Science, public policy, and global warming: rethinking the market-liberal position.
Dolan, Edwin G.
A survey of market-liberal or libertarian publications and websites
finds a large and growing literature on the issue of global warming.
Almost without exception, this literature conveys a comforting message:
Our planet is in good health. The markets that regulate resource use are
working well. The only real dangers come from ill-considered policy
initiatives that, if implemented, would do more harm than good. It would
seem that the message is well received by its audience--it is repeated,
embellished, and applauded with little variation.
In this article, I take a contrarian position, not so much with
respect to the science of climate change as with respect to the
arguments used by market liberals in support of their message of comfort
and complacency. One problem area concerns the proper use of scientific
evidence in reaching conclusions regarding public policy. It seems to me
that market liberals are often reckless in the degree of certainty they
professes regarding climatological hypotheses that are, in fact, still
controversial and in early stages of development. A second problem
concerns the use of cost-benefit analysis. Market-liberal writers are
prone to make cost-benefit arguments regarding climate policy that they
would never accept in other contexts. Third, the literature on global
warming is often weakly rooted, if rooted at all, in the core principles
of classical liberalism from which modern market liberalism has evolved.
Instead, it is, for the most part, indistinguishable from what is said
by conservatives. It might even be said that there is no market-liberal
position on this issue--only an echo of arguments made by Republican
patriots and the carbon lobby.
In short, the whole issue of global warming policy, as viewed by
market liberals, needs to be revisited. This can best be done by going
back to some of the classical liberal sources, particularly Friedrich
Hayek and John Locke, from which modern market-liberal thought is
derived.
Hayek on Liberalism, Conservatism, and Science
A good place to start the rethinking process is with Hayek's
essay, "Why I am Not a Conservative" (1960). Hayek identifies
a number of traits that distinguish conservatism from market liberalism
("liberalism" without a modifier, in his terminology):
* Habitual resistance to change, hence the term
"conservative."
* Lack of understanding of spontaneous order as a guiding principle
of economic life.
* Use of state authority to protect established privileges against
the forces of economic change.
* Claim to superior wisdom based on self-arrogated superior quality
in place of rational argument.
* A propensity to reject scientific knowledge because of dislike of
the consequences that seem to follow from it.
Hayek points out that it is wrong to represent the political
spectrum as a line, with leftists at one end, conservatives at the
other, and liberals somewhere in the middle. Instead, he represents the
political playing field as a triangle with socialists, liberals, and
conservatives each occupying their respective corners.
When the political left advances proposals for increased state
intervention in free markets, liberals tend to see conservatives as
their natural allies. This was especially true in the 1940s and 1950s,
the background for Hayek's 1960 essay, when socialism seemed to be
on the ascendancy. In Hayek's view, the alliance of liberals with
conservatives was reinforced by the fact that, in the America of his
time, it was possible to promote individual liberty by defending
long-established institutions, not just because they were long
established, but because they corresponded with liberal ideals.
In our own day, alliances between market liberals and modern
conservatives are still possible, but as the nature of conservatism has
changed, issues have emerged where market liberals' natural allies
are found on the political left. Defense of human rights and due process
against expanding executive power is one example. Protecting freedom of
personal choice against government-imposed standards of morality is
another. In these cases the alliance of market liberals with the left is
rooted in genuine shared values.
In addition, market liberals and parties of the left may sometimes
form a united front to attack the entrenched privileges of state-favored
elites. However, in this case the alliance is more opportunistic than
principled, since the two allies are likely to see different solutions
to the problem of privilege. Whereas the left seeks to overthrow
privilege by imposing state regulation, market liberals want to remove
regulations in order to expose privileged positions to the influence of
competition.
In order to apply Hayek's political triangle to the issue of
global warming, we need to address several questions. One issue is what
the status is of the privileges and interests of those who are
threatened by the possibility of climate change and of those who are
threatened by proposed actions to mitigate it. Which of these has the
greater claim to the sympathy of market liberals, when viewed in terms
of the standards they apply in other areas of public policy? Another
issue is what the values are that lie behind the positions taken by
various parties to the debate. The issue of values may determine when
market liberals can make principled alliances with one of the other
corners of the triangle and when they want to make only tactical
alliances. Still another issue is what manner of argument should be
employed. For example, what is the proper attitude toward the purely
scientific element in the global warming controversy? It will be worth
taking a closer look at this last issue before proceeding further.
Hayek expresses himself so well on the role of science that it is
worth quoting him at length:
Personally, I find that the most objectionable feature of the
conservative attitude is its propensity to reject
well-substantiated new knowledge because it dislikes some of
the consequences which seem to follow from it--or, to put it
bluntly, its obscurantism. I will not deny that scientists as
much as others are given to fads and fashions and that we have
much reason to be cautious in accepting the conclusions that they
draw from their latest theories. But the reasons for our reluctance
must themselves be rational and must be kept separate from our
regret that the new theories upset our cherished beliefs .... By
refusing to face the facts, the conservative only weakens his own
position. Frequently the conclusions which rationalist presumption
draws from new scientific insights do not at 'all follow from them.
But only by actively taking part in the elaboration of the
consequences of new discoveries do we learn whether or not
they fit into our world picture and, if so, how. Should our moral
beliefs really prove to be dependent on factual assumptions shown
to be incorrect, it would hardly be moral to defend them by
refusing to acknowledge facts [Hayek 1960: 404].
This passage raises obvious questions for the global warming
debate. What lies behind the skepticism of market liberals regarding the
propositions that the world is getting warmer at a rate that is
unusually rapid in climate history, if not altogether unprecedented, and
that this apparent trend is likely the joint product of natural cycles
and human activity, rather than of the former acting alone? Are liberals
correctly rejecting an inadequately grounded scientific fad'? Or
are they refusing to acknowledge facts for fear that doing so would
upset their cherished beliefs?
Perhaps some market liberals believe that global warming poses an
unacceptable dilemma that would force them, one way or another, to act
against their deeply held principles. They might, on the one hand,
believe that the mechanism of market adaptation through spontaneous
order is too fragile to cope with the pace of environmental change that
some climatologists foresee and, on the other hand, think that the only
imaginable policies for coping with climate change involve an
intolerable degree of state intervention. If so, they might refuse to
consider evidence that a problem exists rather than face a perceived
choice between roasting or succumbing to tyranny in order to remain
cool.
Fortunately, the supposed dilemma is a false one. Liberals have
long acclaimed the market as a way of adapting to change, and climate
change should be no exception. For example, Robert Davis (2000) of the
University of Virginia has showed how air-conditioning and other
market-mediated innovations, have, over recent decades, reduced
mortality from urban heat waves.
Also, market liberals should know well that effective environmental
policy does not have to take the form of heavy-handed
command-and-control measures. In dealing with local air pollution,
traffic congestion, and land-use issues, market liberals have developed
imaginative, workable proposals and in several cases have made headway
in getting them adopted. As recently as the 1970s, market-based
solutions to environmental problems were regarded as libertarian science
fiction. Beginning with the use of averaging, banking, and trading in
dealing with lead gasoline additives in the 1980s, and continuing with
policies dealing with CFC (chlorofluorocarbon) phaseout, NOx (nitrogen
oxide) precursors for acid rain, and continuing with the very recent
Environmental Protection Agency measures on mercury pollution, market
mechanisms have become very much part of the mainstream. Similarly,
congestion pricing for urban roadways, also once regarded as science
fiction, is now an established policy in cities like New York,
Singapore, Melbourne, and Toronto. The same kind of market-oriented
policies should be possible in the case of climate change.
In short, if one takes into account both the market's
potential for adapting to change and market-based policy alternatives,
there is no reason for market liberals to be anything but open-minded
toward ongoing developments in climate science, whether those
developments, as they unfold, reveal indications or counter-indications
of global warming.
There could, instead, be another explanation for some market
liberals' apparent close-mindedness toward the global warming
hypothesis. It could be that, when taking a position on issues of
climatology, they are speaking not from perceived threats to their
beliefs, but out of loyalty to conservative interests with whom they
have struck some tactical alliance. For example, policies designed to
reduce greenhouse gas emissions, no matter how carefully market-guided
in their design, are likely to undermine the interests of politically
powerful producers of carbon-based energy. Equally, they are likely to
have a disproportionate impact on the United States relative to other,
less carbon-intensive, economies. It is understandable that a
conservative member of Congress could be pledged to uphold the interests
of energy-industry workers or shareholders from his or her home
constituency. It is also understandable that a U.S. negotiator at an
international conference could work to increase the benefits for the
United States of a proposed treaty while shifting the costs to other
countries. What is harder to understand is why market liberals would see
fit to support such positions, unless for the narrowest of tactical
reasons.
Even when fear of change or tactical considerations do not
introduce bias in selection and interpretation of scientific material,
it may not be wise to base the market-liberal position on global warming
too heavily on science alone. The danger is that there is then no
fall-back position if future trends in science more strongly establish
climate change as a reality. As an example of heavy reliance on
scientific material, consider the chapter on global warming from the
Cato Handbook on Policy (Michaels 2005). Without making any allegation
of bias in selection or interpretation of scientific sources, it can be
noted that the entire chapter is devoted to purely scientific issues,
with the exception of a couple of sentences at the end, which allude
briefly to estimated costs and benefits. Some points made in that
document also illustrate how fast the scientific ground can shift from
under the policy argument. For example, the argument is made that the
frequency and intensity of hurricanes in the Atlantic and Caribbean are
currently "no different than the regime that was dominant in the
1940s, 1950s, and 1960s" (p. 484). Perhaps this statement seemed
safe when it was made in early 2005, but then came along later that year
the greatest number of named storms in history, the single strongest
storm (measured by barometric pressure), the most economically
destructive storm ever, and, to top things off, the latest recorded
post-season storm, which lingered on past New Year's Day. Does one
bad season constitute proof of a causal link from climate change to
storm intensity? As a matter of science, no doubt it does not. But as a
matter of argumentation, those who want to urge inaction on global
warming might now do best not to mention hurricanes at all.
In focusing too heavily on scientific evidence, market liberals
sometimes seem to be making the unspoken concession that, if global
warming turns out to be real, then the policy proposals put forward by
the nonliberal side are the only ones possible. In that case, if
policymakers later do decide to act against climate change, market
liberals will have lost their chance to have their voices heard in
shaping the specifics of policy design. At a minimum, it would be more
prudent to take a two-track approach: "We are not yet convinced
that global warming is a reality, but if it turns out to be, here is how
it should be handled."
The danger is even greater when market liberals rely on scientific
sources that represent a minority within the climatology community.
Confronted with the charge that they are relying on minority scientific
views, market liberals sometimes reply that science is not a democratic
process that establishes the validity of propositions by head-count.
They go on to point out that all dominant scientific theories were once
minority opinions. This is a weak argument. All mature oak trees were
once acorns, but of all the acorns that fall to the forest Floor, only a
tiny percentage become oaks. Likewise, the chance that any one
contrarian in the scientific community will be vindicated is small.
At the risk of digressing from the main theme of this article, it
is perhaps worth adding that the perceived validity of one or another
hypothesis may not always depend on purely scientific factors alone. In
their choice of research fields, and sometimes even in their
conclusions, scientists may be influenced by considerations of funding.
Funding for science, in turn, depends on the whole range of factors
falling under the heading of public choice theory. The interaction of
self-interested behavior by allocators of government research grants
with the grant-seeking behavior of researchers could plausibly produce
systematic biases. For example, research that produces eye-catching
findings may be more likely to generate follow-up funding than that
which reports ambiguous results. To the extent this is true, public
choice considerations may bias reported research results toward the
extremes, and in some cases, asymmetrically toward one extreme rather
than the other. (1)
A detailed investigation of how public choice considerations
operate in the case of global warming would have to deal with several
issues. First, it would be necessary to penetrate beyond the widespread
feeling among scholars that if only their particular line of research
were adequately funded, their point of view would become the generally
accepted one. Complaints of this kind, often accompanied by accusations
of bias by grantors, can be found in any field of study, whether
economics, climatology, or women's studies. What is needed is some
way to sort the naively self-justifying allegations from the valid ones.
Another issue to be addressed is the relationship between political
pressures at various levels of government. In one recently publicized
case, James Hansen of NASA reported political pressures to suppress his
findings confirming climate change. On the other hand, some observers
believe that at the operational level, where specific funding requests
are considered, there is a bias in favor of projects that tend to
confirm global warming. For example, Margaret Kris (2005) cites Jeff
Kueter, president of the George C. Marshall Institute, as arguing that
"White House policy is not filtering down to career
bureaucrats" when it comes to funding of global warming research.
It appears likely that there are conflicting biases at different levels
of the government bureaucracy.
Finally, a thorough study of the issue of biases in research
funding would have to take into account private as well as public
sources of funding. Private funding can sometimes be available on a
surprisingly generous scale for minority science. For example, Randall
Mills and his company Blacklight Power have attracted some $50 million
in private funding for research into hydrogen energy that is based on
theories that lie far outside the mainstream of contemporary physics.
(2) Private funding serves as a healthy factor protecting minority
science from establishment bias but, in other cases, it is alleged to be
a source of bias itself. For example, organizations opposing genetically
modified crops complain that their views are swamped by masses of
supposedly biased research funded by agribusinesses. In the field of
climate science, there are reports of bias both for and against the
global warming hypothesis with regard to funding from private
foundations and energy-industry sources (Kris 2005).
Fascinating as these issues are, they are tangential to the theme
of this article. For present purposes, it will be enough to treat public
choice considerations as an additional source of uncertainty that must
be faced by policymakers, who must worry not only about complex
scientific arguments, but also about whether the researchers involved
are being objective. We will return to the consequences of uncertainty
in a later section of this article.
Climate Change and Property Rights: A Lockean Perspective
If the market liberal position on global warming cannot rely on
science alone, what should it be built on? The answer, to take the lead
of market-liberal thinking as applied to other environmental issues, is
a theory of property rights. (3) Following our plan to go back to first
principles, we can begin with the writings of John Locke (1690), whose
views on property rights and just government are the very cornerstone of
classical liberalism.
Locke's thinking on property' can be summarized in terms
of three rights and three corresponding duties:
Rights: (4)
* to property in one's own person
* to property in the fruits of one's own labor
* to property in land and natural resources taken from nature when
mixed with one's own labor
Duties: (5)
* to abstain from harming others
* to abstain from taking property of others
* to leave enough and as good for others when taking from the
common
The rights and duties are inseparable. One cannot claim the former
without binding oneself to uphold the latter. Because the three Lockean
duties are central to the issue of global warming, it will be worth
taking a moment to examine them in more detail.
The first two duties are incorporated in another body of principles
that market liberals endorse, the English common law. Without implying
that seeking legal redress is necessarily the best way to deal with
large-scale environmental harms under existing laws and court
institutions, it is helpful to use analogies with the law to draw
attention to ethical and philosophical parallels between environmental
harms and other more familiar harms.
In law, the duty not to harm others is covered by the tort of
assault, which means threatening or attempting to inflict offensive
physical contact, combined with an immediate ability to do so, with the
result that the victim is put in a state of apprehension. If the threat
is carried out, battery is committed. Following common practice, when no
confusion arises, we will use the term assault as shorthand for assault
and battery, the combined making and acting on a threat.
The duty not to harm others in their property is covered by the
common law tort of trespass. According to one standard legal source, the
tort of trespass to land occurs "'any time a person, without
permission, enters onto land that is owned by another, or causes
anything or anyone to enter onto the land or remains on the land, or
permits anything to remain on it" (Jentz et al. 1993: 99). Actual
harm is not an essential element of this tort. Trespass to personal
property occurs "whenever any individual unlawfully harms the
personal property of another or otherwise interferes with the personal
property owner's right to exclusive possession and enjoyment of
that property." Assault and trespass were well established in
common law at the time Locke was writing. More recently, both have
become codified as part of criminal law.
Certain defenses are allowed against a charge of assault or
trespass. Consent of the victim is one. Also, if no causal relationship
can be shown between the action of the defendant and the offense to the
victim, the tort is not proved. However, certain attempted defenses are
not recognized as legally valid:
* A showing that others have committed the same offense against the
same victim without being held to account, so that the actions of the
present defendant are responsible for only a small part of the aggregate
harm to the victim.
* A showing that the defendant gained benefits from the tort, the
value of which exceeds the costs to the victim.
* A showing that the defendant has committed the same tort in the
past without being held to account.
The relevance of these defenses to the case of global warming will
be discussed in the next section.
Locke's third duty, to leave enough and as good for others
when taking from the common, can be called the duty not to engross.
Engrossment, as Locke uses the term, means unjustly acquiring most or
all of something at the expense of other holders of common rights. Locke
understands that without a restriction on engrossment, the process of
taking from the common could lead to unacceptable results. In one of his
clearest statements, he qualifies his principles for taking as follows:
It will perhaps be objected to this, that if gathering the acorns,
or other fruits of the earth, &c. makes a right to them, then any
one may ingross as much as he will. To which I answer, Not so. The
stone law of nature, that does by this means give us property, does
also bound that property too.... As much as any one can make use
of to any advantage of life before it spoils, so much he may by his
labour fix a property in: whatever is beyond this, is more than his
share, and belongs to others [Locke 1690: chap. 5, sec. 31].
Engrossment of land, as opposed to nuts or game, would occur if a
person claimed more land than he or she could "improve, cultivate,
or use the product of" (Locke 1690: chap. 5, sec. 32).
The duty not to engross has important implications for the process
of enclosing land or other resources from the commons--implications that
seem not always to be clearly understood by market liberals who
enthusiastically cite Locke as a basis for a theory of property. One
implication is obvious: The whole or a disproportionate part of the land
cannot be enclosed, or privatized, by the first individual who happens
to come along. Think of a Walter Raleigh standing on the Atlantic coast
of North America and claiming a swath of property that extends westward
all the way to the Pacific. Less obviously, it means that the
"mixing of labor" principle can never be used to enclose the
entirety of any commons even if each person who comes along takes only
that modest amount that he or she can use personally. Instead, at some
point a scarcity constraint is reached beyond which enclosing even one
more small parcel fails to leave "enough and as good for
others." Beyond that point further enclosure may occur but, if so,
it must proceed using some different mechanism that requires the consent
of all who hold rights in common to the unenclosed remainder.
In this regard, Locke contrasts the situation of a country like the
America of his day, where land existed in abundance, with that of
England, where the scarcity constraint had already been reached. In the
latter case, he writes,
No one can inclose or appropriate any part, without the consent of
all his fellow commoners; because this is left common by compact,
i.e. by the law of the land, which is not to be violated.
... Besides, the remainder, after such enclosure, would not be as
good to the rest of the commoners, as the whole was when they could
all make use of the whole; whereas in the beginning and first
peopling of the great common of the world, it was quite otherwise
[Locke 1690: chap. 5, sec. 35].
It is not that Locke thinks the remaining land is better used when
held in common than when held privately. Quite the contrary, just a few
paragraphs later, he asserts that one acre of enclosed land is as
productive as 10 or more acres held in common. Still, if the remaining
commons is to be privatized, this must happen by the consent of all the
tenants in common. To use modern terminology, they must be bought out,
not simply expropriated. If the value of the land really increases
through enclosure, a buyout should be feasible. But until the actual
consent of the tenants in common is secured, justice trumps efficiency.
We must either find efficient rules for managing the land that is still
held in common, or we must, for the sake of justice, be resigned to live
with the possible inconveniences and inefficiencies of common property.
Applying the Lockean Framework
In this section we consider the implications of the Lockean
approach for global warming policy. In doing so, we will, for the
moment, set scientific uncertainties to one side. We will take it as a
certainty that a harmful amount of global warming is taking place and
that this warming is caused by human emissions of greenhouse gasses. In
the next section we will consider how our conclusions should be modified
to allow for the fact that both the alleged harms from global warming
and the causal pathways are not, in fact, understood with certainty.
We can start by looking at cases in which warming has an impact on
private property rights that have been clearly established. For the sake
of discussion, let us cast in the role of victim a Bangladeshi farmer
whose private land is threatened by inundation from a few centimeters
further rise in the level of the oceans, and may already be subject to
more frequent flooding from the small rise in ocean levels that has
already taken place. In the role of defendant, we will cast a coal-fired
power plant in the American Midwest. What defenses does the power plant
have against a complaint of trespass by the farmer?
One attempted defense might be that the power plant in question
contributes only a tiny part of present greenhouse gas emissions.
Furthermore, it could be argued that the measured rise in the ocean is
the product not just of today's emissions but is, in part, the
cumulative result of emissions back to the start of the industrial age,
the effects of which have themselves been aggravated by coming on top of
a natural warming cycle.
As a matter of justice, this defense would fail. We have already
seen that it is no defense against the torts of assault or trespass to
argue that others participated in the offense. Suppose I am beaten by a
gang of youths, but only one of the gang is apprehended. Would we let
him off on the grounds that he caused only part of the harm, or on the
grounds that his accomplices got away scot-free? Would we allow the
defense to introduce evidence that I had been beaten by other gangs in
the past? We certainly would not, and the same principles should apply
to our power plant.
A second attempted defense might be that any harm to the farmer was
unintentional on the part of the power plant. Its owners may have known
nothing about climatology or the low-lying geography of Bangladesh.
However, this defense of "sorry--I didn't realize it would
hurt" would also fail in a court of law. If the underlying act is
intentional--in this case, generating power and releasing greenhouse
gasses into the air--intent to accomplish the ultimate harm is
irrelevant. In law, one is assumed to intend the consequences of
one's actions. For example, a drunk driver cannot plead that he did
not intend to run into a pedestrian. The court would hold that the act
of drinking was intentional, and that impaired driving is a foreseeable
consequence of drinking (Jentz et al. 1993: 92).
A third defense might be to invoke costs and benefits. The power
plant might plausibly argue that the cost of mitigating the damage, say
by substituting nuclear or solar energy for coal, would exceed the cost
of the damage, or the cost of adapting to the damage by building a sea
wall or purchasing alternative land on higher ground. If correct, do
such calculations constitute a valid defense against environmental
assault or trespass?
The question is an important one, since the cost-benefit argument
is very often invoked in the case of global warming. Typically,
cost-benefit studies find that there would be some benefits from slowing
global warming, but often they find that the costs are greater than the
benefits. For example, a widely cited analysis of the Kyoto Protocol by
Nordhaus and Boyer (1999) estimates discounted costs of implementation
at about $800 billion to $1.5 trillion, compared with discounted
benefits of about $120 billion.
There are formidable methodological difficulties involved in any
cost-benefit study of such a large-scale phenomenon as climate change.
One problem that is especially important, given the long periods of time
involved in global warming, is the choice of an appropriate discount
rate. The present value of costs or benefits realized a century or more
in the future will either loom large or become vanishingly small
depending on the discount rate one chooses. (6) Another important issue
is where to draw the line in counting costs and benefits. Should
calculations include only direct, or also indirect costs and benefits?
As an example of indirect benefits, University of Virginia climatologist Patrick Michaels (2004) calculates that "fossil-fuel powered
societies of the 20th century saw a virtual doubling in life expectancy,
largely as a result of the technological and scientific development.
Because of the number of people affected, this is equivalent to saving
about a billion lives." As another example, New York Times
columnist Thomas Friedman has emphasized in a series of columns that
proper accounting of the costs of fossil fuel consumption should include
not just pollution and climate change, but also geopolitical costs
arising from the way that high energy consumption enriches hostile
regimes elsewhere in the world.
These methodological issues, however, are not germane to this
article. What is important for our purposes is only that human
activities leading to climate change produce some adverse effects,
regardless of how large they are or whether or not they are outweighed
by benefits. We will therefore set all questions of cost-benefit
measurement to one side by stipulating that the costs of mitigating
global warming would exceed the benefits of doing so. How should such a
finding affect the market-liberal position on global warming policy?
To begin, we should note that a cost-benefit defense is not valid
against intentional torts like assault or trespass. In the case of
trespass, the common law does not require any demonstration of harm at
all. Unless property owners consent to intrusions, they have (with a few
narrow exceptions) an absolute right to exclude them. Even in the case
of assault, it is not necessary to prove physical harm. Contact that is
merely unwanted or unpleasant can also constitute assault. Nor, in the
cases of trespass or assault, are defendants allowed to introduce
evidence as to their own gains. If I trespass on your property and cut
down a tree that blocks my view, I cannot defend myself on the grounds
that the increase in the value of my property is greater than the
reduction in the value of yours. Similarly, in our earlier example, the
gang member who beat me would not be allowed to plead that the thrill he
got from administering the beating was greater than the pain I suffered
as a result of it. There is no reason why a tort committed at a
distance, via greenhouse gas emissions, should be treated differently
from one committed at close range with a blunt instrument. The bottom
line is: If you intentionally harm someone, you are liable for that
harm, no matter how large the benefit you get from your action.
This does not amount to a blanket rejection of cost-benefit
analysis as a tool of decisionmaking. Suppose, for example, that a
railroad company is considering construction of a tunnel in place of a
track through a mountain pass that is sometimes blocked in winter. The
proper approach would be to compare the benefits of the tunnel (fuel
savings, scheduling improvements) against the costs of digging it, both
properly discounted at an interest rate reflecting the opportunity cost
of capital. The same approach would be appropriate for a government
considering a tunnel on a public highway. But even if the benefits
outweigh the costs, liberal principles would require the builder of the
tunnel, whether private or public, not just to calculate the costs but
actually to pay them. For example, the tunnel will require some land for
the entrance, the approaches, and for dumping waste rock. A favorable
cost-benefit calculation would not justify digging the tunnel on land
not owned by the builder, or dumping waste on someone else's land
without their permission. But that is exactly what is advocated when it
is argued that no action should be taken against global warming, because
the costs of reducing greenhouse gas emissions exceed the gains (the
reduction in harm to victims) of doing so.
A comparison can be made with the liberal attitude toward the
state's power of eminent domain. Market liberals have long been
wary of this power. Although eminent domain is allowed by the U.S.
Constitution, market liberals have traditionally argued that it should
be used only in rare circumstances, as a last resort, when problems of
strategic bargaining, holdouts, or transaction costs might otherwise
bring some essential activity to a standstill. Recent attempts to use
eminent domain to condemn land for ordinary commercial projects like
shopping centers have been almost universally criticized by market
liberals. Yet even eminent domain requires that the owners of the
condemned property be compensated. Proposals to inundate low-lying
coastal property in order to keep Midwestern electric rates low are not
usually accompanied by even the fig leaf of a promise to compensate
those who are harmed.
Much the same can be said of the argument that adapting to climate
change is less expensive than mitigating it. Yes, a case can be made
that adaptation is sometimes more cost-effective than mitigation, and a
global strategy should of course take both into account. Convincing data
to this effect are provided by Indur Golkany (2005). However, to
establish that adaptation is more effective than mitigation is only the
beginning of the argument for permitting continued greenhouse gas
emissions, not its conclusion. A market-liberal position, based on
Lockean property rights concepts, would insist not just on a
demonstration that adaptation is theoretically superior, but on the
actual undertaking of adaptation measures, at the expense of the
interests that stand to benefit from continued emissions. Not just that,
the true liberal position would insist that actual consent of the harmed
parties be secured, rather than allowing the adaptation versus
mitigation decision be made elsewhere and imposed on the victims.
Up to this point, the analysis has been artificially simplified by
casting the global warming scenario as a clash of clear-cut private
property interests, the Midwestern power plant versus the Bangladeshi
farmer. This approach has made the problem into something like the
example used by Coase (1960) of the farmer versus the railroad, expanded
to a global scale. A more complete discussion needs to take into account
the role of unenclosed commons as well as private property.
In the case of global warming, the relevant unenclosed commons
include the world air-shed, which, in one of its several competing uses,
serves as a sink for greenhouse gasses, and the oceans, which serve as a
sink for heat generated by the greenhouse effect and a catchment basin
for melting ice. (We are still stipulating scientific certainty of these
effects.) Whatever adverse impact the Midwestern power plant has on the
Bangladeshi farmer are transmitted through the effects of greenhouse gas
emissions on these common-property resources. What does a Lockean
approach tell us about rights to make use of the global atmospheric and
oceanic commons, and about how those rights might be established?
One result of adding common property to the mix is to give our
hypothetical power plant a possible new line of defense, namely, the
first-use principle. As a simple example of this principle, suppose I
build a drag strip in a rural area and operate it for several years
without drawing objections from the neighboring farmers. Later, someone
buys part of an adjacent wheat field and builds a housing development.
According to the first-use principle, the buyers of the houses have no
right to complain about the noise of the drag strip. I was there first,
and the noise was priced in when the sale of the houses was negotiated.
The situation would be different if I built my drag strip in the middle
of an established residential area. Then, the first-use principle would
cut in the favor of homeowners, and I would either have to pay
compensation, shut down, or limit my races to silent electric cars.
Reduced to simple terms, the first-use principle is nothing more than
the Lockean doctrine that the acorns in the forest belong to the first
person to pick them up.
In the global warming case, our Midwestern power plant could argue
that it has established ownership rights to the sink-value of the
air-shed by emitting greenhouse gasses into it for many years without
anyone's objection. No one has the right to come along now and
change the roles of the game. If the emissions are to be stopped, it is
the power plant that must be compensated for any abatement costs.
The problem is that the first-use principle ceases to be decisive
when it runs up against a scarcity constraint, that is, against the
Lockean duty not to engross. In the case of greenhouse gasses, it can be
argued that energy users have the right to "enclose" air-shed
rights under the first-use principle only so long as enough and as good
is left for others. Suppose we reach a point beyond which further
appropriation of air-shed rights encroaches on the interests of others
who have common-property rights to the world's atmosphere and
oceans. From that point on, following Lockean principles, further
enclosure cannot proceed by unilateral taking. Instead, if emissions are
to be increased at all (or even to continue, if the limit has already
been crossed), they can only do so with the consent of all of the
tenants in common, including our Bangladeshi farmer and anyone else
similarly harmed. If the polluters want to gain that consent, they
should bargain for it by offering buyouts, side-payments, or financing
of adaptation costs.
To be more specific, we could turn from the general issue of
climate change to the debate over the Kyoto Protocol. With regard to
this agreement, it is often objected that the United States would bear a
disproportionate share of compliance costs since its emissions of
greenhouse gasses are, at present, farther above the 1990 reference
level than those of other industrial nations. Viewed in Lockean terms,
this amounts to arguing that the United States should be let off the
hook exactly because it has, in the past, been the most extreme
engrosser of the world's common property. (7) This is a profoundly
illiberal position to take. Defending the rights of property that has
been unjustly acquired is a conservative position, not a liberal one. It
reminds one of arguments made in defense of property in slaves, at the
dawn of the American republic, by writers who, in other respects, were
staunch disciples of Locke.
The Significance of Scientific Uncertainty
In the previous section, for the sake of discussion, we treated it
as a scientific certainty that harmful global warming is taking place
and is caused by human activities. In this section, we relax that
assumption to allow for scientific uncertainty. The question to be
addressed is, can an action that is proscribed when it is certain to do
harm become permissible if the harm is less than certain?
To be sure, some people on the market-liberal side of the debate
have denied that there is any scientific uncertainty. Statements to the
effect that "there is no credible evidence supporting the theory of
global warming" continue to appear from time to time (see, for
example, Holcberg 2001). Most serious writers on the subject are more
cautious, however. They allow that there is some credible evidence on
both sides of the scientific debate.
Consider, for example, Britain's recent report on "The
Economies of Climate Change" (House of Lords 2005). That report is
cited approvingly by many market-liberal and conservative writers as a
counterweight to the report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate
Change (IPCC 2001), a favorite of environmentalists. After hearing from
many witnesses, the authors of the House of Lords report agree that
"forecasters do seem to indulge periodically in 'end of the
world' stories." On balance, though, they conclude, "We
do not believe that today's scientists are 'crying wolf: They
may turn out to have been wrong in some respects, but the arguments on
which they base their case are better researched than in earlier
cases" (House of Lords 2005: 20). Even the IPCC report, if it is
read closely and not just mined for the most sensational passages,
includes a wide range of projections and lists many "key
uncertainties" in the literature on climate change.
Furthermore, as mentioned previously, we should also take into
account possible nonscientific sources of uncertainty. In addition to
limitations of data or theories that are available for interpreting the
data, it is possible that reported scientific findings are subject to
biases motivated by political, ideological, or grant-seeking
considerations. This problem makes it even more difficult to be sure
that the whole truth about climate change lies on one side or the other
of the debate.
What difference do the uncertainties make? One way to answer that
question is to see how we deal with uncertainties in other contexts.
In daily life, we sometimes deal with uncertainty simply by
ignoring the worst and hoping for the best. Suppose, for example, a male
executive, during a meeting with an attractive female associate, is
tempted to take a hands-on approach to management. He knows well enough
that any intentional, unwanted touching will constitute the tort of
assault. However, he is uncertain, at least in his own mind, whether his
touch will be unwanted. To his way of thinking, some women like that
kind of thing. If he takes his chances and makes a grab, should he be
allowed, if rebuffed, to make the defense that he was not certain that
his act would be ill-received? No, he should not. Our executive, and the
rest of us too, know that we should avoid intentional acts that have a
reasonable probability of causing harm, even if they are not certain to
do so. Intentionally taking an action that has a substantial probability
of environmental harm is no different.
This does not mean that we must, like members of a certain
religious sect, go around wearing masks to avoid inhaling some
endangered species of gnat. Sometimes the evidence pointing to possible
harm is so tenuous as to approach zero. For example, some people believe
that radiation from electric transmission lines causes cancer. However,
despite repeated investigation, the scientific evidence supporting the
transmission line-cancer link is vanishingly slim. We need not be
deterred from building transmission lines. But the evidence of a linkage
from greenhouse gasses to global warming is several orders of magnitude
stronger, even if it falls short of perfect certainty. It is strong
enough to nullify the "I wasn't sure" defense attempted
by our chauvinist executive.
At the opposite pole from hoping for the best and ignoring the
worst lies the minimax strategy for dealing with uncertainty. This
approach focuses on minimizing the chance of a maximum loss. An example
from public policy would be the defense system the U.S. government is
building to protect against a nuclear missile attack from North Korea.
Although the probability of such an attack is small and the efficacy of
the defense system is uncertain, a successful strike by even a single
nuclear missile would be so catastrophic that it justifies the expense,
at least in the opinion of some people who appear otherwise rational.
The fact that more lives could be saved, in terms of mathematical
expectations, by spending the same hundreds of millions of dollars on,
say, diabetes clinics, is, for them, beside the point. To take another
example, this time from the private sector, we know that some people, in
planning for retirement, invest in a portfolio of stocks, while others
buy certificates of deposit or insured annuities. The latter sacrifice
the higher expected rate of return of the stock portfolio to protect
themselves against the small possibility that a large-scale market crash
could have a catastrophic effect on their standard of living.
A minimax strategy is most likely to make sense when the
mathematical expectation of loss is hard to calculate and the feared
loss is of a nature that would make a qualitative, not just a
quantitative, impact on individual welfare. Some of the risks of global
warming may fall into this category, for example, the possible
disruption of Atlantic currents that keep Europe warm in the winter. The
consensus among scientists seems to be that the probability of such an
event is small, at least for the near future. However, it could fit the
minimax pattern if, as some oceanographers think, the current might,
under some future conditions, stop abruptly with a catastrophic impact
on the European climate.
When it comes right down to it, the merits of a minimax strategy
depend less on science than on subjective risk preference. There is no
objective way to prove that a minimax strategy is the best in a given
situation, but equally, no reason to exclude this approach from the
discussion of public policy. This should be especially true for market
liberals, who, in other contexts, are quite comfortable with taking
people's subjective risk preferences as they find them. In
discussing financial markets, people with greater than average risk
aversion are characterized as "prudent," and markets are
lauded for their ability to accommodate their preferences. Why is it,
then, that when climate policy is being discussed, people with greater
than average risk aversion are dismissed as "alarmists" who do
not even deserve a seat at the table?
A third approach to decisionmaking with uncertainty, the
"reasonable care" standard, lies between a strategy of hoping
for the best while ignoring the worst and the strong risk aversion of a
minimax strategy. According to the reasonable care standard, when there
is risk that some activity may cause harm, one should take all
cost-effective precautions. Cost-effective, in this case, means those
precautions which, at the margin, have a cost that is less than the
resulting reduction in the expected value of harm.
One application of this standard is to the law of negligence.
Suppose I own a trucking company, and you are injured when the brakes on
one of my trucks fail, causing it to collide with your car. In a suit
for negligence, one issue that could arise is whether I took reasonable
precautions to avoid brake failure. Did I buy quality parts from a
reputable manufacturer? Did my mechanics make regular brake inspections?
If it turns out that I tried to save a few dollars by using substandard
parts and skipping inspections, I could be judged negligent and required
to pay damages. If I did take reasonable care, I would be judged not
negligent and the loss falls on you, the victim.
Applied to the issue of global warming, the reasonable care
standard suggests that we should take measures to reduce greenhouse gas
emissions up to the point where the marginal costs of doing so begin to
exceed the expected value of the marginal gains. This is an improvement
over the head-in-the-sand idea that we should do nothing at all until we
are fully certain about every detail of climate science. Still, applying
the reasonable care standard to the case of global warming is open to an
important qualification.
In tort law, the reasonable care standard is most widely accepted
in reference to negligence, an unintentional tort. However, as discussed
in the previous section, emissions of greenhouse gas are better viewed
as intentional torts, akin to assault or trespass. When we build a
coal-fired power plant, we intend all of the foreseeable results, not
just generation of energy but also emissions of carbon dioxide. We just
don't know how much damage the emissions will do. Rather than the
analogy of brake failure, to which the reasonable care standard applies,
the carbon emissions are more like drunken driving. As explained
earlier, both the drinking and driving are intentional acts. We are not
excused from the consequences of drunken driving just because we
don't know exactly what we will hit in our drunken state--a tree, a
car, or a school bus. Despite the uncertainty, we are liable for any
harm we cause, and we are required to pay damages.
This reasoning does not absolutely mean that the power plant should
not be built. It could be correct that the cost savings from using coal
rather than solar energy outweigh the expected value of damage done from
the incremental global warming, and even true that there is a nonzero possibility of zero damage. Still, that does not excuse owners of the
plant from liability for harm. If harm can later be demonstrated,
restitution must be made through payment of appropriate damages or
investment in adaptation projects.
To put it another way, the presence of uncertainty cannot mend the
flaws in the cost-benefit argument that were discussed in the previous
section. Remember, the most widely cited cost-benefit studies do not
claim that the harm done by global warming is zero, only that the
benefit of doing anything about it is exceeded by the costs of
mitigation. Earlier we saw that such calculations, when both costs and
benefits are known with certainty, does not create a right to take other
people's property without payment. By the same token, the
reasonable care standard, which is the application of cost-benefit
principles under uncertainty, does not offer an escape from contingent
liability if intended actions turn out, after the fact, to cause harm
that was not certain to occur when the actions were taken.
Unfortunately, an acknowledgment of contingent liability is too often
missing from market-liberal writings on the subject of global warming.
Instead, estimates of the expected value of costs and benefits are
treated as dispositive, with the implication that emission sources
should be held harmless even if the climatological optimists on whose
research the estimates were based turn out to be wrong. This does not,
to me, seem a sound position for a market liberal to take. It sounds
more like a conservative defense of arbitrary privilege, similar to
claims of sovereign immunity made by kings and presidents.
Conclusion
What, then, is the bottom line? What is the proper market-liberal
position on global warming? If that position is to be constructed on a
sound Lockean respect for the persons and property of others, some of
its outlines are clear, even if many details remain to be filled in.
First, market liberals should keep arguments based on comparisons
of costs and benefits in proper perspective. The fact that an action
produces net benefits, even very large net benefits, does not shield the
actor from liability if it also does harm. The relative magnitude of the
costs and benefits, or their relative probabilities, is, in this regard,
irrelevant. The duty not to harm people in their persons or property is
not to be bypassed on the basis of any facile cost-benefit calculus.
This is an essential part of what distinguishes the classical liberal
tradition from other political theories that would invoke the power of
the state to override individual rights in favor of some greater
societal utility. This being said, cost-benefit calculations may in some
other respects be relevant to the formulation of a market-liberal
position on global warming. They may help choose between different
mechanisms for implementing climate change policy. They may be relevant
to the decision of whether to abstain from possibly harmful actions, or
to risk possible harm while accepting a contingent duty of restitution.
And they may be relevant to whether harm is better avoided by mitigation
of climate change, or instead compensated through investments that help
victims of climate change to adapt.
Second, the market-liberal position should be distinct from a
conservative position that defends unjustly acquired privileges.
Liberalism in America, in particular, grew up in a Lockean state of
nature where it was really true, or at least seemed true, that
homesteaders, loggers, grazers, and industrialists could take what they
needed while leaving "enough and as good for others." What the
environmentalist side of the global warming debate is telling us is that
we no longer live in such a world. It is not just that we can take no
more from the commons; we have quite possibly already taken so much as
to have breached our duty not to engross. To be sure, the science of
just how much can safely be taken is not yet perfect. We may be way past
the limit already or still a bit short of it. But to cry foul because
those who have taken the most are now asked to bear a substantial share
of the costs is not liberalism.
Third, market liberals should keep a clear head when it comes to
the relationship between science and public policy. It is fine to be
legitimately cautious when policies are urged on the basis of weakly
established scientific fads. One should be vigilant against attempts to
smuggle questionable economic or political assumptions into scientific
analysis, as is sometimes done in the global warming debate, and also to
possible biases in research produced by grant-seeking and public choice
considerations. But at the same time, as Hayek warned, any reluctance to
accept new scientific theories must itself be rational and must be kept
separate from the regret that the new theories may upset cherished
beliefs (let alone that they threaten the financial interests of useful
allies). This is a fine line to walk, and I fear that the market-liberal
camp may at times have overstepped it.
Fourth, market liberals should think about the implications of
their principles not just for public policy, but for their personal
conduct. It is fashionable in some conservative circles to ridicule
environmentalism as a new religion that calls for a personal morality of
abstinence (see, for example, Schlesinger 2005). Perhaps market liberals
would not want to describe their beliefs as a religion, but all of the
great thinkers to whom they pay homage make it clear that the duty not
to harm others in their persons or property is not just an abstract
guideline for public policy, but a specific imperative of personal
morality. To cede the moral high ground on environmental issues to the
left is not just tactically foolish, it is unprincipled. To put it
simply, a market liberal should not be ashamed to drive a Prius rather
than a Humvee.
These broad outlines of a market-liberal position on global warming
leave a great deal of room for debate and discussion. They leave open
the whole area of how to design a policy to deal with global warming.
Are the flaws of the Kyoto Protocol so serious that it is worse than
doing nothing at all? Perhaps so--even its staunchest supporters
acknowledge that it has many limitations. Should we act now, based on
current scientific knowledge? Or should we wait, while firmly insisting
on the principle of contingent liability, being prepared to make
restitution should subsequent harm turn out to be greater than optimists
think it will be? In formulating global warming policy, should each
country act unilaterally, based on a duty to avoid harm regardless of
what others do, or is it best to try to negotiate international
agreements? If measures are to be taken, what role should be given to
market-based mechanisms like tradable permits? How can such market-like
devices, if used, be introduced in a way that respects existing property
rights? How do such devices relate to Lockean principles regarding
enclosure and management of residual unenclosed commons?
By addressing these and other questions, market liberals can make a
uniquely valuable contribution to the global warming debate. If,
however, they allow themselves to be perceived as ostriches whose only
policy in the face of uncertainty is to hope for the best while ignoring
the worst, and base their position on climate policy on arguments that
they would disdain in any other context, they will end up making no
useful contribution at all.
References
Cline, W. R. (2004) "Meeting the Challenge of Global
Warming." Copenhagen Consensus Program of the National
Environmental Assessment Institute
(www.cgdev.org/doe/expert%20pages/cline/C1Chan300404.pdf).
Coase, R. (1960) "The Problem of Social Cost." Journal of
Law and Economics 3: 1-44.
Cordato, B. (2004) "Toward an Austrian Theory of Environmental
Economics." Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 7 (1): 13-16.
Davis, R. E. (2000) "Links between Deaths and Climate
Weakening Over Time." Environmental News (1 February,). Chicago:
Heartland Institute.
Golkany, I. (2005) "Living with Global Warming." National
Center for Policy Analysis, Policy Report, no. 278.
Hayek, F. A. (1960) "Why I Am Not a Conservative."
Postscript to The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Holcberg, D. (2001) "Global Warming vs. Prosperity."
Capitalism Magazine (21 March) www.capmag.com/article.asp?ID=418).
House of Lords (2005) "The Economies of Climate Change."
Select Committee on Economic Affairs, Second Report of Session 2005-06.
London.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, IPCC (2001) Climate
Change 2001: Synthesis Report (www.ipcc.ch/pub/un/syreng/spm.pdf).
Jentz, G. A. et al. (1993) West's Business Law, 5th ed. St.
Paul, Minn.: West Publishing.
Kris, M. (2005) "Lobbying and Law--Cold Cash and
Global-Warming Research." National Journal (2 April)
(www.marshall.org/article.php?id=284).
Locke, J. (1690) Second Treatise of Government
(www.constitution.org/jl/2ndtreat.htm).
Mathews, R. (2006) "The Atom Bombshell that is Splitting
Opinion." Financial Times (10 March): 7.
Michaels, P. J. (2004) Private communication.--(2005) "Global
Warming and Climate Change.'" In Cato Handbook on Policy, 6th
ed., 479-89. Washington: Cato Institute.
(www.cato.org/pubs/handbook/hb109/hb_109-48.pdf.)
Nordhaus, W. D., and Boyer, J. G. (1999) "Requiem for
Kyoto" (www.econ.yale.edu/~nordhaus/hoinepage/Kyoto.pdf).
Savage, J. D. (1999) Funding Science in America. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schlesinger, J. (2005) "The Theology of Global Warming."
Wall Street Journal (8 August): A10.
(1) For a discussion of biases in government funding of scientific
research, see Savage (1999). Biases in corporate funding of research
have been the subject of a series of conferences held by the Center for
Science and the Public Interest.
(2) For an account of Mills's work and funding sources, see
Matthews (9006).
(3) A seminal source is Ronald Coase (1960). It is analysis of
pollution and property fights, as well as the importance of transaction
costs in understanding the relationship between the two, is now widely
accepted by market liberals. The same cannot be said of some of the
policy conclusions that Coase, and others since, draw from the analysis
in the 1960 article. For a critique of Coase from a property-rights
viewpoint, see Cordato ('2004).
(4) "Though the earth, and all inferior creatures, be common
to all men, vet every man has a property' in his own person: this
no body has any right to but himself. The labour of his body, and the
work of his hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he
removes out of the state that nature hath provided, and left it in, he
hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own,
and thereby makes it his property. It being by him removed from the
common state nature hath placed it in, it hath by this labour something
annexed to it, that excludes the common right of other men: for this
labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer, no man but he
can have a right to what that is once joined to, at least where there is
enough, and as good, left in common for others" (Locke 1690: chap.
5, see. 27). That the principle for acquiring property applies not just
to nuts and berries, but to the land itself, is made clear in Locke
(1690: chap. 5, see. 32): "As much land as a man tills, plants,
improves, cultivates, and can use the product of, so much is his
property. He by his labour does, as it were, inclose it from the
common."
(5) With regard to the first two duties, Locke (1690: chap. 2, sec.
6) writes, "The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it,
which obliges every one: and reason, which is that law, teaches all
mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent,
no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or
possessions." The third duty' is given, among other places, in
the admonition to leave "enough, and as good, ... for others"
(chap. 5, sec. 27).
(6) Using a modest discount rate of 2.5 percent means that the
present value of $100 in costs or benefits 200 years from now is just 71
cents--equivalent to saying that costs and benefits that far in the
future are almost irrelevant for today's decisionmaking. For a
discussion of the discount rate and other methodological issues in
cost-benefit studies of global warming, see Cline (2004). He finds
larger present-value benefits of reducing greenhouse gas emissions than
do Nordhaus and Boyer.
(7) To avoid misunderstanding, the "engrossment" of
air-shed rights with which greenhouse gas emitters are here charged is
something different from the more general allegation that rich nations
use more than their fair share of the world's resources. It is a
cliche in certain circles to decry the fact that the United States, with
x percentage of the world's population, uses some much larger
percentage y of its copper, natural gas, olive oil, or whatever. A
market liberal would reply that as long as the greater consumption of
high-income countries reflects the fact that they produce more, and as
long as they acquire goods through voluntary exchange, not through
unilateral expropriation, the fact of producing and consuming large
quantities of goods and services does not in itself constitute
engrossment in the Lockean sense.
Edwin G. Dolan teaches economics at the Stockholm School of
Economics, Riga, and the University of Economics, Prague. This article
is an outgrowth of a lecture presented at the Liberal Institute in
Prague, November 21, 2005. The author thanks the Liberal Institute and
Tereza Urbanova, organizer of the lecture, for the opportunity to make
the presentation, and those who attended for their many perceptive
comments. He also thanks Kitty Dolan and an anonymous referee for
additional helpful input.