: 72-6). This does not mean,
however, that we cannot understand the maintenance of variability in
functional terms (as opposed to proximate causation, see Krebs &
Davies 1993: 4-8), it just means that we won't be able to
understand all variability this way. The only way to know, however, is
to test our ideas against observations. An illustration of evolutionary
history or a description of diversity, no matter how precise, will not
explain variability. This was what distinguished Darwin from Linnaeus:
Darwin realized that no matter how well we describe different historical
trends or synchronic diversity, we cannot explain differences with
increased precision of classification. Kent's volume and
Kelly's book are commendable in that they provide description that
assists in demolishing our imposed typologies of hunter-gatherers. But,
as many of these authors note, tearing down taxonomies will not explain
diversity any better than building them.
References
BINFORD, L.R. 1967. Smudge pits and hide smoking: the use of analogy
in archaeological reasoning, American Antiquity 32: 1-12.
BOYER, P. 1995. Ceteris paribus (all else being equal), in J.
Brockman & K. Matson (ed.), How things are: 169-75. New York (NY):
William Morrow.
KREBS, J.R. & N.B. DAVIES. 1993. An introduction to behavioural
ecology. Oxford: Blackwell.
WILLIAMS, G.C. 1992. Natural selection: domains, levels, and
challenges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.