What can aid do?
Skarbek, David B. ; Leeson, Peter T.
Under normal conditions, devoting more resources to X'S
production produces more X. This follows from the nature of the physical
world, which positively relates quantities of outputs to quantities of
inputs used in their production. In principles of economics classes, it
is common to highlight that this relationship has nothing to do with the
economic problem. The economic problem asks how to produce X in the
least-cost way, whether to produce more or less X, and indeed, whether
to produce any X at all given the alternative uses of the inputs
required to produce it.
Solving the economic problem determines whether a country's
economy develops. It is strange, then, that professional economists have
had trouble distinguishing the positive relationship between inputs and
outputs from solving the economic problem when it comes to evaluating
foreign aid. (1) The purpose of this article is to make this
distinction, and in doing so to clarify what aid can and cannot do.
Foreign aid's advocates claim aid has been successful. Aids
critics claim aid has failed. We explain why both camps are correct. Aid
can, and in a few cases has, increased a particular output by devoting
more resources to its production. In this sense, aid has occasionally
had limited success. However, aid cannot, and has not, contributed to
the solution of economic problems and therefore economic growth. In this
much more important sense, aid has failed.
Flashbacks from Econ 101
Economic progress requires economic efficiency: resource
allocations that maximize resources' value to society. Economic
efficiency improves when economic actors move resources from less-valued
uses to more-valued ones. Economic actors tend to move resources in this
way when they make their decisions in an institutional environment
defined by private property rights? In this institutional environment,
market prices emerge that communicate information to entrepreneurs about
how to use resources in ways that enhance wealth, and entrepreneurs have
incentives to act on this information (see Mises 1920, Hayek 1945,
Kirzner 1978, Coyne and Leeson 2004). Central planning, which attempts
to allocate resources without private property and market prices, cannot
allocate resources efficiently because central planners can't learn
about resource allocations that maximize resources' value (Mises
1920, Hayek 1945). (3)
Since central planning cannot promote economic efficiency, it
cannot promote economic progress. Nevertheless, like anyone else,
central planners can increase a given output by devoting more resources
to its production. There is nothing surprising about this fact. The
nature of the physical world, including the positive relationship
between inputs and outputs, is as true for central planners as for
anyone else. The distinction between a central planner's ability to
increase a particular output by devoting more resources to its
production and his ability to solve the economic problem is where most
evaluations of foreign aid go awry.
An example from the real world illustrates the relationship, or
rather lack of relationship, between increasing a predetermined output
by devoting more resources to its production and solving the economic
problem. Before its collapse, the Soviet Union devoted substantial
resources to training scientists and engineers. Because of these
expenditures, during the 1980s the Soviet Union had 10-30 percent more
scientists and engineers than the United States (Dezhina and Graham
1999). Occasionally, people pretend this fact illuminates the relative
efficiency of these countries' contrasting economic systems.
It does no such thing. If the United States had devoted as many
resources to training scientists and engineers as the Soviet Union, it
could have produced as many scientists and engineers, and perhaps many
more. However, the United States allowed private citizens to determine
resource allocations in a way the Soviet Union did not. Under the
institution of private property, U.S. citizens used market prices to
direct resources to ends they valued more than additional scientists and
engineers. While the United States had fewer people trained in these
professions, it was richer than the Soviet Union because markets
consider alternative uses when they allocate resources. Although the
Soviet Union had many more scientists and engineers, it was poorer than
the United States because central planners allocated resources without
considering alternative uses.
What Can Aid Do?
Before discussing what aid can do, we discuss what it cannot do.
Foreign aid cannot make recipient economies grow. As Easterly (2006)
points out, foreign aid is akin to central planning with externally
gifted funds. Central planning cannot create economic growth because it
lacks private property and market prices, which prevents it from solving
economic problems. It follows that aid, therefore, cannot generate
economic growth either.
For example, the influential Harrod-Domar model suggests financing
the difference between the investment required to achieve some growth
rate and a developing country's savings. While aid may supply
additional capital to poor countries, these finances do not tell
recipient planners how to invest them in economically efficient
ways--that is, in ways that produce wealth.
Hayek (1944) pointed out that central planning "works"
when it has only one will to satisfy and one goal to focus on achieving.
(4) Under such circumstances, there is no economic problem to solve
because there are no competing demands for resource uses and
consequently no trade-offs for planners to negotiate. This is why
central planning tends to be more effective during war. During war,
there's a more-or-less singular end--victory. For the same reason,
aid is more effective when it is aimed at a singular, predetermined end,
such as reducing malaria.
However, this "effectiveness" does not help aid solve the
economic problem that keeps poor countries poor. There isn't a
unified, lexicographic preference for one good in developing economies.
There are many different individuals with different and conflicting
demands, and thus different and conflicting uses for scarce resources.
Developing countries confront an economic problem--one regarding
appropriate resource allocations. Foreign and domestic aid planners
don't know how to use aid in ways that generate a pattern of
resource movement away from less-valued uses toward more-valued ones.
Thus, as Andrei Shleifer (2009: 380) puts it, "The consensus that
aid has failed is nearly universal among those who look at the
data." (5) Aid cannot solve economic problems.
So, what can aid do? Like other forms of central planning, aid can
increase X by devoting additional resources to X's production.
Returning to our example from the Soviet Union, aid can produce more
scientists and engineers. If planners pick a specific outcome, such as
more immunizations, aid can provide additional resources to produce
immunizations. All of the "'success stories" that
aid's advocates highlight are of this nature.
In his book The End of Poverty, aid's most prominent academic
advocate, Jeffrey Sachs (2006), provides a list of aid
"successes." These successes include the Green Revolution in
Asia, the eradication of small pox, improvements in children's
health, dispersions of vaccines, reductions in the spread of malaria,
control of African river blindness, the eradication of polio,
improvements in family planning, and the mobile phone revolution in
Bangladesh.
Though Easterly is an aid critic, the aid "successes" he
highlights also involve increasing a particular output by devoting more
resources to its production (Easterly 2006: 175-77). These successes
include programs designed to keep Bangladeshi girls in school, reduce
the percentage of malnourished children in Bangladesh, control
tuberculosis deaths, improve child nutrition in Tanzania, and reduce
infant mortality. Easterly (2009) argues that education and health
programs in Africa in particular have been successful. He notes the
achievements of the "elimination of smallpox, the near-eradication
of river blindness and Guinea worm, the spread of oral rehydration
therapy for treating infant diarrheal diseases, DDT campaigns against
malarial mosquitoes ... and the success of WHO vaccination programs
against measles and other childhood diseases. The aid campaign against
diseases in Africa ... is likely the single biggest success story in the
history of aid to Africa" (Easterly 2009: 406-07).
In pointing out that aid can produce more of a given output by
increasing expenditures on that output, we have delineated the maximum
aid can do. In many cases aid has failed even to achieve this. Sometimes
aid resources intended for a particular output do not lead to more of
that output because of incentive problems and a lack of knowledge about
local conditions that impede aid's application. (6) Corruption is
sufficient to prevent aid from increasing a particular, targeted output.
If a recipient government corruptly appropriates aid resources intended
for vaccinations and diverts these resources to its supporters instead,
vaccinations may not increase despite the attempt to devote more
resources to their production. (7)
Conclusion
At least in principle, foreign aid can increase X by devoting more
resources to X's production. In some cases aid has managed to do
this in practice. Aid advocates herald these cases as evidence of
aid's "'success." However, these cases are
"successes" in the same sense that the Soviet Union's
army of scientists and engineers was a "success." They are
successes of increasing a predetermined output by devoting more
resources to its production. They are not economic successes. Aid
cannot, and has not, increased economic growth. Economic growth requires
a solution to the economic problem of how to allocate resources in ways
that maximize their value. Like other forms of central planning, aid
necessarily remains silent on this question. In this much more important
sense, aid's critics are correct that aid has failed.
Aid's advocates and critics should be clearer about what they
mean when they say aid can and can't "work." The
distinction this article makes explains why it is possible to both
acknowledge the aid "success stories" that aid's
advocates highlight and consider aid a doomed approach to development.
By clarifying what aid can and can't do, we hope our analysis helps
economists and policymakers evaluate aid's potential more sensibly.
References
Boettke, R J., and Leeson, R T. (2002) "Hayek, Arrow, and the
Problems of Democratic Decision-Making." Journal of Public Finance
and Public Choice 20 (1): 921.
--(2004) "Liberalism, Socialism, and Robust Political
Economy." Journal of Markets and Morality 7 (1): 99-111.
Coyne, C. J., and Leeson, R T. (2004) "The Plight of
Underdeveloped Countries." Cato Journal 23 (4): 235-49.
Coyne, C. J., and Ryan, M. E. (2009) "With Friends Like These,
Who Needs Enemies? Aiding the World's Worst Dictators."
Independent Review 14 (1): 26-44.
Dezhina, I., and Graham, L. (1999) "Science and Higher
Education in Russia." Science 286 (5443): 1303-04.
Easterly, W. (2002) The Elusive Quest for Growth: Economists"
Adventures and Misadventures in the Tropics'. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
--(2006) The White Man's Burden: Why the West's Efforts
to Aid the Rest Have Done So Much Ill and So Little Good. New York:
Penguin Books.
--(2009) "Can the West Save Africa?" Journal of Economic
Literature 47 (2): 373-447.
Gibson, C. C.; Andersson, K.; Ostrom, E.; and Shivakumar, S. (2005)
The Samaritan's Dilemma: The Political Economy of Development Aid.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gwartney, J., and Lawson, R. (2008) Economic Freedom of the World:
2008 Annual Report. Vancouver, Canada: Fraser Institute.
Hayek, E A. (1944) The Road to Serfdom. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
--(1945) "The Use of Knowledge in Society." American
Economic Review 35 (4): 519-30.
Kirzner, I. M. (1978) Competition and Entrepreneurship. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Leeson, P. T. (2008) "Escaping Poverty: Foreign Aid, Private
Property, and Economic Development." Journal of Private Enterprise
23 (2): 39-64.
--(2009) "Two Cheers for Capitalism?" Mimeo. Fairfax,
Va.: George Mason University.
Mises, L. yon (1990 [1920]). Economic Calculation in the Socialist
Commonwealth. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
Moyo, D. (2009) Dead Aid: Why Aid Is Not Working and How There Is
Another Way for Africa. London: Allen Lane.
Sachs, J. (2006) The End of Poverty: Economic Possibilities of Our
Time. New York: Penguin Books.
Shleifer, A. (2009) "Peter Bauer and the Failure of Foreign
Aid." Cato Journal 29 (3): 379-90.
Tullock, G. (2002) Government Failure: A Primer in Public Choice.
Washington: Cato Institute.
(1) Easterly (2009) comes close to making this distinction in his
recent summary of the aid literature on Africa, where he identifies the
key change between large and rapid "transformational" programs
and smaller, "marginal" changes.
(2) Evidence for the positive relationship between private property
rights and economic progress is voluminous. For just a few recent
examples, see Gwartney and Lawson (2008) and Leeson (2009).
(3) This is true even if central planners have incentives to
allocate resources efficiently, which is highly questionable (see
Boettke and Leeson 2004).
(4) For a discussion of Hayek's "one will" idea and
its relationship to Arrow's impossibility theorem, see Boettke and
Leeson (2002).
(5) See Easterly 2002, 2006; Leeson 2008; and Moyo 2009.
(6) In fact, Coyne and Ryan (2009) find that a large amount of
foreign aid goes to the world's worst dictators, which suggests
that some aid programs might be financing the accomplishment of a
single, illiberal end.
(7) On the problems of government failure that can plague the
foreign aid process as much as other political processes, see Tullock
(2002). On these problems in the foreign aid process in particular, see
Gibson et al. (2005).
David B. Skarbek is a doctoral candidate in the Department of
Economics at George Mason University. Peter T. Leeson is BB&T
Professor for the Study of Capitalism at George Mason University and
Visiting Professor of Economics in the Becker Center on Chicago Price
Theory at the University of Chicago. The authors thank the Mereatus
Center at George Mason University for financial support.