Markets without Limits: Moral Virtues and Commercial Interests.
Morrison, Richard
Markets without Limits: Moral Virtues and Commercial Interests
Jason Brennan and Peter M. Jaworski
New York: Routledge, 2016, 239 pp.
Are there some things that should be beyond the market, that is,
which should not be permitted to be bought and sold? Jason Brennan and
Peter Jaworski think, "No, for the most part."
Brennan and Jaworski, both philosophy professors at Georgetown
University's McDonough School of Business, dedicate Markets without
Limits "to the authors, supporters, and readers of the Business
Ethics Journal Review." BEJR editors Chris MacDonald and Alexei
Marcoux paid $275 for this dedication. Yet, far from a frivolous
exercise, this is an example of both the practical seriousness the
authors bring to their premise and the good humor with which they go
about making their case. The acknowledgments list a couple of dozen
other well-wishers who paid for their names to be included, and who, as
the authors put it, "greatly assisted us by putting their money
where our mouths are."
First, I should offer a clarification on the title. Brennan and
Jaworski's arguments in favor of the moral nature of market
exchange, while very broad in terms of what may be legitimately bought
and sold, do not necessarily advocate a market without any limits
whatsoever. This is not, as some of their anti-market critics would have
it, a tome of "market fundamentalism" that promotes absolute
laissez-faire as the only, or even the most, moral economic system. As
the authors point out in the text--and have tried to remind hostile
interlocutors since the book's publication--the heart of their
argument is, "If you may do it for free, you may do if for
money," not that all goods and services must be sold without any
restrictions or regulation.
The idea of responding to critics is very much at the heart of this
project. In the opening chapter, the authors describe the flood of books
in recent years that have attacked markets as inherently immoral or
selectively corrupting in dangerous ways. The first three years of the
current decade alone saw the publication of Why Some Things Should Not
Be for Sale: The Moral Limits of Markets (2010) by Stanford's Debra
Satz and What Money Cant Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets (2012) by
Michael Sandel of Harvard. Sandel's attacks on markets, in
particular, have received dramatic accolades, including a Newsweek
contributor describing him as "possibly the world's most
relevant living philosopher."
The critics attacking market transactions, then, are not a club of
marginal cranks, but represent some of the nation's most praised
and frequently published public voices. Brennan and Jaworski refer to
them collectively as the "anti-commodification theorists" and
posit themselves as "the critics' critics." They review
several of these theorists' major objections, including concerns
about exploitation, misallocation, and corruption, and proceed to
examine those thematic critiques in individual chapters through examples
of specific controversial products and services.
The authors do a good job of separating incidental objections from
the fundamental moral questions at the heart of the anti-commodification
debate. In a section titled "Business Ethics vs. What Can Be for
Sale," we are asked to consider objections to a couple of
scenarios. Some critics of the fast food chain Chick-fil-A, for example,
object to the company's political opposition to marriage equality.
Other critics have been appalled at reports of abusive working
conditions at facilities operated by Apple's Chinese contractor
FoxConn. If we deem these companies' products to be worthy of a
boycott, that would represent a kind of limit on the market for chicken
and smartphones, but not the kind of limit that concerns the authors.
Their primary question is whether there are things that categorically
cannot be legitimately bought and sold. They are not concerned, in this
book at least, with the objectionable actions or business practices of
particular companies. To date, the anti-market critics have not yet
argued that chicken sandwiches and iPhones are inherently immoral items
to sell.
That distinction, along with the understanding that Brennan and
Jaworski are not necessarily arguing for unregulated markets, sets the
stage for considering the anti-commodification theorists' real
objections. And while ultimately they conclude that all of those
objections can be answered and refuted, they do take them seriously. For
example, Brennan and Jaworski engage in fascinating discussions on
whether public betting on the likelihood of future terrorist attacks
should be legal, as well as on more well-trod debate topics like
legalizing sex work and the moral status of surrogate motherhood.
By conceding that a highly regulated market can legitimately
address some people's concerns about unethical market practices,
the authors are able to answer a wide range of objections to allegedly
problematic market exchanges. A highly regulated market is still a
market, after all, and thus market exchanges are allowed if the
regulations are met. The question for them is, "When are market
exchanges permitted?" not "What are the correct regulations
for a permitted market exchange?" For every accusation that a
certain kind of transaction might generate a negative outcome, they
suggest a market structure or legal safeguard to alleviate the concern.
If you're worried that the interests of the baby in a surrogacy
agreement won't be adequately represented, require an independent
legal advocate for the baby. If you're worried about the ethics of
arranging surrogacy though a paid broker, forbid brokers. If you're
worried that prospective mothers won't be adequately compensated,
institute a minimum compensation package. A market would still exist
under these, or even far greater, restrictions.
There are obvious practical limits to this approach, however, both
from the free market and the anti-commodification perspectives. Brennan
and Jaworski suggest, via a clever analogy to consumer electronics, that
certain markets simply need to be "dialed in" correctly in
order to be considered morally permissible; that is, they need to have
their terms of payment, mode of exchange, prices, or other conditions
legally bounded. Under a certain set of regulated conditions, even the
most problematic market transaction can theoretically be made
acceptable. But those restrictions, while they might answer the
objections of certain critics, obviously can create problems of their
own by restricting entry, raising prices, increasing inefficiency, and
incentivizing black markets.
On the flipside, the legal acrobatics necessary to alleviate all of
the anti-commodifiers' concerns may, in effect, render certain
exchanges illegal under all but a handful of mostly hypothetical
conditions. Why bother, such a critic might ask, creating an elaborate
legal and regulatory structure to supervise a transaction with such a
narrow range of morally acceptable applications? Even George Mason
University's Ilya Somin, no anti-capitalist gadfly, has raised this
objection to Brennan and Jaworski's argument that paying someone
for his vote should be legally permissible. Somin writes, "It may
well be impossible in practice to separate out the (relatively rare)
cases of defensible vote-buying from the much more common ones where
people are paid for their vote for the purpose of advancing the goals of
some narrow interest group or voting the straight party line." The
authors claim that "most of the repugnant markets could be
'fixed' rather easily" with sufficiently clever market
design, but I'd like to hear from some of the anti-commodification
theorists themselves on whether they consider the fixes to be quite so
easy.
The authors move most decisively from unlikely hypothetical to
practical public policy when they consider the market for human kidneys.
They understandably bring a more forceful case to arguing for the
permissibility of markets in life-saving organs than for ones in
line-standing services and household chores. They counter objections to
organ sales, as they did with paid surrogacy services, with specific
policy proposals. They also recognize that many opponents will remain
unconvinced even when their announced objections are addressed. The
authors describe this state of implacable resistance as "moral
dumbfounding."
A large portion of the general public's objections are in this
category--a nonrational sense of disgust at the idea of buying and
selling human body parts. Contrary to some widely read theorists like
Leon Kass, who coined the phrase "the wisdom of repugnance,"
Brennan and Jaworski suggest that visceral reactions of disgust to
certain ideas are not a meaningful guide to moral judgement. They argue
that semiotic objections to kidney selling--the idea that, if nothing
else, it signals an inappropriate lack of reverence toward the human
body--should be discarded.
Therein lies the challenge, of course. To the extent that
anti-commodification arguments are really about nonrational dislike of
market processes, the practical applications for this insight seem
limited. In the United States, allowing a national market for kidney
sales could save thousands of lives a year. If even that hasn't
been able to budge public opinion, it's difficult to see how policy
advocates will be able to persuade their squeamish fellow citizens to
simply "get over" their aversions. That's not Brennan and
Jaworski's job, of course, but it does somewhat deflate the
enjoyment of their well-reasoned arguments to realize that the task at
hand is nothing less than "change American culture." I'll
get right on that.
Markets without Limits probably won't, as the authors hope,
"put philosophers out of the business of talking about the moral
limits of markets" (especially since that seems to be one of the
few commercially popular topics in academic philosophy), but hopefully
it will help generate better conversations among academics and students.
Clarifying the debate on the morality of markets per se versus the
business practices of particular market actors will, on its own, go a
long way towards helping capitalism's critics better frame their
objections and capitalism's defenders better respond to them.
Brennan and Jaworski's book both clarifies the debate over the
limits of markets and shows how honest intellectuals can forthrightly
and effectively respond to critics of markets.
Richard Morrison
Competitive Enterprise Institute