Celestial anarchy: a threat to outer space commerce?
Salter, Alexander W. ; Leeson, Peter T.
The wealth-creating potential of outer space commerce is
tremendous. Companies such as SpaceX are successfully providing private
sector responses to public sector demands for transportation to the
International Space Station. Planetary Resources and Deep Space
Industries promise to create wealth by mining asteroids for rare metals
and water. And Virgin Galactic and Space Adventures are pioneering the
market for space tourism.
The world's first commercial spaceport, Spaceport America, in
New Mexico, which cost nearly $209 million to build, is already in use
by SpaceX and Virgin Galactic. In addition, high-powered investors, such
as Elon Musk (creator of PayPal, now CEO of SpaceX), Larry Page
(co-founder of Google, now also involved with Planetary Resources), and
Sir Richard Branson (chairman of the Virgin Group, the venture capital
conglomerate behind Virgin Galactic), are pouring hundreds of millions
of dollars of their own capital into outer space ventures. (1)
Yet an ominous feature of the celestial environment seems to
threaten the ability of outer space commerce to achieve its potential:
celestial anarchy. Although, terrestrially, governments enjoy the
sovereignty over their territories needed for the state to define and
enforce property rights in those territories, celestially, things are
quite different. In outer space, much as in international space, no
government has sovereignty. This fact is enshrined in the 1967 Outer
Space Treaty, signed by the spacefaring nations. Article II of the
treaty prohibits signatory nations from extending territorial
jurisdiction to celestial bodies. (2)
In practice, at least, the same Article prevents even private
citizens from using their sovereigns to define or enforce privately held
property rights in celestial bodies. (3) As White (2002: 84) points out,
"in common law countries such as the United States, legal theory
dictates that the government must have sovereignty over territory before
it can confer title on its citizens. Consequently, traditional real
property rights [in outer space] are inconsistent with this
theory."
The problem celestial anarchy seems to create here is
straightforward. Private parties who have property disputes when
operating in outer space need to settle their disputes in courts of law.
But such courts are within the legal domains of national sovereigns.
Enforcing private parties' property rights in outer space therefore
requires a de facto concession of national sovereignty, running afoul of
Article II. (4) As Pop (2000: 281) puts it, because "the Outer
Space Treaty prohibits the national appropriation of outer space and
celestial bodies, a State endorsement" of private parties'
property rights in such bodies "would be interpreted as a means of
national appropriation, hence it would be unlawful."
Economists have long highlighted the necessity of private property
rights for thriving commercial activity (e.g., Smith 1776, Mises 1949,
Alchian and Demsetz 1973, North 1990). Without some means of enforcing
claims to mine and thine, individuals have little incentive to risk
investing in and growing commercial enterprises. This is as true for
celestial enterprises as it is for terrestrial ones. As White (2000: 2)
notes, "Implementing [a] real property regime would provide greater
legal certainty to investors and entities participating in the
development and settlement of outer space." Celestial anarchy thus
appears to pose a serious obstacle to flourishing outer space commerce.
But what if private parties sidestepped the problem posed by
sovereigns' inability to support celestial property rights by
enforcing such rights privately--that is., without reliance on any
government? Pop (2000: 281) summarizes the conventional view of this
possibility: "Appropriation of land can exist outside the sphere of
sovereignty, but its survival is dependent upon endorsement from a
sovereign entity." (5) In other words, it is widely believed that a
purely private celestial property rights regime is not possible.
This article argues that conventional wisdom is wrong. Celestial
anarchy is genuine, but the ostensible problem it poses for the
development of outer space commerce is not. Private property rights can
and do survive without the endorsement or involvement of any sovereign
entity. This suggests that private parties can, if given the chance,
enforce property rights in outer space. Economically, at least,
celestial anarchy poses no obstacle to the flourishing and hill
development of celestial enterprise.
The conventional wisdom's failure to grasp this fact stems
from two sources: unfamiliarity with economic theory and unfamiliarity
with economic reality. Economic theory demonstrates how private
individuals can enforce property rights without reliance on government.
And economic reality demonstrates how they in fact do so. There's
nothing special about this theory or its manifestations in practice that
would limit it to terrestrial property rights.
Our argument does not deny potential political problems associated
with private individuals of particular nationalities claiming property
rights in outer space when those claims run afoul of sovereigns'
interpretation of the Outer Space Treaty. It denies the alleged economic
problem of them doing so, upon which the prevailing view that celestial
anarchy threatens to undermine outer space commerce is based. In this
sense, our article complements existing contributions to the literature
on governance in outer space that discuss mechanisms for achieving
resource usage (see Weeden and Chow 2012, Cooper 2003, Milligan 2011,
and Simberg 2012). In our concluding section, we briefly consider the
relevance of our analysis of the economic (non-) problem of celestial
anarchy for the political problem such anarchy may pose.
Enforcing Property Rights without a Sovereign in Theory
According to conventional wisdom, a sovereign state--a monopoly
authority that all parties must submit to as the final arbiter of
property disputes--is necessary to enforce and thus sustain a regime of
property rights. To understand this claim it's helpful to consider
an analytic scenario that has done much work for economists who study
the nature of governance: the Prisoners' Dilemma. Figure 1 depicts
this scenario.
Alice and Bob are considering how to behave toward one another in
an environment without a sovereign. The rows and columns in Figure 1
depict the strategies that Alice and Bob, respectively, can pursue in
their interaction with one another. Inside each row-column box are
Alice's and Bob's payoffs--that is, what each party earns by
interacting with the other--depending on the strategy they pursue and
the strategy the other party pursues. Alice's payoff appears first
in each box and Bob's appears second.
Alice and Bob each have two strategies they may follow in their
interaction with the other. They choose their strategies simultaneously.
Each party can "cooperate" by respecting the property rights
the other party claims to have, say by trading with the other party
honestly. Or they can "defect" by violating the property
rights the other party claims to have by, say, by stealing what the
other party claims as his or her own or trading with him or her
fraudulently.
When both parties cooperate with each other, both capture gains
from trade equal to A > 0. When one party defects but the other party
cooperates, the defecting party benefits at the cooperating party's
expense. In this case the defecting party earns C > A, and the
cooperating party earns B < 0. When both parties defect, both parties
earn 0: mutual theft is damaging to both parties, but not as damaging to
either party as being "suckered"--i.e., respecting the other
party's property rights when the other party violates their
property rights.
Without a property right-enforcing sovereign to keep them in line,
how will Alice and Bob behave? Examining each party's payoff under
each of the possible scenarios in Figure 1 reveals that both Alice and
Bob will defect. This is because, no matter what the other party does,
both Alice and Bob maximize their own payoff by violating the property
rights of the other.
If Alice thinks Bob will cooperate, Alice wants to defect because
she earns her highest payoff possible, C, in this scenario. If Alice
thinks Bob will defect, Alice again wants to defect because she earns 0
in this scenario, which is higher than what she earns if she cooperates
and Bob defects, B. Bob, whose situation is symmetric, reasons the same
way. So he always defects too.
Both parties therefore earn 0, which is less than what both could
earn if they could instead agree to respect each other's property
rights, A. Each party can promise the other that they will cooperate.
But without a sovereign to enforce that promise, each is led to break
their word, tempted by the specter of earning C if the other party keeps
his or her word, or of at least earning 0 instead of B if they expect
the other party to break his or her word.
This dilemma described by Figure 1 is a stylized version of that
which conventional wisdom suggests must be the outcome under celestial
anarchy in arguing that enforceable property rights are unsustainable
here. Consider what happens, however, if we modify the analytical
situation that Alice and Bob confront in a small way that more closely
resembles reality. Suppose that Alice and Bob interact, and thus have
the opportunity to respect or violate one another's property
rights, not just once, but an indefinite number of times--the case of a
repetitive game. Suppose that both parties defect on the other party for
all subsequent interactions if he or she defects on him or her even once
and that both parties tell the other as much. Now how will Alice and Bob
behave without a sovereign to keep them in line?
Unless Alice or Bob is excessively impatient, both will cooperate.
Where [gamma] [member of] (0,1) is the discount rate that Alice and Bob
apply to payoffs from interacting in the future (since earnings in the
future are worth less than earnings today), for both parties,
cooperation now yields: (6)
(1) [[summation].sup.[infinity].sub.t] = 0 [[gamma].sup.t] A.
And for both parties, defecting now yields C. Recalling the rule
for solving an infinite geometric series and using simple algebra to
solve for y reveals that cooperating is now more profitable than
defecting for both Alice and Bob when:
(2) A - C/C > [gamma].
As long as Alice and Bob are patient enough to satisfy this
inequality (i.e., they don't discount future payoffs too steeply),
both will respect the other's property rights despite the absence
of a sovereign. (7) Simply permitting Alice and Bob to interact
repeatedly and conditioning each party's strategy choice on the
strategy chosen by the other party in the past reverses the result we
found earlier. Instead of always violating one another's property
rights, Alice and Bob always respect one another's rights.
The reason for this result is what economists call the
"discipline of continuous dealings." The intuition that
underlies it is simple. When Alice and Bob interact indefinitely rather
than just once, the possibility of being "punished" by the
other party in the future for defecting in the past emerges. Both
parties know that if they violate the other party's property rights
today, the other party will defect when interacting with them
tomorrow--and in every period after that--preventing the defecting party
from earning positive payoffs ever again. Since the gain from defecting
is a onetime gain but the gains lost from defecting even once are
forever, if parties don't discount the future excessively, they
earn more by always cooperating than by ever defecting. Property rights
are self-enforcing.
In Figure 1 there are only two parties. But the logic is the same
if there are more than two. Indeed, when there are more than two
parties, reputations become possible, strengthening self-enforcing
property rights still further. Suppose, for example, that in addition to
Alice and Bob, there's another party, Charlie. Now if, say, Alice
violates Bob's property rights, not only may Bob defect when
interacting with Alice in the future, cutting her off from the gains of
future cooperation with him, but Bob may tell Charlie that Alice is a
property right violator, leading Charlie to defect on Alice in all his
future interactions with her as well. This makes the
"punishment" that Alice suffers for defecting even stronger,
which in turn strengthens her incentive to respect Bob's and
Charlie's property rights.
The discipline of continuous dealings illustrates theoretically why
a sovereign isn't necessary to sustain enforceable property rights.
In what follows we draw on economic reality to illustrate how private
parties leverage self-enforcing property rights without a sovereign in
practice. Although there are many examples we could draw on for this
purpose (see, for instance, Friedman 1979; Ellickson 1994; Anderson and
Hill 2004; Leeson 2007a, 2007b, 2009, 2013), we focus on one in
particular because of its similarity in several important respects to
the situation of celestial anarchy this article is interested
in--namely, international anarchy.
Enforcing Property Rights without a Sovereign in Practice
International anarchy refers to the fact that, although globally
many sovereigns exist to define and enforce property rights among
persons engaged in commerce in each of their domestic domains, no formal
supranational sovereign exists to define and enforce property rights
among persons engaged in international commerce--commerce between
citizens hailing from different territories governed by different
national sovereigns. Nor has such a sovereign ever existed. In this
sense the property rights situation that parties to international
commerce confront is similar to the property rights situation that
prospective parties to outer space commerce confront.
Yet international anarchy hasn't prevented international
commerce from flourishing. In the absence of a supranational sovereign
that could create a sustainable property rights regime for international
traders, international traders have developed a private regime of
self-enforcing property rights for this this purpose instead. The result
has been booming international commerce that generates nearly a quarter
of the world's wealth annually. Central to this regime of
self-enforcing property rights is the discipline of continuous dealings
described above. (8)
The Medieval Law Merchant
In the ninth and tenth centuries a professional class of merchants
emerged across Europe. These merchants confronted the central obstacle
of international anarchy pointed to above: the absence of a
supranational sovereign that could protect international traders'
property rights, enabling the growth of international commerce. Given
this situation, if a trader from Italy entered a commercial contract
with a trader from Spain, how could their contract, and thus the
property rights embodied in that agreement, be enforced?
A trader who believed his counterparty had violated their agreement
might attempt to seek enforcement against his counterparty in his
nation's courts. But such courts typically refused to adjudicate
international cases on the grounds that they involved citizens from
other nations, over whom they had no jurisdiction. Even if one agreed to
adjudicate such a case, since it lacked authority over the counterparty,
who was from another country, it had no means of enforcing its decision.
An Italian court, for example, couldn't seize the assets of a
merchant located in Spain. Further, on the basis of which
sovereign's law should such a court adjudicate the traders'
disagreement? The laws created and enforced by the government of Italy
to govern Italian citizens didn't (and don't) apply to Spanish
citizens governed by Spanish law.
In response to such obstacles to international commerce, medieval
merchants resolved international commercial disputes privately on the
basis of merchant-developed law in private, merchant-developed courts.
This system of self-enforcing property rights is called the medieval lex
mercatoria (law merchant). As Benson (1989: 645) notes in his discussion
of the medieval law merchant, this system demonstrates that
international "commerce and commercial law have developed
conterminously, without the aid ... of the coercive power of
nation-states."
Although initially based on what knowledge of Roman civil law had
been salvaged after the fall of the Roman Empire, the medieval law
merchant evolved as customs and practices common to many geographic
locales became standard practice for merchants engaged in international
commerce (Benson 1989: 648). Common rules enabled merchants to capture
more of the gains from international trade, further cementing them as a
cornerstone of acceptable practices among international traders. (9) By
the 12th century, international "commercial law had developed to a
level where alien merchants had substantial protection in disputes with
local merchants" (Benson 1989: 648).
The private merchant courts that adjudicated property conflicts
under this body of private law developed their own rules of evidence and
employed experts to decide specialized matters involving international
commercial contracts. Compared to the national courts prevalent in the
nascent sovereigns of the period, merchant courts were informal and
reached decisions quickly--a feature valued highly by international
merchants (Benson 1989: 649-51). (10)
To enforce merchant court decisions, members of the international
commercial community leveraged the discipline of continuous dealings
described earlier. Although these courts had no formal enforcement
power, most traders complied with their decisions. Refusing to do so
resulted in the members of the international trading community
blacklisting the uncooperative traders, cutting them off from the
benefits of future trading opportunities with members of that community.
The discipline of continuous dealings between international traders
rendered commercial contracts between them, and thus traders'
property rights, self-enforcing.
The Modern Law Merchant
In the absence of a supranational sovereign to enforce and sustain
property rights between contemporary international traders, modern
international trade is similarly governed privately--by a modern law
merchant. Given the difficulties, and for many years the impossibility,
of using national sovereigns to enforce international commercial
disputes, contemporary international traders rely on private
international arbitration associations instead. Indeed, at least 90
percent of modern international commercial contracts contain clauses
stipulating the resolution of contractual disputes via private
arbitration (Leeson 2008b: 68).
The sums of money at stake in these private courts are enormous.
For example, in 2001 roughly 1,500 parties from 115 countries used the
arbitration services of the International Chamber of Commerce (ICC), the
largest of such organizations, in property conflicts that ranged in
value from $50 to $1 billion. Over 60 percent of these disputes were for
amounts between $1 million and $1 billion (ICC 2002). likewise, in 2001
another private international arbitration association, the International
Center for Dispute Resolution (ICDR), adjudicated contracts worth $10
billion involving parties from 63 different countries (ICDR 2002).
When forging their contracts, parties to private international
arbitration choose the law they want to apply to their agreement in the
event of dispute. They may choose commercial law as embodied in the laws
of various sovereigns. Or they may choose to have customary law, as it
has evolved and developed under the modern law merchant, to govern their
contracts instead.
Like those of their medieval merchant-court counterparts, the
decisions of private international arbitration associations are
overwhelmingly respected by the international traders who rely on them.
The ICC, for instance, estimates that 90 percent of its decisions are
complied with voluntarily (Leeson 2006b: 50). As in the past, the
discipline of continuous dealings plays a crucial role in securing such
compliance and rendering property rights self-enforcing. A trader who
refuses to comply with the decision that one of these private courts has
handed down to him faces losing his reputation among the community of
international traders, and with it, the prospect for future commerce.
In 1958 the first multinational treaty aimed at facilitating the
enforcement of private international arbitral decisions in the national
courts of sovereigns emerged: the United Nations New York Convention on
the Recognition and Enforcement of Foreign Arbitral Awards. Since then,
many, though not all, countries have signed the New York Convention
(NYC). Leeson (2008b: 63) describes how the NYC works:
Private parties to international commercial contracts agree to
have their disputes settled by arbitration associations. Since
these associations are private, they cannot formally compel losers
to comply with their decisions. However, under the terms of
the NYC, winners can have their arbitral decisions enforced by
losers' governments if these governments are members of the
convention.... A simple example illustrates how the NYC provides
state enforcement for international traders. Suppose a
Bulgarian importer contracts with an Argentinian exporter for a
shipment of grade A quality leather. When the shipment
arrives, the Bulgarian finds that the leather is only of B quality,
though his trade partner insists it is A. Before 1958 these traders
would have privately settled their dispute through an international
arbitration association. If the arbitrator decided the
Argentinian did not fulfill his end of the contract and ordered
him to pay, the Bulgarian had no means of compelling payment
should the Argentinian refuse. However, the introduction of the
NYC in 1958 changed this. Traders still use private arbitration
to settle disagreements. But now, under the NYC, if the
Argentinian refuses to pay, the Bulgarian can call on the
Argentinian government, which has signed the NYC, to enforce
his arbitral award.
Because of the NYC, at least in principle, post-1958 international
traders have been able to rely on the support of sovereigns to enforce
their property rights. But it would be mistaken to conclude that the NYC
has succeeded in removing international traders from international
anarchy and thus that international commerce requires, or indeed is
ultimately based on, sovereign enforcement. Prior to 1958 the NYC
didn't exist. Yet international commerce, which was already
substantial, flourished. Equally important, in the absence of s
supranational sovereign, the NYC--which is a contract between
sovereigns--itself has no sovereign that could enforce its terms. What
enforces the NYC's terms is the discipline of continuous dealings.
The NYC is nothing but a statement of promises from its sovereign
signatories to agree to respect private international arbitral awards
rendered by other sovereigns. No third-party enforcement of these
promises exists, or in the absence of a global government is possible.
To the extent that sovereign signatories of the NYC fulfill their
promises under the treaty, they do so under the threat of being
ostracized by the Convention's other signatories who may refuse to
enter into future treaties with a sovereign that goes back on its word.
Thus, even in the case of the NYC, the discipline of continuous
dealings--ultimately a mechanism of self-enforcement--drives compliance.
As Leeson (2008b: 83) puts it, "Like all multinational treaties,
for the NYC as well, there is no formal supranational agency of
authority to compel states that have joined it to abide by its terms.
This leaves the enforcement of the NYC to informal mechanisms, such as
reputation, and the interstate equivalent of international arbitration
through such organizations as the UN."
Conclusion
The economic theory of self-enforcing property rights and the
economic reality that illustrates this theory's application under
international anarchy suggests that conventional wisdom, according to
which a sustainable property rights regime under celestial anarchy
isn't possible, is mistaken. If there are special features of the
celestial environment that preclude our analysis' relevance for
this environment, we can't think of them--and the absence of an
enumeration of such features by others suggests they can't either.
This statement does not, of course, deny that special, particular
features of the outer space environment that would bear on how privately
created governance might emerge in this context exist. For example,
self-enforcing property rights in international traders' anarchic
context differ from their manifestation in the anarchic, 19th century
American frontier (which we did not consider, but see Anderson and Hill
2004). These differences reflect specific features of the property
rights problem situation that individuals confronted in each case.
Likewise, the particular property right problems that outerspace
entrepreneurs may confront will also surely be different, suggesting
that the precise way in which self-enforcing property rights would
manifest in this anarchic environment differ too.
Perhaps commercial space pioneers would use already-existing
arbitration associations, such as the ICC, in order to enforce celestial
property rights. Or perhaps a body of private outer space law-informed
at its core by familiar precedents relating to nuisance, damages,
liability, and so on--might progress to the point that space-specific
arbitration agencies, employing their own experts in space law, would
serve as the primary dispute resolution mechanism and process by which
precedent is set. Alternatively, the first space pioneers might have a
voluntary convention in which their representatives form a kind of outer
space "social contract," thereby setting the rules for
original appropriation of unowned resources, property rights
enforcement, and the proper bounds of behavior between parties when one
party's behavior imposes uncompensated burdens on others.
The specific self-enforcing arrangements that might actually
develop under celestial anarchy can't be established with any
certainty ex ante. What can be established is that some system of
self-enforcing property rights would develop if given the chance and
that such a system would reflect the particular issues that space
entrepreneurs confront in their efforts to secure the substantial gains
that cooperative celestial commercialization offers.
As economists, our comparative advantage is analyzing the economic
problem that celestial anarchy seems to, but, as our analysis suggests,
does not in fact, pose for sustaining enforceable property rights in
outer space. Nevertheless, in concluding we think it worthwhile to touch
briefly on the implications that our analysis may have for the potential
political problem posed by celestial anarchy. That problem is this:
There may be political consequences to private individuals'
securing property rights in outer space if these individuals'
claims run contrary to political actors' interpretation of Article
II of the Outer Space Treaty.
We have in mind here something along the lines of political elites
in country X, in response to the establishment of property rights in
celestial bodies in a manner consistent with what we have described in
this article by an individual citizen of country Y, objecting that such
an establishment violates the "genuine intent" of the Outer
Space Treaty. Such objections could escalate into tensions between the
sovereign nations of which X and Y are citizens. And those tensions may
have further political consequences. (11) Our finding that the economic
problem of celestial anarchy is actually not a problem could help
diffuse such a situation. To the extent that political elites are
interested in seeing the establishment of private property rights in
space so that commercial space activity can flourish, but worry that
this must involve violating the sovereignty restrictions in the Outer
Space Treaty, our analysis shows their concern is misplaced. (12)
References
Anderson, T. L., and P. J. Hill (2004) The Not So Wild, Wild West:
Property Rights on the Frontier. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University
Press.
Alchian, A., and Demsetz, H. (1973) "The Property Rights
Paradigm." Journal of Economic History 33 (1): 16-27.
Benson, B. L. (1989) "The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial
Law." Southern Economic Journal 55 (3): 644-61.
Coffey, S. (2009) "Establishing a Legal Framework for Property
Rights to Natural Resources in Outer Space." Case Western Reserve
Journal of International Law 41 (1): 119-47.
Cooper, L. A. (2003) "Encouraging Space Exploration through a
New Application of Space Property Rights." Space Policy 19 (2):
111-18.
Dunstan, J. E. (2002) "Towards a Unified Theory of Space
Property Rights: Sometimes the Best Way to Predict the Weather Is to
Look Outside." In E. L. Hudgins (ed.) Space: The Free-Market
Frontier, 22.3-41. Washington: Cato Institute.
Ellickson, R. (1994) Order Without Law. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press.
Friedman, D. (1979) "Private Creation and Enforcement of Law:
A Historical Case." Journal of Legal Studies 8 (2): 399-415.
Groove, S. (1969) "Interpreting Article II of the Outer Space
Treaty." Fordham Law Review 37 (3): 349-54.
International Chamber of Commerce (ICC) (2002) International Court
of Arbitration Bulletin 13 (1).
International Center for Dispute Resolution (ICDR) (2002)
"Press Release."
Leeson, P. T. (2006a) "Cooperation and Conflict: Evidence on
Self-Enforcing Arrangements and Heterogeneous Groups." American
Journal of Economics and Sociology 65 (4): 891-907.
--(2006b) "Efficient Anarchy." Public Choice 130: 41-53.
--(2007a) "An-arrgh-chy: The Law and Economics of Pirate
Organization." Journal of Political Economy 115 (6): 1049-94.
--(2007b) "Trading with Bandits." Journal of Law and
Economics 50 (2): 303-21.
--(2008a) "Social Distance and Self-Enforcing Exchange"
Journal of Legal Studies 37 (1): 161-88.
--(2008b) "How Important Is State Enforcement for
International Trade?" American Law and Economics Review 10 (1):
61-89.
--(2009) "The Laws of Lawlessness." Journal of Legal
Studies 38 (2): 471-503.
--(2013) "Gypsy Law." Public Choice 155: 273-92.
Milgrom, P. R.; North, D. C.; and Weingast, B. R. (1990) "The
Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private
Judges, and the Champagne Fairs." Economics and Politics 2 (1):
1-23.
Milligan, T. (2011) "Property Rights and the Duty to Extend
Human Life." Space Policy 27 (4): 190-93.
Mises, L. von (1949) Human Action: A Treatise on Economics. New
Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
North, D. C. (1990) Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic
Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pop, V. (2000) "Appropriation in Outer Space: The Relationship
between Land Ownership and Sovereignty on Celestial Bodies." Space
Policy 16 (4): 275-82.
Simberg, R. (2012). "Homesteading the Final Frontier: A
Practical Proposal for Securing Property Rights in Space."
Competitive Enterprise Institute, Issue Analysis No. 3.
Smith, A. ([1776] 1981) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of
the Wealth of Nations. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Solomon, L. D. (2012) The Privatization of Space Exploration:
Business, Technology, Law and Policy. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction
Publishers.
Weeden, B. C., and Chow, T. (2012) "Taking a Common-Pool
Resources Approach to Space Sustainability: A Framework and Potential
Policies." Space Policy 28 (3): 166-72.
White, W. N. Jr. (1997) "Real Property Rights in Outer
Space." 40th Colloquium on the Law of Outer Space. Available at
www.spacesettlement-institute.org/Articles/research_library/WayneWhite982.pdf.
--(2000) "Implications of a Proposal for Real Property Rights
in Outer Space." Proceedings of the 42nd Colloquium on the Law of
Outer Space. Available at www.spacefuture.com/
archive/implications_of_a_proposal_for_real_property_rights_in_outer_space.shtml.
--(2002) "The Legal Regime for Private Activities in Outer
Space." In E. L. Hudgins (ed.) Space: The Free-Market Frontier,
83-111. Washington: Cato Institute.
--(2003) "Interpreting Article II of the Outer Space
Treaty." Paper presented at the 54th International Astronautical
Conference.
Alexander W. Salter is Assistant Professor of Economics at Berry
College. He coauthored this article while he was a Dissertation Fellow
with the Mercatus Center at George Mason University. Peter T. Leeson is
the Duncan Black Professor of Economics and Law and the BB&T
Professor for the Study of Capitalism at George Mason University.
(1) See Solomon (2012) for a historical overview of companies
currently pioneering space-related commercial activities.
(2) The full text of this treaty and list of signatories and
parties are available at
http://disar1nament.un.org/treaties/t/outer_space. Because of the lack
of signatories among spacefaring nations, we don't consider here
the 1979 Moon Treaty (http://disarmament.un.org/treaties/t/moon).
(3) Whether or not the Outer Space Treaty precludes private
citizens from holding property rights in celestial bodies in principle
is contested. Some scholars argue that some form of private property
rights is reconcilable with the requirements of the Outer Space Treaty
(see, for instance, Groove 1969 and White 1997, 2000, 2003). Others
argue that the Treaty precludes all private property rights (see, for
instance, Pop 2000 and Dunstan 2002).
(4) This is why White (2002: 84), a defender of private property
rights in outer space, argues in favor of a
"quasi-territorial" jurisdiction for the establishment of any
kind of private property rights regime. In this sense the analysis that
follows has implications for civil law nations as well.
(5) See also Coffey (2009).
(6) Alternatively, one can think of y as the probability that Alice
and Bob's interaction in a particular period will be their
last--that is, the probability with which the game they're playing
ends each period (or as a parameter that reflects Alice and Bob's
discount rate and the probability with which the game they're
playing ends each period).
(7) Because outer space commerce requires large up-front
investments before net benefits can be secured--and even then only after
repeated periods of cooperative interaction with fellow space
entrepreneurs--the "space business" selects for individuals
who are patient.
(8) However, this isn't the only mechanism of self-enforcing
property rights that international traders rely on. For a discussion of
a second mechanism--one rooted in signaling--see Leeson (2006a, 2008a).
(9) This "snowballing" effect whereby the success of
least-cost norms and behaviors further entrenches their common usage is
a hallmark of spontaneous social institutions, such as the common law,
language, and even the use of money.
(10) See also Milgrom et al. (1990).
(11) We don't wish to ascribe empirical content to political
elites' motivations. Perhaps political elites in country X believe
the arrangement entered into by the individual citizen of country Y
violates the spirit of the treaty, and thus is an injustice requiring
rectification. Alternatively, these political elites may make
threatening gestures in the hope that they will be compensated with some
of the wealth generated by commercial space activities entered into by
the citizen of country Y and his or her co-parties. Both of these
scenarios, and countless others, are plausible.
(12) In doing so, our analysis also frees up intellectual and
physical resources that might otherwise be spent devising unnecessary
rationales for the de facto extension of sovereignty to celestial
bodies.
Figure 1
The Prisoner's Dilemma
Cooperate Defect
Cooperate A,A B,C
Defect C,B 0,0