Friedman and Samuelson on the business cycle.
Hammond, J. Daniel
Chicago School economists have come in for criticism since the
financial crisis and so-called Great Recession began in 2007.
Commentators have blamed recent problems on a laissez-faire faith in the
efficacy of markets and simple rules for business-cycle policy--ideas
associated with economics as taught and practiced at the University of
Chicago. Events over the past four years, we are told, demonstrate the
need for a restoration of Keynesian thinking about business cycles and
activist government policies to keep markets from failing, However,
there is another aspect of Chicago School economics that is commonly
overlooked. This is the conviction that economists' understanding
of the business cycle is meager in light of the knowledge necessary for
activist countercyclical policy to be effective. From this comes the
Chicago School concern that economists and policymakers not attempt to
do something beyond their capability. Overreaching can make the problems
worse.
In the public mind, Milton Friedman and Paul Samuelson represent
more than any other individuals two competing schools of thought that
dominated macroeconomic and business cycle debates over much of the past
century. As readers of their Newsweek columns from the late 1960s into
the 1980s learned, Friedman was the "conservative" Chicago
economist favoring free markets, deregulation, and rules-based monetary
policy. Samuelson was the "middle-of-the-road" economist,
favoring regulatory oversight of markets and activist monetary and
fiscal policy. Friedman was the monetarist and Samuelson the Keynesian.
Friedman died in 2006, so we do not have his commentary on the current
crisis. Samuelson died in 2009, and before his death spoke with
journalist Nathan Gardels of his and Friedman's respective ideas
and influence in light of the crisis.
Nathan Gardels: You have outlived Milton Friedman, who died in
2006. And now your Keynesian ideas have also outlived his radical
free-market ideology. Is economics back to where you started?
Paul Samuelson: You are right. I am old enough to have seen the
cycle come full circle. My experience is more valuable now than it
"was even a year ago, since I first became actively engaged in
economic policy on January 2, 1932, at the rock bottom of the Great
Depression, when I was an adviser to the Federal Reserve Bank in
Washington. In subsequent years, I was principal economic adviser to
President-elect John F. Kennedy in 1960 and recruited the team for his
Council of Economic Advisers.
I became a centrist early on. Of course, the central planning
system of the socialist states we still contested with ideologically in
those days was idiotic, but that didn't mean government
doesn't play a critical role.
And today we see how utterly mistaken was the Milton Friedman
notion that a market system can regulate itself [Samuelson 2011].
As Americans struggle in the current climate with what to believe
about economic conditions and policy, it is instructive to look back at
the ideas on business cycles and macroeconomic policy of these two
giants of 20th century economics.
Friedman: NBER Economist
The question of how much economists know about the business cycle,
and thus how much expertise they can bring to the policymaking table,
including crucially their ability to forecast business conditions, was
an important part of what separated Friedman's views from the
mainstream over the course of his career (see Hammond 1996). A good
place to begin seeing this difference is in the late 1940s, as Friedman
and Anna J. Schwartz embarked on their monetary project for the National
Bureau of Economic Research (NBER). Friedman's background was in
statistics and to a smaller extent business cycle analysis, but he had
little experience with monetary economics at the outset of their
project. His two most important mentors, Arthur F. Burns and Wesley C.
Mitchell, had instilled in him firm convictions of how to do economics.
From Bums he learned the Marshallian approach to economics, which
involved use of relatively lowbrow theory in close relation with
measureable entities theory that could be used to extract useful
information from data. From Mitchell Friedman learned the techniques
used at the NBER to analyze business cycle data, and he also learned
that constructing economic data is as important as constructing economic
theory.
Friedman's early perspective on business cycle analysis is
evident in his review of Jan Tinbergen's Business Cycles in the
United States of America, 1919-1932. Tinbergen's book was one of
the early attempts to estimate coefficients of a general equilibrium
model of the business cycle, work for which he was awarded the very
first Nobel Prize in Economic Science (shared with Ragnar Frisch).
Tinbergen and Frisch were cited "for having developed and applied
dynamic models for the analysis of economic processes"
(http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/ laureates/1969/#).
Friedman was less impressed in 1940 than the Nobel committee later was
in 1969, He wrote of the estimates:
Tinbergen's results cannot be judged by ordinary tests of
statistical significance. The reason is that the variables with which he
winds up, the particular series measuring these variables, the leads and
lags, and various other aspects of the equations besides the particular
values of the parameters ... have been selected after an extensive
process of trial and error because they yield high coefficients of
correlation [Friedman 1940: 659].
Friedman quoted his teacher Wesley Mitchell to the effect that a
statistician can take almost any pair of data series and manipulate them
to obtain a high correlation coefficient between the two. What Tinbergen
failed to do is to test his model with data from outside the sample that
he used to estimate the coefficients. Friedman did such a test in a
rudimentary form and found that the model did not explain the
out-of-sample observations very well.
A decade later Friedman commented on another test of a general
equilibrium business cycle model. In this case Carl Christ tested the
model on out-of-sample data, as Friedman had suggested for Tinbergen.
But Friedman was still not impressed with the results. He set up an
alternative, and extremely simple, model in which the values of
endogenous variables were predicted to be unchanged from period to
period. This was in effect running a contest between a highly
sophisticated model of the business cycle and "we know nothing
about the business cycle." "We know nothing" won the
contest! Friedman concluded that economists using the big general
equilibrium "system" models were striving for something well
beyond their reach. Greater progress would be made in "analysis of
parts of the economy in the hope that we can find bits of order here and
there and gradually combine these bits into a systematic picture of the
whole (Friedman 1951: 114).
We tend to think of Friedman as a monetarist and economists on the
other side of debates about business cycles as Keynesians. But the
critiques we just examined were before Friedman and Schwartz began their
money and business cycles project, and therefore before he was a
monetarist. The position he represented was the NBER approach to
business cycle analysis. His opponents in the 1940s tended to be
Keynesians, but the pressing issue was not so much what one thinks are
the causes and cures for the business cycle, as how one searches for
answers to the question and how much is known. A good illustration of
this debate is in Arthur Burns's 1946 annual report of the NBER,
where Burns was director of research. Burns criticized Keynesians for
presuming that they had figured out the business cycle, and for relying
on theory with scant resort to economic data other than highly
aggregated data. Keynesians saw compensatory fiscal policy as the
solution to the cycle. Referring to the set of assumptions behind the
analysis, about the shape and stability of the consumption function, the
relative size of consumption effects of tax cuts and tax hikes, and so
forth, Burns (1946: 11) concluded:
Although assumptions such as these may be extremely helpful at a
stage in our thinking about an exceedingly complicated problem, it
seems that the inferences to which they lead cannot be regarded as
a scientific guide to governmental policies.
Burns (1946: 21) continued:
Keynes' adventure in business cycle theory is by no means
exceptional. My reason for singling it out is merely that the
General Theory has become for many, contrary to Keynes' own wishes,
a sourcebook of established knowledge. Fanciful ideas about
business cycles are widely entertained both by men of affairs and
by academic economists. That is inevitable as long as the problem
is attacked on a speculative level, or if statistics serve only as
a casual check on speculation. To develop a reliable picture of the
business cycles of actual life it is necessary to study with fine
discrimination the historical records of numerous economic
activities.... Work on this plan is costly and time-consuming; it
means turning back, revising, rethinking, redoing; it often leads
to disappointments and taxes patience. But there is no reliable
shortcut to tested knowledge.
Friedman, Mitchell, and Burns's approach to business cycle
analysis and their sense of what was known and unknown about cycles was
viewed as outdated by many in the midst of enthusiam for Keynesian
theory and mathematization of economics and statistics. With the
mathematization of economic theory and statistics economists developed a
hubris for which experience at the National Bureau provided immunity.
This hubris is in full flower in Paul Samuelson's writings about
the business cycle.
Samuelson: Mathematical Economist
Paul Samuelson was a mathematical economist, whose work was by and
large pure theory, without empirical data. In the autobiography he wrote
for the Nobel Prize Samuelson quotes an earlier autobiographical piece
in which he proclaimed himself "the last 'generalist' in
economics." And he was indeed a generalist in subject matter if not
method. Lloyd Metzler's review of Samuelson's Foundations of
Economic Analysis (Metzler 1948), which was Samuelson's Ph.D.
dissertation, noted that the book was a contribution to economic method,
with illustrations of the method from a variety of fields such as
taxation, international trade, business cycles, money and banking, and
employment. But problems in these fields were not treated with depth.
That is, the analysis made no use of institutions and data. What
Samuelson's method offered in place of depth was unification. It
was mathematically difficult, but offered in the unification a kind of
simplification, for economic analysis in the disparate fields could be
reduced to problems of equilibrium and maximization. Metzler admired
Samuelson's contribution, but was skeptical that analysis could be
taken very far without resort to empirical evidence. This would be a
limitation, for example, "'in the study of complicated and
unsymmetrical systems such as one encounters in business cycle
theory" (Metzler 1948: 910).
Samuelson's was the second Nobel Prize in Economics. Assar
Lindbeck opened the 1970 presentation speech by calling attention to the
formalization of two sides of economies, statistical analysis and
economic theory. The previous year Frisch and Tinbergen were honored for
their contributions to the formalization of statistical theory and
analysis--econometrics "designed for immediate statistical
estimation and empirical application" (Lindbeck 1970). Samuelson
was being honored for his contributions to the formalization of economic
theory, "without any immediate aims of statistical, empirical
confrontation" (Lindbeck 1970).
Nonetheless, Samuelson regarded economics and all science as
empirical. In the opening chapter of his textbook Economics (1948), he
wrote:
It is the first task of modern economic science to describe, to
analyze, to explain, to correlate these fluctuations of national income.
Both boom and slump, price inflation and deflation, are our concern.
This is a difficult and complicated task. Because of the complexity of
human and social behavior, we cannot hope to attain the precision of a
few of the physical sciences. We cannot perform the controlled
experiments of the chemist or biologist. Like the astronomer we must be
content largely to "observe" [Samuelson 1948: 4].
And a few pages later:
Properly understood, therefore, theory and observation, deduction
and induction cannot be in conflict. Like eggs, there are only two kinds
of theories: good ones and bad ones. And the test of a theory's
goodness is its usefulness in illuminating observational reality. Its
logical elegance and fine-spun beauty are irrelevant. Consequently, when
a student says, "That's all right in theory but not in
practice," he really means "That's not all right in
theory," or else he is talking nonsense [Samuelson 1948: 8].
Several of Samuelson's earliest papers were on macroeconomics,
including "Interactions between Multiplier Analysis and the
Accelerator Principle" (1939) and "The Theory of Pump-Priming
Reexamined" (1940). These two articles provide us with a view of
how the mathematical formalist of Foundations (Samuelson 1947) handled
macroeconomic theory when most people writing in macroeconomics did so
with more words than mathematical symbols, more diagrams than theorems
and proofs. Samuelson's older contemporaries were economists such
as J. M. Keynes and Alvin H. Hansen, and Friedman's mentor Wesley
C. Mitchell.
In the 1939 article Samuelson sought to generalize multiplier
analysis along lines begun by Hansen. Samuelson's contribution was
to move the analysis from arithmetical examples to algebraic analysis of
income sequences contingent on a government expenditure stimulus---that
is, mathematization of multiplier-accelerator theory. Samuelson produced
a four-way taxonomy of the behavior of income under different assumed
combinations of multiplier and accelerator coefficients. He warned that
his analysis assumed a constant marginal propensity to consume and a
constant accelerator coefficient, although these would actually change
with the level of income. The analysis was thus
strictly a marginal analysis to be applied to the study of small
oscillations. Nevertheless, it is more general than the usual analysis.
Contrary to the impression commonly held, mathematical methods properly
employed, far from making economic theory more abstract, actually serve
as a powerful liberating device enabling the entertainment and analysis
of ever more realistic and complicated hypotheses [Samuelson 1939: 78].
In the 1940 article Samuelson considered whether a countercyclical
fiscal deficit might be self-eliminating--that is, whether the income
generated by the fiscal stimulus might produce enough tax revenue to
close the deficit. He presented no explicit mathematical analysis in the
article, beyond a reference to the 1939 piece, but reasoned to a theorem
of multiplier analysis "that the increase of expenditure of an
extra dollar cannot result in increased tax revenues of as much as a
dollar even though all succeeding time is taken into consideration"
(Samuelson 1940: 503).
He derived this conclusion from analytical assumptions and
analytical presumptions. By analytical assumptions I mean assumptions
the role of which was to simplify and thus facilitate analysis. By
analytical presumptions I mean presumptions about the nature of the
economic system. In the first category were the assumptions that induced
private investment is proportional to the increase in consumption from
one period to the next, and that prices remain unchanged. In the second
category were presumed actual characteristics of the economy:
The economic system is not perfect and frictionless so that there
exists the possibility of unemployment and underutilization of
productive resources.
There exists the possibility of, if not a definite tendency toward,
cumulative movements of a disequilibrating kind.
The average propensity to consume is less than one, at least at
high levels of national income.
Even in a perfect capital market there is no tendency for the rate
of interest to equilibrate the demand and supply of employment.
There exist no technical difficulties to prevent the government
from financing deficits of the magnitudes discussed [Samuelson 1940:
492-94].
Samuelson gave no justification for these presumptions other than
that they were regarded as fundamental in recent business cycle
literature.
He divided economic downturns into two categories: (1) downturns
that arise from exhaustion of investment opportunities, and (2)
downturns that arise from inventory accumulation based on expected but
unrealized price increases. He suggested that the Great Depression
belonged at least in part in the first category--that is, the Depression
was caused in part by exhaustion of investment opportunities. With
regard to recessions that are caused by unwarranted inventory
accumulation he suggested that "waiving the difficulties of quickly
engineering a spending policy, there seems to be every reason in this
case for the government to act promptly so as to maintain the national
income and aid in the orderly reduction of inventories" (Samuelson
1940: 497).
Notice how much is swept aside by Samuelson's waiver of the
difficulties of quickly engineering a spending policy--all of the
politics of budget writing plus the matter of targeting expenditures at
the industries that have surplus inventories. Also notice that if
Samuelson's two categories are exhaustive, then no downturns begin
in the public sector, from misguided fiscal policy or monetary policy.
What Friedman and Schwartz were to later conclude about the Great
Depression and what many economists believe exacerbated the recent real
estate bubble is ruled out a priori.
At a 1959 American Economic Association (AEA) session on price
level stability, Samuelson and Robert Solow devoted more than half of
their discussion to impediments to the use of historical data for
identification of different types of inflation: demand-pull, cost-push,
and demand shift. The authors were critical of one-sided explanations of
inflation for these typically ignored the "intricacies involved in
the demand for money," relied on aggregate ex post data and partial
equilibrium analysis, and failed to account for the possibility that
effects may precede causes. Following this rather pessimistic rendering
of the problems involved in evaluating historical instances of
inflation, Samuelson and Solow turned to A.W. Phillips's
"fundamental schedule relating unemployment and wage changes"
in the United Kingdom, the Phillips Curve. From a scatter plot of U.S.
data on unemployment rates and increases in hourly earnings, a plot
without showing actual numerical values, they offered suggestions about
the Phillips Curve for the United States. They began by noting
deficiencies in the data:
The first defect to note is the different coverages represented in
the two axes. Duesenberry has argued that postwar wage increases in
manufacturing on the one hand and in trade, services, etc., on the
other, may have quite different explanations: union power in
manufacturing and simple excess demand in the other sectors. It is
probably true that if we had an unemployment rate for manufacturing
alone, it would be somewhat higher during the post war years than the
aggregate figure shown. Even if a qualitative statement like this held
true over the whole period, the increasing weight of services in the
total might still create a bias. Another defect is our use of annual
increments and averages, when a full-scale study would have to look
carefully into the nuances of timing.
A first look at the scatter is discouraging; there are points all
over the place. But perhaps one can notice some systematic effects
[Samuelson and Solow 1960: 188].
The systematic effects that they inferred from the plot were:
1. 1933 to 1941 are sui generis; if there is a Phillips Curve it
has a positive slope. The anomaly is the result either of NRA pricing
codes or of structural unemployment.
2. The data for the early years of World War II are also atypical,
though less so.
3. The remainder of the data "show a consistent [Phillips
Curve] pattern."
4. The Phillips Curve shifted upward "slightly but
noticeably" in the 1940s and 1950s. In the earlier period
"manufacturing wages seem to stabilize absolutely when 4 or 5
percent of the labor force is u employed," but since 1946 "one
would judge now that it would take more like 8 percent unemployment to
keep money wages from rising."
5. The data may or may not represent an aggregate supply curve. If
so, the movements along it indicate demand pull and shifts indicate cost
push. But if employers in anticipating full employment give wage
increases during slack periods, this makes it problematic to interpret
the Phillips Curve relationship as an aggregate supply curve.
Samuelson and Solow (1960: 191) conclude on this pessimistic note:
We have concluded that it is not possible on the basis of a priori
reasoning to reject either the demand-pull or cost-push hypothesis,
or the variants of the latter such as demand-shift. We have also
argued that the empirical identifications needed to distinguish
between these hypotheses may be quite impossible from the
experience of macrodata that is available to us; and that, while
use of microdata might throw additional light on the problem, even
here identification is fraught with difficulties and ambiguities.
Despite their pessimistic acknowledgment of the difficulties,
Samuelson and Solow (1960) ventured "guesses" portrayed in
their Figure 2, which is a smooth, nonlinear Phillips Curve
"roughly estimated" from the most recent 25 years of data. The
guesses are that (1) an unemployment rate of 5-6 percent is necessary
for wage increases to match productivity growth, and (2) to keep
unemployment at 3 percent, inflation must be 5 percent.
They warned that the policy tradeoffs indicated by their Phillips
Curve were at best short-term. The tradeoffs could well change in the
future. Nonetheless, their diagram and inferences are surprisingly
precise in light of the serious difficulties they brought to light about
drawing inferences from the data.
Shortly after he presented the paper with Solow at the 1959 AEA
meeting, Samuelson wrote an evaluation of Federal Reserve policy. The
primary question on his mind was what might be inferred from both the
Fed's policy record and criticisms that the Fed had waited overly
long to ease credit conditions in 1957. Samuelson took issue with two
lines of criticism: (1) the claim that monetary policy was powerless,
and (2) the claim that the Fed would gain from a fixed policy rule. (1)
His argument against a policy rule was based on the same presumption as
Milton Friedman's argument for a policy rule--namely, that little
was known of the complexities of the macroeconomy. Where Friedman drew
the implication from economists" ignorance that a rule could be
used to minimize mistakes, Samuelson drew the implication that the rule
itself was likely to be ill-designed and thus exacerbate business
cycles. He advocated policy based on two principles: "prudent
man" forecasting and willingness to respond quickly to changing
conditions.
I would say that the problem of lags should predispose us even more
toward the following view: instead of adapting policy passively to the
recent past, the authorities should try to form a judgment of what a
prudent informed man thinks the rough probabilities are for a couple of
quarters ahead and should take action accordingly, being perfectly
prepared to change their tack as new evidence becomes available to
modify these prudent probabilities [Samuelson 1960: 264].
Samuelson's statement brings to the foreground the question,
Who is the "prudent informed man"? Is he a mathematical
economist, a pure theorist, or one with a more empirical bent who looks
long and hard at data?
Theory, Evidence, and Prudence
Anna Schwartz brought experience and expertise in money and banking
to the monetary factors in business cycles project that she and Friedman
took up at the request of Arthur Burns in 1948. She had compiled a data
series for currency covering the period 1917 to 1944, and was working on
the companion series for bank deposits. In spring 1948 she sent Friedman
a list of readings on monetary and banking history, warning him that the
literature was pretty bad, but suggesting that he would acquire less
misinformation from the readings on her list than from others. Friedman
spent the summer reading and joined Schwartz in the work of compiling
data. This is a point worth noting. Friedman and Schwartz began their
monetary project not by reading monetary theory or macroeconomic theory,
but by building data and reading banking history. And this was to become
a hallmark of their approach to monetary economics; their work was
empirical and historical.
Friedman made several proposals for reforming monetary policy over
the course of his career. The proposals were all in the direction of
streamlining and simplifying policy, and protecting the public from
arbitrary use of power by policymakers. In A Program for Monetary
Stability (1960) he proposed confining monetary policy to a single
instrument, open market operations; requiring 100 percent reserves on
all bank deposits; and requiring that open market operations be guided
by a money stock growth rate rule. Friedman acknowledged that his
proposal for a fixed money stock growth rule was counterintuitive. In
theory "leaning against the wind"-discretionary policy--looked
better than a "do nothing" fixed money growth rate rule. But
Friedman predicted that in practice the rule would provide more
stability than discretionary "leaning against the wind."
Why? First, because the empirical evidence compiled by Friedman and
Schwartz suggested that changes in the growth rate of the money stock
had effects that were long and variable. (2) This meant that in order to
effectively lean against the wind, the Fed would have to lean against
future winds. Not only that. Because of the variability of the lag, they
would have to lean against a wind that would be blowing at an uncertain
time in the future. Second, he opposed leaving policy open to Fed
officials' discretion because countercyclical policy was open to
different interpretations as to content. For example, is the policy
objective price level stability or low unemployment, or both; and how
stable and how low; and stable and low over what time frame? It was too
easy to agree that the Fed should lean against the wind because that
directive was a container with a "stabilization" label, but
without definite content. Therefore, people with diverse ideas of the
content could agree ex ante that the Fed should lean against the wind,
but have little basis for agreement ex post about whether it had
effectively done so. Friedman thought that disagreement, uncertainty,
and lack of accountability were built in to any system without a clear
policy target.
In contrast with Samuelson's ability to begin and finish a
formal theoretical project on his own in a brief time, Friedman's
empirical and historical work involved a team of researchers including
not only himself and Anna Schwartz, but a host of students in the
Workshop in Money and Banking. (3) Where Samuelson's goal was a
unified theory of disparate economic phenomena, Friedman's goal was
an empirically verified theory of one particular economic phenomenon,
the business cycle. He presented the first somewhat complete results to
the Joint Economic Committee of the U.S. Congress in 1958, a decade
after his call for this research. In recommending that the growth rate
of the money stock be set at a constant 3 to 5 percent per year, he
wrote:
The extensive empirical work that I have done since that article
["A Monetary and Fiscal Framework for Economic Stability"
(1948)] was written has given me no reason to doubt that the
arrangements there suggested would produce a higher degree of stability;
it has, however, led me to believe that much simpler arrangements would
do so also; that something like the simple policy suggested above would
produce a very tolerable amount of stability. This evidence has
persuaded me that the major problem is to prevent monetary changes from
themselves contributing to instability rather than to use monetary
changes to offset other forces [Friedman 1958: 106, n. 19]. (4)
Friedman and Schwartz's "Money and Business Cycles"
(1963) illustrates the difference in Friedman's heavily empirical
approach to macroeconomics and Samuelson's approach as we have seen
it in several articles. Friedman and Schwartz used 32 pages to present
and analyze extensive data records of money and business cycle turning
points, with data coveting the period from 1867 to 1960. They observed
first that the money stock tended to rise rather than fall through most
business cycle contractions. They removed the positive trend from the
series by taking logarithmic first differences and examined patterns in
rates of change in the money stock over deep and mild contractions. Then
they presented the data both in charts and in numerical tables to
uncover the cyclical timing and amplitude of money growth through NBER
reference cycles. In their analysis everything is out on the table.
Friedman and Schwartz made interpretive judgments about patterns in
their data, as Samuelson and Solow did about changes in hourly earnings
and unemployment, but they presented all the information readers would
need to make their own judgments. Their conclusions for major business
cycles were that (1) "There is a one-to-one relation between money
changes and changes in money income and prices," and (2) "The
changes in the stock of money cannot consistently be explained by the
contemporary changes in money income and prices" (Friedman and
Schwartz 1963: 50).
By this they meant that although causation goes both ways between
money and nominal income, money has an active role in the business
cycle. In particular,
There seems to us, accordingly, to be an extraordinarily strong
ease for the proposition that (1) appreciable changes in the rate of
growth of the stock of money are a necessary and sufficient condition
for appreciable changes in the rate of growth of money income; and that,
(2) this is true both for long secular changes and also for changes over
periods roughly the length of business cycles. To go beyond the evidence
and discussion thus far presented: our survey of experiences leads us to
conjecture that the longer-period changes in money income produced by a
changed secular rate of growth of the money stock are reflected mainly
in different price behavior rather than in different rates of growth of
output; whereas the shorter period changes in the rate of growth of the
money stock are capable of exerting a sizable influence on the rate of
growth of output as well [Friedman and Schwartz 1963: 53].
From their analysis of the evidence Friedman and Schwartz provided
their own version of what Samuelson strived for and was generally
acknowledged by other economists to have attained a unified theory of
economic phenomena. Only for Samuelson the unification was in the
mathematical method of constrained optimization1 Friedman and
Schwartz's unification was in observed empirical regularities, in a
monetary explanation of business cycles.
Friedman and Schwartz were well aware that their explanation of
business cycles was in competition with others, such as the Keynesian
theory that investment was the prime cause:
It is perhaps worth emphasizing and repeating that any alternative
interpretation must meet two tests: it must explain why the major
movements in income occurred when they did, and also it must explain why
such major movements should have been uniformly accompanied by
corresponding movements in the rate of growth of the money stock. The
monetary interpretation explains both at the same time....
We have emphasized the difficulty of meeting the second test, But
even the first alone is hard to meet except by an explanation which
asserts that different factors may from time to time produce large
movements in income, and that these factors may operate through diverse
channels which is essentially to plead utter ignorance [Friedman 1958:
54].
Conclusion
Paul Samuelson was a vigorous advocate for the mathematization of
economics, recognizing the particular virtue of math in laying bare
logical relationships. But mathematical general equilibrium did not
equip him to say much at all about economic conditions and policies of
any particular time and place. This task was left to the "prudent
informed man." Presumably the prudent man would be informed about
empirical regularities, for in his principles textbook Samuelson
affirmed that science is based on observation. "Like eggs, there
are only two kinds of theories: good ones and bad ones. And the test of
a theory's goodness is its usefulness in illuminating observational
reality. Its logical elegance and fine-spun beauty are irrelevant"
(Samuelson 1948: 8).
Friedman (1946) observed in a critique of Oscar Lange's Price
Flexibility and Employment, an example of the mathematical approach used
and advocated by Samuelson, that economists using this approach to deal
with real-world problems invariably resort to empirical observations and
claims. In contrast with the rigor and clarity of their mathematical
theory, their observation of data and institutions tends to be casual
and obscure. We have seen this to be the case with Samuelson. In a 1967
discussion with Arthur Bums, Samuelson described his forecasting
technique:
I am not now referring to the regressions of the computer but I am
speaking now of the regressions of the mind, the intuitive forecasting
which I do. The other day a colleague of mine... said to me, "Paul,
how long do you think it will take before a computer will replace
you?" ... I thought for a moment, and as the question seemed to be
asked in a mean way, I replied, "Not in a million years"
[Burns and Samuelson 1967: 92-93].
Friedman was more modest about what he knew, less sanguine about
what any experts knew, and believing in the power of monetary policy,
more wary of the potential for harm from misguided policies. He also was
committed to systematic examination of data bearing on the business
cycle. In the words of his mentor Arthur Burns, Friedman believed that
"there is no reliable shortcut to tested knowledge." The
program in business cycle research on which Friedman and Schwartz
embarked in 1948 was begun by Wesley Mitchell at the beginning of the
20th century. After more than half a century of painstaking research the
results were still "provisional." The project had produced
knowledge, but not of the type and detail that would allow macroeconomic
fine-tuning. We would do well to keep this in mind as politicians,
pundits, and government economists make claims that they have unlocked
the mysteries of the business cycle.
References
Burns, A. F. (1946) Economic Research and the Keynesian Thinking of
Our Times. Annual Report. New York: National Bureau of Economic
Research.
Burns, A. F., and Samuelson, P. A. (1967) Full Employment,
Guideposts, and Economic Stability. Washington: American Enterprise
Institute.
Friedman, M. (1940) "Review of Business Cycles in the United
States of America by Jan Tinbergen." American Economic Review 30
(3): 657-60.
--(1946) "Lange on Price Flexibility and Employment: A
Methodological Criticism." American Economic Review 36 (4): 613-31.
Reprinted in Essays in Positive Economics, 277-300. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1953,
--(1948) "A Monetary and Fiscal Framework for Economic
Stability." American Economic Review 38 (3): 245-64.
--(1951) "Comment on 'A Test of an Econometric Model for
the United States, 1921-1947,' by Carl Christ." In Conference
on Business Cycles, 107-14. New York: National Bureau of Economic
Research.
--(1958) "The Supply of Money and Changes in Prices and
Output." In The Relationship of Prices to Economic Stability and
Growth: Compendium. Washington: U.S. Government Printing Office.
--(1959) Testimony (on 25 May 1959, 86th Cong., 1st sess., pursuant
to S.Con. Res. 13) and "The Quantity Theory of Money: A
Restatement." In U.S. Congress, Joint Economic Committee, Hearings
on Employment, Growth, and Price Levels, part 4: 605-69. Washington:
Government Printing Office,
--(1960) A Program for Monetary Stability. New York: Fordham
University Press.
--(1961) "The Lag in Effect of Monetary Policy." Journal
of Political Economy 69 (5): 447-66.
Friedman, M., and Schwartz, A. J. (1963) "Money and Business
Cycles." Review of Economics and Statistics 45, Supplement
(February): 32-64.
Hammond, J. D. (1996) Theory and Measurement: Causality Issues in
Milton Friedman's Monetary Economics. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Lindbeck, A. (1970) Presentation Speech, 1970 Nobel Prize in
Economics. Available at
http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/1970/press.html.
Metzler, L. (1948) "Review of Foundations of Economic
Analysis." American Economic Review 38 (5): 905-10.
Samuelson, P. A. (1939) "Interactions between the Multiplier
Analysis and the Principle of Acceleration." Review of Economics
and Statistics 21 (2): 75-78.
--(1940) "The Theory of Pump-Priming Reexamined."
American Economic Review 30 (3): 492-506.
--(1947) Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
--(1948) Economics. New York: McGraw-Hill.
--(1960) "Reflections on Monetary Policy." Review of
Economics and Statistics 42 (3): 263-69.
--(2011) "Don't Expect Recovery before 2012--with 8%
Inflation." New Perspectives Quarterly 28 (2). Available at www,
digitalnpq.org/articles/economic/331/01_16_2009/paul_samuelson.
Samuelson, P. A., and Solow, R. M. (1960) "Analytical Aspects
of Anti-inflation Policy." American Economic Review 50 (2): 177-94.
(1) The previous year Friedman had proposed a fixed money stock
growth rate rule in testimony before the Joint Economic Committee (see
Friedman 1958).
(2) On average 16 months from the peak in money growth to the peak
in general business activity, and 12 months from trough to trough, with
the range of lags from 6 to 29 months for peaks and 4 to 22 months for
troughs.
(3) In the early years his students included Phillip Cagan, David
Meiselman, John J. Klein, Richard T. Selden, and Eugene Lerner.
(4) See also Friedman (1959, 1960, 1961).
J. Daniel Hammond is Hultquist Family Professor in the Department
of Economies at Wake Forest University. Prior versions of this article
were presented at conferences sponsored by the BB&T Center for the
Study of Capitalism at Wake Forest University and the History of
Economies Society, and at the Duke University History of Political
Economy (HOPE) lunch seminar. For comments the author thanks Roger
Backhouse, John Dalton, Art Diamond, Claire Hammond, Robert L. Hetzel,
Kevin D. Hoover, Sandeep Mazumder, Mary Morgan, John H. Wood, and two
Cato Journal referees.