Is the Market Moral? A Dialogue on Religion, Economics, and Justice.
Bandow, Doug
Is the Market Moral? A Dialogue on Religion, Economies, and Justice
Rebecca M. Blank and William McGurn Washington, D.C.: Brookings
Institution Press, 2004, 151 pp.
Market economies have won the so-called bathtub test. Few people,
even denizens of institutions historically resistant to the wiles of
capitalism--academia and the environmental movement--still deny that
economic freedom delivers more and better goods and services.
But critics of capitalism often make a more fundamental attack:
markets are immoral. They might work, but they are unfair. In
particular, their outcomes are badly flawed, requiring intrusive
corrective action by government. This is the topic that spurred the
debate about theology and economics between Rebecca Blank, Dean of the
Gerald R. Ford School of Public Policy and professor of economics at the
University of Michigan, and William McGurn, then an editorial writer for
the Wall Street Journal--and since chosen to be President George W.
Bush's chief speechwriter. The two commentators stake out their
initial positions and follow with two rounds of responses.
Blank is a critic, but a well-informed one. As an academic
economist she suffers none of the illusions held by those on the utopian
left. In order to have a productive, prosperous society, markets are
necessary but not sufficient, she contends: "Christian theology
surely recognizes the fact that human beings can be selfish and
self-interested, but Christian faith calls us to be more than that
whenever possible" (p. 22). That's an unexceptional claim,
however. Her most important assertion is that Christians should engage
government to advance their faith by "showing other-interest"
(p. 26), as she puts it. "For Christians, government programs may
serve as an instrument to help support the values and responsibilities
taught by their faith" (p. 49).
That means making--or attempting to make--markets more efficient,
limiting their scope, and, perhaps most significantly, altering
"market outcomes by redistributing resources" (p. 43).
Although Blank's ambitions seem reasonably restrained, these
principles broadly interpreted would allow the sort of market
manipulation characteristic of mismanaged economies around the world.
McGurn develops his analysis by drawing on his experience in Hong
Kong, which became a beacon of prosperity and freedom aside a murderous
totalitarian state. He has no illusions about the problems that result
from human imperfection transmitted through markets. Nevertheless, he
emphasizes "the possibilities of markets, especially for the most
hopeless parts of the world" (p. 59).
Capitalism has its limits, he acknowledges, but "my
experience, especially in the developing world, tells me that for the
poor the real danger is almost never markets and almost always the
absence of them" (p. 59). It is an observation that has borne out
in my extensive travels abroad as well: what poor countries have in
common is the absence of economic liberty--especially open, competitive
markets.
McGurn reacts as much against typical leftist critiques of
capitalism as against Blank's analysis. The basic theological
analysis, he explains, "depends largely on whether we see freedom
as enhancing possibilities and solidarity or taking them away" (p.
62). He takes the former position, even as he allows that abuses occur.
But those flaws are rooted not in the market itself, but rather in human
nature and culture.
Although freedom gives more opportunity to sin, "the sins
themselves are by no means unique to capitalism" (p. 85). As
tempting as it is to look to government for redress, he emphasizes
reforming the culture. He concludes: "Within this structure of
markets and competition, there still remains plenty of room for
redressing injustices and taking the side of the weak against the
powerful" (p. 87).
Their sharpest disagreements emerge in the rounds of
point-counterpoint. Do markets promote virtuous behavior? McGurn says
yes. Blank disagrees, at least to some degree. She contends "that a
virtuous market goes beyond individual traits" (pp. 94-95). Which
means using government to impose broader social goals: "The
government and private structures that surround markets should reflect
the Christian mandate to care for the poor and the disadvantaged"
(p. 96).
Here McGurn and Blank clash most directly, and McGurn has by far
the better argument. He confronts Blank's claims: "Not least
of the weaknesses in so-called 'Christian' prescriptions for
economic life is the idea that the gospels are somehow a policy
platform, as though the Golden Rule can be simply legislated" (p.
105). The first point is principle: The use of coercion is "hardly
the premier Christian virtue," he observes. Blank never explains
what justifies threatening to jail those who are less generous or more
discriminating than the government decides is appropriate.
The second factor is practical, pervasive government failure. Even
the best-intentioned programs, such as foreign aid, often have had
disastrous consequences. Blank, in contrast, thinks we should be asking,
"How does the government accomplish so much, given all of the
problems that it faces?" Her curiously rosy view of government
action is the weakest link in her argument. She even points to the
postal service--an unnecessary and grossly inefficient government
monopoly--as a paragon of government success.
McGurn's concluding argument is devastating. Government
intervention is so often counterproductive even in the most tempting
circumstances, such as child labor and the minimum wage. After all, he
notes, "the real alternative" for a child laborer in the Third
World "would not be trundling off to class but scavenging through
garbage heaps or prostituting herself" (p. 131). The problem is not
just unintended consequences, but intended consequences, since
"when the government intervenes, it puts the powers of the state on
the side of one interest--which makes redress much more difficult to
effect." If getting government right were as easy as Blank seems to
think, he adds, "our problems would have been solved long ago"
(p. 134).
In sum, both intellectual combatants recognize the virtues of the
market and the importance of virtue, but they differ on how best to
constrain harmful human behavior. Despite McGurn's needless
rhetorical swipes at libertarianism, there is no inconsistency between
government limits and moral restraint.
Indeed, McGurn nicely links the practical ease for freedom to his
transcendent theological beliefs. As he concludes, "We know, from
the considered experience of the century past, that markets work better
than control, that markets require law and not simply license, in short,
that freedom works--and, if we are Christians, that it works not because
it sanctions greed but because it is more in accord with our God-created
human natures" (p. 143).
Doug Bandow
Cato Institute