Stark optimal fiscal policies and sovereign lending.
Sarte, Pierre-Daniel G.
Capital income taxes are a salient feature in the taxation schemes
of many modern countries, though countries make distinctions between
capital gains and income earned by capital. Most countries include rents
received on capital in the income calculation for each taxpayer. When
the rates are averaged over the 1965-1996 period, average capital income
tax rates can be moderately high in industrially advanced nations,
ranging from 24.1 percent in France to 54.1 percent in the United
Kingdom. When averaged across the first six years of the 1990s, average
capital income tax rates for the same countries are 25 percent and 47.7
percent, respectively. Over the same periods, the United States had
average capital income taxes of 40.1 percent (1965-1996) and 39.7
percent (1990-1996) (see Domeij and Heathcote 2004).
Following the work of Judd (1985), and Chamley (1986), much of the
literature on optimal taxation has argued that it is not efficient to
tax capital in the long run. As shown in Atkeson, Chari, and Kehoe
(1999), this policy prescription is relatively robust in the sense that
it holds whether agents are heterogenous or identical, the
economy's growth rate is endogenous or exogenous, and the economy
is open or closed. (1) At the same time, however, the notion that
long-run capital taxation is inefficient arises in settings where
optimal policies are often extreme at shorter horizons. For instance,
when the capital stock is sufficiently large and no restrictions are
placed on the capital income tax, it is optimal for the government to
raise all revenues through a single capital levy at date 0 and never
again tax either capital or labor. For that reason, Chamley (1986)
imposes a 100 percent exogenous upper bound on the capital income tax,
which Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe (1994) show can be motivated by
assuming that households have the option of holding onto their capital,
subject to depreciation, rather than renting it to firms. With an upper
bound imposed on capital income tax rates, optimal fiscal policy
continues to be surprisingly stark, with the optimal capital tax rate
set at confiscatory levels for a finite number of periods, after which
the tax takes on an intermediate value between 0 and 100 percent for one
period, and is zero, thereafter. This article points out that government
lending to households, which is seldom observed in practice, plays a
crucial role in generating extreme optimal fiscal policies. Absent a
domestic debt instrument, more moderate capital and labor tax rates
emerge as optimal, although the capital tax rate does converge to zero,
asymptotically.
Without an upper bound imposed on capital income taxes, it is easy
to see why a single capital levy at date 0 is optimal in the environment
studied by Chamley (1986). Since the capital stock is fixed at date 0,
the initial capital levy amounts to a single lump sum tax and no
distortions are ever imposed on resource allocations over time. The
economy, therefore, achieves a first-best optimum. That said, the
presence of a debt instrument plays a key role in the implementation of
a single initial capital levy. In particular, such an instrument allows
the government to front-load all taxes in the initial period (equal to
the net present discounted value of future government expenses), lend
the proceeds to the private sector, and finance government expenditures
from interest revenue on the loans. Thus, Chamley's model never
generates government debt but generates government surpluses which are
lent back to households.
Although Chamley's single initial capital levy allows for
first-best allocations to be achieved, such a taxation scheme has
evidently little to do with the kinds of policies one observes in
practice. In particular, almost all countries continue to rely on
distortional tax systems to finance their public expenditures. This
article highlights the fact that environments that limit ex ante
government lending are more apt to generate nonzero optimal distortional
taxes at all dates. In particular, we provide an analysis of
Chamley's taxation problem without a policy instrument that allows
for sovereign lending. In that case, the government cannot carry the
proceeds from a large initial tax to future periods, and the single
capital levy prescribed in Chamley (1986) cannot be implemented. (2)
For the purposes of this article, we think of restrictions on
sovereign lending as a (rudimentary or ad hoc) way of getting rid of
extreme taxation policies in the short run. (3) More generally, gaining
a better understanding of institutional or agency constraints that
endogenously limit the kinds of contracts the government can write with
households seems central in generating optimal fiscal policies that more
closely resemble those observed in practice. It may be helpful, for
instance, to consider in greater depth the kinds of frictions that may
limit or impede government lending. At first glance, such frictions are
not necessarily obvious. In particular, any potential commitment
problems on the part of households (to repay their loans) should easily
be overcome by suitable punishment such as the garnishment of wages.
There have also been times in U.S. history, (such as during World War
II), where the government directly owned privately operated capital. (4)
Formally, the taxation problem we study, introduced by Kydland and
Prescott (1980), discusses the time inconsistency of optimal policy.
While matters related to time inconsistency lie beyond the scope of this
article, we use the insights of Kydland and Prescott (1980), as well as
more recent work by Marcet and Marimon (1999), to present the solution
to this problem in terms of stationary linear difference equations that
can be solved using standard numerical methods. While Kydland and
Prescott (1980) show how the taxation problem they consider can be
written (and solved) as a recursive dynamic program, the article does
not ultimately present properties of the solution either in the short
run or long run.
What do optimal tax rates look like when one exogenously prohibits
sovereign lending? Numerical simulations carried out in this article
indicate that capital income tax rates are never set either at 100
percent or zero at any point during the transition to the long-run
equilibrium. Furthermore, we find that labor income is subsidized in the
first few periods. This feature of optimal fiscal policy drives up labor
supply and allows household consumption to be everywhere above its
long-run equilibrium along its transition path. Finally, we provide
straightforward proof of the optimality of zero long-run capital taxes
that does not rely on the primal approach used in Chamley (1986) and
summarized in Ljungqvist and Sargent (2000, chapter 12).
This article is organized as follows. Section 1 provides a brief
summary of findings in the literature on optimal fiscal policy in the
presence of domestic lending and borrowing. In Section 2, we describe
the economic environment under consideration. Section 3 presents the
Ramsey problem associated with the analysis of optimal fiscal policy.
Salient properties of the long-run Ramsey equilibrium are discussed in
Section 4. Section 5 gives a numerical characterization of the
transitional dynamics of optimal tax rates. Section 6 offers concluding
remarks.
1. A BRIEF DESCRIPTION OF STARK FISCAL POLICIES WITH SOVEREIGN
LENDING
This section describes the kinds of extreme optimal fiscal policies
that have been described in the optimal taxation literature. Beginning
with Chamley (1986), we have already seen in the introduction that a
single capital levy at date 0, if feasible, allows the economy to
achieve first-best allocations. The problem, of course, is that the
associated capital income tax rate might well exceed 100 percent, in
which case one might interpret the tax as not only applying to capital
income but more directly to the capital stock. Whether this policy is
feasible ultimately depends on if the initial capital stock is large
enough to finance the net present discounted value of future government
expenditures. If so, the necessary revenue is raised entirely through
the levy at date 0, and lent back to households with the proceeds from
the loans used to finance the stream of government expenditures over
time. In that sense, a need for strictly positive distortional taxes
never arises.
When capital income tax rates are restricted to be at most 100
percent, Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe (1994) show that it is optimal to
set tax rates at their upper limit for a finite number of periods, after
which the capital tax rate takes on an intermediate value and is zero,
thereafter. The intuition underlying this result relates directly to the
distortional nature of capital income tax rates. In particular, having
the capital tax rate positive in some period t > 0 distorts savings
decisions, and thus, private capital allocations, in all prior periods.
Hence, front-loading capital income taxes, by having the associated tax
rates set at their upper limit from date 0 to some finite date [bar.t]
> 0, distorts the least number of investment periods. This intuition
is only partially complete in that household preferences also play an
important role in determining the horizon over which capital income is
initially taxed. When preferences are separable in consumption and
leisure, it is not optimal to tax capital after the initial period,
although labor taxes may be positive at all dates (see Chari,
Christiano, and Kehoe 1994). Xie (1997) shows that when preferences are
logarithmic in consumption less leisure, it is optimal never to tax
labor while capital income tax rates (Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe 1994)
hit their upper bound for a finite number of periods and are zero,
thereafter.
All of the above policies have in common a radical character and a
lack of resemblance to more moderate capital tax rates in practice
(i.e., capital tax rates that are neither set at confiscatory rates nor
zero). However, a key part underlying the mechanics of these policies
relates to the fact that the government is able to build large negative
debt holdings by having the capital income tax rate hit its upper limit
over some initial period of time, date 0 to date [bar.t] > 0. In Xie
(1997), it is apparent that once these negative debt holdings are large
enough to finance the remaining net present discounted value of
government expenditures, then no distortional taxes need ever be set
again. In essence, date [bar.t] is then analogous to date 0 in Chamley
(1986).
The following sections examine the problem of optimal taxation
initially posed by Chamley (1986), but without the policy instrument
that allows the government to accumulate large negative debt holdings.
Absent this instrument, numerical simulations suggest that it is
possible to have more moderate taxes on capital and labor emerge as
optimal at every date, without any bounds necessarily imposed on either
capital or labor income tax rates. Since the restriction on sovereign
lending takes away the usefulness of building a large negative debt
position on the part of the government, setting capital tax rates at
confiscatory levels is no longer warranted. More importantly, this
observation suggests further consideration of the role of institutional
or agency constraints that prevent the government from confiscating
capital income for an extended period of time, frictions that limit
sovereign lending in practice, and how these constraints help shape
optimal fiscal policy more generally.
2. ECONOMIC ENVIRONMENT
Consider an economy populated by infinitely many households whose
preferences are given by
U = [[infinity].summation over (t=0)] [[beta].sup.t]
[[[[c.sub.t.sup.1-[sigma]] - 1]/[1 - [sigma]]] - v[[n.sub.t.sup.1 +
[1/[gamma]]]/[1 + [1/[gamma]]]]], [sigma] > 0, [gamma] > 0, (1)
where [c.sub.t] and [n.sub.t] denote household consumption and
labor effort at date t, respectively, and [beta] [member of] (0, 1) is a
subjective discount rate.
A single consumption good, [y.sub.t], is produced using the
technology
[y.sub.t] = [k.sub.t.sup.[alpha]] [n.sub.t.sup.1-a], 0 < [alpha]
< 1, (2)
where [k.sub.t] denotes the date t stock of private capital.
Capital can be accumulated over time and evolves according to
[k.sub.t+1] = [i.sub.t] + (1 - [delta])[k.sub.t], (3)
where [delta] [member of] (0, 1) denotes the depreciation rate and
[i.sub.t] represents household investment. Production can be used for
either private or government consumption, or to increase the capital
stock,
[c.sub.t] + [i.sub.t] + [g.sub.t] = [k.sub.t.sup.[alpha]]
[n.sub.t.sup.1-[alpha]] (4)
where {[g.sub.t]}[.sub.t=0.sup.[infinity]] is an exogenously given
sequence of public expenditures.
As in Chamley (1986), the government finances its purchases using
time-varying linear taxes on labor income and capital income. We denote
these tax rates by [[tau].sub.t.sup.n] and [[tau].sub.t.sup.k],
respectively. At each date, the government's budget constraint is
given by
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k][r.sub.t][k.sub.t] +
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n][w.sub.t][n.sub.t] = [g.sub.t], (5)
where [r.sub.t] and [w.sub.t] are the market rates of return to
capital and labor. The left- and right-hand sides of (5) represent
sources and uses of government revenue, respectively.
There exists a large number of homogenous small size firms that act
competitively. Taking the sequences of prices
{[r.sub.t]}[.sub.t=0.sup.[infinity]] and
{[w.sub.t]}[.sub.t=0.sup.[infinity]] as given, each firm maximizes
profits and solves
[max.[[k.sub.t], [n.sub.t]]]
[k.sub.t.sup.[alpha]][n.sub.t.sup.1-[alpha]] - [r.sub.t][k.sub.t] -
[w.sub.t][n.sub.t]. (6)
The implied first-order conditions equate prices to their
corresponding marginal products, [r.sub.t] = [alpha][k.sub.t.sup.[alpha]
- 1][n.sub.t.sup.1-[alpha]] = [alpha][[y.sub.t]/[k.sub.t]] and [w.sub.t]
= (1 - [alpha])[k.sub.t.sup.[alpha]][n.sub.t.sup.-[alpha]] = (1 -
[alpha])[[y.sub.t]/[n.sub.t]].
At each date, households decide how much to consume and save in the
form of private capital investment, as well as how much labor effort to
provide. Taking the sequences of government expenditures,
{[g.sub.t]}[.sub.t=0.sup.[infinity]], and tax rates,
{[[tau].sub.t.sup.n]}, [[tau].sub.t.sup.k]}[.sub.t=0.sup.[infinity]], as
given, these households maximize lifetime utility subject to their
budget constraint,
[max.[[c.sub.t], [n.sub.t], [k.sub.t+1]]] [[infinity].summation
over (t=0)][[beta].sup.t] [[[[c.sub.t.sup.1-[sigma]] - 1]/[1 - [sigma]]]
- v[[n.sub.t.sup.1+[1/[gamma]]]/[1 + [1/[gamma]]]]] ([P.sup.H])
subject to
[c.sub.t] + [k.sub.t+1] = (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k])[r.sub.t][k.sub.t] + (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t][n.sub.t] + (1 - [delta])[k.sub.t], (7)
[k.sub.0] > 0 given.
The first-order necessary conditions implied by problem (7) yield a
static equation describing households' optimal labor-leisure
choice,
v[n.sub.t.sup.[1/[gamma]]] = [c.sub.t.sup.-[gamma]](1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t], (8)
as well as a standard Euler equation describing optimal consumption
allocations over time,
[c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] = [beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]] [(1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] + 1 - [delta]]. (9)
The constraints (5) and (7), together with the optimality
conditions (8) and (9) and the expression for prices given above,
describe our economy's decentralized allocations over time.
3. THE RAMSEY PROBLEM
Having described the decentralized behavior of households and
firms, we now tackle the problem of choosing policy optimally. Thus,
consider a benevolent government that, at date 0, is concerned with
choosing a sequence of tax rates that maximize household welfare given
the exogenous sequence of government spending. In choosing policy, this
government takes as given the behavior of households and firms. We
further assume that, at date 0, the government can credibly commit to
any sequence of policy actions. The problem faced by this benevolent
planner is to maximize (1) subject to the constraints (5) and (7), and
households' optimality conditions (8) and (9), where prices are
given by marginal products. (5)
We can address the policy problem described at the start of this
section by solving the following Lagrangian,
[max.[[c.sub.t], [n.sub.t], [[tau].sub.t.sup.k],
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n], [k.sub.t+1]]] L = [[infinity].summation over (t=0)]
= [[beta].sup.t] [[[[c.sub.t.sup.1-[sigma]] - 1]/[1 - [sigma]]] -
v[[n.sub.t.sup.1+[1/[gamma]]]/[1 + [1/[gamma]]]]] ([P.sup.R]) +
[[infinity].summation over (t=0)] [[beta].sup.t] [[mu].sub.1t]
[[beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]] [(1 - [[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1]
+ 1 - [delta]] - [c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]]] + [[infinity].summation over
(t=0)] [[beta].sup.t] [[mu].sub.2t]
[[[tau].sub.t.sup.k][r.sub.t][k.sub.t] +
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n][w.sub.t][n.sub.t] - [g.sub.t]] +
[[infinity].summation over (t=0)] [[beta].sup.t] [[mu].sub.3t] [(1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k])[r.sub.t][k.sub.t] + (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t][n.sub.t] + (1 - [delta])[k.sub.t] -
[c.sub.t] - [k.sub.t+1]] + [[infinity].summation over (t=0)]
[[beta].sup.t] [[mu].sub.4t] [[c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t] - v[n.sub.t.sup.[1/[gamma]]]],
where the Lagrange multipliers [[mu].sub.jt], j = 1,..., 4, are all
nonnegative at the optimum.
The first-order necessary conditions associated with problem (10)
that are related to the optimal choices of [c.sub.t], [n.sub.t], and
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k] are as follows:
[c.sub.t] : [c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] -
[sigma][[mu].sub.1t-1][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]-1][(1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k])[r.sub.t] + 1 - [delta]] +
[sigma][[mu].sub.1t][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]-1] -[[mu].sub.3t] -
[sigma][[mu].sub.4t][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]-1](1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t] = 0, t > 0, (10)
with
[c.sub.0.sup.-[sigma]] -
[sigma][[mu].sub.10][c.sub.0.sup.-[gamma]-1] - [[mu].sub.30] -
[sigma][[mu].sub.40][c.sub.0.sup.-[sigma]-1](1 -
[[tau].sub.0.sup.n])[w.sub.0] = 0 at t = 0, (11)
[n.sub.t] : -v[n.sub.t.sup.[1/[gamma]]] + [[mu].sub.2t]
[[[tau].sub.t.sup.k][k.sub.t][[[partial derivative][r.sub.t]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.t]]] + [[tau].sub.t.sup.n]([w.sub.t] + [n.sub.t]
[[[partial derivative][w.sub.t]]/[[partial derivative][n.sub.t]]])] +
[[mu].sub.3t] [(1 - [[tau].sub.t.sup.k])[k.sub.t][[[partial
derivative][r.sub.t]]/[[partial derivative][n.sub.t]]] + (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])([w.sub.t] + [n.sub.t] [[[partial
derivative][w.sub.t]]/[[partial derivative][n.sub.t]]])] + [[mu].sub.4t]
[[c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] (1 - [[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[[[partial
derivative][w.sub.t]]/[[partial derivative][n.sub.t]]] -
[v/[gamma]][n.sub.t.sup.[1-[gamma]]/[gamma]]] +
[[mu].sub.1t-1][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] (1 - [[tau].sub.t.sup.k])
[[[partial derivative][r.sub.t]]/[[partial derivative][n.sub.t]]] = 0, t
> 0, (12)
with
-v[n.sub.0.sup.[1/[gamma]]] + [[mu].sub.20]
[[[tau].sub.0.sup.k][k.sub.0][[[partial derivative][r.sub.0]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.0]]] + [[tau].sub.0.sup.n]([w.sub.0] +
[n.sub.0][[[partial derivative][w.sub.0]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.0]]])] + [[mu].sub.30] [(1 -
[[tau].sub.0.sup.k])[k.sub.0][[[partial derivative][r.sub.0]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.0]]] + (1 - [[tau].sub.0.sup.n])([w.sub.0] +
[n.sub.0][[[partial derivative][w.sub.0]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.0]]])] + [[mu].sub.40] [[c.sub.0.sup.-[sigma]] (1 -
[[tau].sub.0.sup.n])[[[partial derivative][w.sub.0]]/[[partial
derivative][n.sub.0]]] - [v/[gamma]][n.sub.0.sup.[1-[gamma]]/[gamma]]] =
0, at t = 0, (13)
and
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k] : -[[mu].sub.1t-1][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] +
([[mu].sub.2t] - [[mu].sub.3t])[k.sub.t] = 0, t > 0, (14)
with
[[mu].sub.20] - [[mu].sub.30] = 0, at t = 0. (15)
The fact that the above first-order conditions differ at t = 0 and
t > 0 suggests an incentive to take advantage of initial conditions
in the first period only, with the promise never to do so in the future.
It is exactly in this sense that the optimal policy is not time
consistent. Once date 0 has passed, a planner at date t > 0 who
re-optimizes would want to start with choices for consumption, labor
effort, and capital taxes that differ from what was chosen for that date
at time 0.
It should be clear that the incentives identified by Chamley (1986)
continue to be present in our model economy. Consider that the
difference between equations (14) and (15), which governs the optimal
choice of [[tau].sub.t] at dates t = 0 and t > 0, and involves an
additional term in (14),
-[[mu].sub.1t-1][u.sub.c]([c.sub.t]) < 0. (16)
This term originates from the Euler constraint in problem (10),
[beta][u.sub.c]([c.sub.t]) [(1 - [[tau].sub.t])[r.sub.t] + 1 - [delta]]
= [u.sub.c]([c.sub.t-1]), and corresponds to the reduction in the
after-tax real return to investment made at date t - 1 which is created
by an increase in the tax rate at time t. Consequently, in committing to
a tax rate in a given period t > 0, the government takes into account
the implied substitution effect on investment decisions undertaken in
the preceding period. Of course, at date t = 0, no such distortion
exists since history commences on that date with a predetermined capital
stock, [k.sub.0]. In choosing [[tau].sub.0], therefore, the government
is free to ignore its effects on previous investment decisions that can
be thought of as "sunk"; and there exists some incentive for
the optimal sequence of tax rates to begin with a high tax in period 0
relative to all other dates.
A central insight in Kydland and Prescott (1980) is that despite
the time inconsistency problem we have just mentioned, it is actually
possible to collapse equations (10) through (15) into a set of
stationary difference equations [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0.
This requires interpreting the lagged Lagrange multiplier
[[mu].sub.1t-1] as a predetermined variable with initial condition
[[mu].sub.1t-1] = 0 at t = 0.
The remaining first-order conditions associated with problem (10)
determining the optimal choice of labor income taxes and private capital
are, respectively,
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n] : ([[mu].sub.2t] - [[mu].sub.3t])[n.sub.t] -
[[mu].sub.4t][c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] = 0, t [greater than or equal to] 0,
(17)
and
[k.sub.t+1] : [[mu].sub.1t][beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]] (1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k]) [[[partial derivative][r.sub.t+1]]/[[partial
derivative][k.sub.t+1]]] + [beta][[mu].sub.2t+1] [[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k]
([r.sub.t+1] + [k.sub.t+1] [[[partial derivative][r.sub.t+1]]/[[partial
derivative][k.sub.t+1]]]) + [[tau].sub.t+1.sup.n] [n.sub.t+1] [[[partial
derivative][w.sub.t+1]]/[[partial derivative][k.sub.t+1]]]] -
[[mu].sub.3t] + [beta][[mu].sub.3t+1] [(1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[[r.sub.t+1] + [k.sub.t+1] [[[partial
derivative][r.sub.t+1]]/[[partial derivative][k.sub.t+1]]]] + (1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.n])[n.sub.t+1][[[partial
derivative][w.sub.t+1]]/[[partial derivative][k.sub.t+1]]] + 1 -
[delta]] + [beta][[mu].sub.4t+1][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]](1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.n]) [[[partial derivative][w.sub.t+1]]/[[partial
derivative][k.sub.t+1]]] = 0, t [greater than or equal to] 0. (18)
4. THE STATIONARY RAMSEY EQUILIBRIUM
With the optimality conditions (10) through (18) in hand, we first
turn to long-run properties of optimal taxes and revisit the notion that
it is not efficient to tax capital in the long run. We do so, however,
without any reference to the primal approach that is standard in the
literature, but rely instead on the simple first-order conditions we
have just derived. To this end, we define the long-run equilibrium of
the Ramsey problem as follows:
Definition: A stationary Ramsey equilibrium is a ninetuple (c, n,
k, [[tau].sup.n], [[tau].sup.k], [[mu].sub.1], [[mu].sub.2],
[[mu].sub.3], [[mu].sub.4]) that solves the government budget constraint
(5), households' budget constraint (7), the optimality condition
for labor effort (8), and the Euler equation (9), as well as the
first-order conditions associated with problem (10), equations (10),
(12), (14), (17), and (18), all without time subscripts.
It is straightforward to show that in a stationary Ramsey
equilibrium, equations (14), (17), and (18) imply that
[[tau].sup.k][[mu].sub.2][beta]r - [[mu].sub.3][1 - [beta]((1 -
[[tau].sup.k])r + 1 - [delta])] = 0. (18)
From the Euler equation in the stationary equilibrium, it follows
that 1 - [beta][[alpha](1 - [[tau].sup.k])[y/k] + 1 - [delta]] = 0.
Hence equation (18) above reduces to
[[tau].sup.k][[mu].sub.2][beta]r = 0. (19)
Now, we have that either [[tau].sup.k] > 0 or [[tau].sup.k] = 0.
Suppose first that [[tau].sup.k] > 0. Then, it must be the case that
[[mu].sub.2] = 0. From equation (14), this would mean that
[[mu].sub.1] = -[[mu].sub.3]k[c.sup.[sigma]],
which implies that [[mu].sub.1] = [[mu].sub.3] = 0 since
[[mu].sub.1] and [[mu].sub.3] are both nonnegative. However, in that
case, all Lagrange multipliers are zero in the steady state and
[c.sup.-[sigma]] = 0 from equation (10), which cannot be a solution
because household utility would be unbounded. Hence, [[tau].sup.k] >
0 cannot be a solution, and therefore, [[tau].sup.k] = 0. As in Chamley
(1986), it is optimal not to tax capital in the long run. From the
budget constraint, this implies that the steady state tax on labor is
essentially determined by the extent of government expenditures. For
instance, if government spending was a constant fraction, [phi] of
output in the long run, we would have the optimal tax on labor income in
the long run to be simply [[tau].sup.n] = [phi]/[1 - [alpha]].
The notion that it is optimal to set capital income tax rates to
zero in the long run is independent of whether government lending takes
place. This is relatively easy to see within our framework when no upper
bound is imposed on the capital income tax rate. In that case, the
government budget constraint (5) reads as
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k][r.sub.t][k.sub.t] +
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n][w.sub.t][n.sub.t] + [b.sub.t+1] = [g.sub.t] + (1 +
[r.sub.t.sup.b])[b.sub.t], (20)
where [b.sub.t] denotes one-period government bonds that are
perfectly substitutable with capital, and [r.sub.t.sup.b] is the return
on bonds from period t - 1 to t. Government lending takes place when
[b.sub.t] < 0. Moreover, the household budget constraint becomes
[c.sub.t] + [k.sub.t+1] + [b.sub.t+1] = (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k])[r.sub.t][k.sub.t] + (1 -
[[tau].sub.t.sup.n])[w.sub.t][n.sub.t] + (1 - [delta])[k.sub.t] + (1 +
[r.sub.t.sup.b])[b.sub.t]. (21)
Substituting these modified constraints in problem (10), the
planner now also has to decide how much sovereign lending will take
place. A simple arbitrage equation (obtained from the modified household
problem) dictates that in the decentralized equilibrium, 1 +
[r.sub.t.sup.b] = (1 - [[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] + 1 - [delta].
Hence, the first-order condition associated with the optimal choice of
[b.sub.t+1] in the Ramsey problem is
([[mu].sub.2t] - [[mu].sub.3t]) - [beta][(1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] + 1 - [delta]]([[mu].sub.2t+1] -
[[mu].sub.3t+1]) = 0 [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0. (22)
It is now easy for us to show that capital income taxes are zero in
the long run. In fact, with no upper bound imposed on the capital income
rate, [[tau].sub.t.sup.k] = 0 [for all]t > 0. To see this, observe
that equations (15) and (22) imply that [[mu].sub.2t] - [[mu].sub.3t] =
0 [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0. It follows from (14) that
[[mu].sub.1t-1] = 0 [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0 and from
(17) that [[mu].sub.4t] = 0 [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0.
Substituting these results into equation (18) gives
[c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] = [beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]][[r.sub.t+1]
+ 1 - [delta]] [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0,
which is simply the household's Euler equation (9) when
[[tau].sub.t.sup.k] = 0 [for all]t > 0. When an upper bound is
imposed on the capital income tax rate, [[tau].sub.t.sup.k] [less than
or equal to] 1 [for all]t [greater than or equal to] 0, it is still the
case that [[tau].sub.t.sup.k] = 0 [for all]t > 0 when preferences are
separable in consumption and leisure, and that [lim.sub.t[right
arrow][infinity]] [[tau].sub.t.sup.k] = 0, otherwise. Proof of the
latter results is more difficult to see using our Lagrangian
formulation, but is nicely presented in Erosa and Gervais (2001).
5. TRANSITIONS TO THE STEADY STATE
Even in the absence of an instrument that allows government lending
to households, we saw in the previous section that the optimal fiscal
policy with commitment prescribes zero capital taxes in the long run. In
the short and medium run, however, capital income tax rates are not as
extreme as predicted in a model with a debt instrument. Compared to the
environment studied by Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe (1994) for instance,
where capital income tax rates are set at their upper bound up to some
date [bar.t] and are zero thereafter, capital income tax rates in our
framework approach confiscatory rates only in the initial period and
then decline monotonically over time. Labor income tax rates are also
moderate at every point along the transition.
To illustrate these points, we carry out a numerical simulation of
our economy when fiscal policy is determined optimally. The parameters
we use are standard and selected along the lines of other studies in
quantitative general equilibrium theory. A time period represents a
quarter and we assume a 6.5 percent annual real interest rate, [beta] =
0.984, and a 10 percent capital depreciation rate, [delta] = 0.025. We
set the intertemporal elasticity of substitution, 1/[sigma], to 1/2 and
the Frisch elasticity of labor supply, [gamma], to 1.25. The share of
private capital in output in the United States is approximately 33
percent so we assign a value of [alpha] = 1/3. Finally, we fix the share
of government expenditures in output at 0.20.
To compute the transitional dynamics associated with optimal
capital and labor income tax rates, we replace the optimality conditions
in Section 3 with log-linear approximations around the stationary Ramsey
equilibrium. The solution paths for the state and co-state variables are
then computed using techniques described in Blanchard and Kahn (1980) or
in King, Plosser, Rebelo (1988). The resulting system of linearized
equations possesses a continuum of solutions, but only one of these is
consistent with the transversality condition associated with the
household problem.
Figure 1 depicts transitions to the stationary Ramsey equilibrium
when the initial capital stock is set at its long-run level. In other
words, Figure 1 shows transitions to the steady state when restarting
the problem. In Panel A, we can see that capital income tax rates start
near confiscatory rates in the initial period but quickly fall within 10
quarters to a more moderate range, at less than 35 percent. (6) Thus,
the notion that capital income tax rates are optimally higher in the
initial periods remain, but these rates are within a moderate range for
the greater part of the transition. More specifically, in contrast to
Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe (1994), capital income tax rates are never
set at either 100 percent or zero at any point during the transition.
(7) Interestingly, the optimal fiscal policy suggests subsidizing labor
income in the first few periods, after which labor income taxes
monotonically rise to their steady state. Because labor income
represents 2/3 of total output in our calibrated economy, and because
government expenditures account for 20 percent of output, the labor
income tax rate approaches 30 percent asymptotically as capital income
tax rates approach zero.
The initial subsidization of labor income generates an increase in
labor input, shown in Figure 1, Panel D, along the transition to the
steady state. As a result, household consumption is everywhere above its
long-run level on its way to the steady state. Moreover, the optimal
fiscal policy is such that households are able to front-load
consumption.
6. CONCLUSION
In this article, we highlighted that environments in which ex ante
government lending is limited are more apt to generate optimal
distortional taxes at all dates that do not share the stark character of
those typically presented in the literature. Absent an instrument that
allows households to borrow from the government, the government cannot
carry the proceeds from a large initial tax to future periods, and the
single capital levy prescribed in Chamley (1986) cannot be implemented.
For an economy whose capital stock is initially below its long-run
level, we have shown that capital income tax rates are never set at
either 100 percent or zero at any point during the transition to the
long-run equilibrium. Furthermore, our analysis has highlighted that
labor income is subsidized in the first few periods. This feature of
optimal fiscal policy gave rise to increased labor supply and allowed
household consumption to be everywhere above its long-run equilibrium
along its transition path. As in Chamley (1986), however, even without a
debt instrument, our analysis continued to prescribe zero-capital income
tax rates in the long run.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
We interpret our findings to suggest that a better understanding of
institutional or agency constraints that prevent the government from
confiscating capital income for an extended period of time, as well as
commitment problems associated with household borrowing, may be central
in explaining the character of observed fiscal policies.
APPENDIX
Marcet and Marimon (1999) point out that equalities associated with
feasibility constraints can generally (and in this case) be replaced
with weak inequalities, with an appeal to nonsatiated preferences
thereby guaranteeing that the feasibility constraints rewritten as such
will also be satisfied with equality. However, an analogous argument for
the equality constraints (8) and (9) is less obvious. Because of the
equality signs in (8) and (9), the set of allocations satisfying these
equations is not convex.
Consider the Euler equation (9). Marcet and Marimon (1999) show
that it is possible to rewrite this constraint as a weak inequality in
such a way that, in the optimum of the new problem, this weak inequality
is satisfied as a strict equality. One can be sure, therefore, that the
optimum subject to the weak inequality constraint is the same as that
subject to the strict equality (9), and that one is actually solving the
problem of interest.
We now provide a brief description of the arguments presented in
Marcet and Marimon (1999) but refer the reader to the paper for the
formal proofs. The question is whether to write the inequality
associated with (9) as [less than or equal to] or [greater than or equal
to]. Consider the case [greater than or equal to] first, in which
[c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] [greater than or equal to]
[beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]] [(1 - [[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] +
1 - [delta]]. The authors show that writing the inequality constraint in
this way actually makes the first-best allocation feasible, so that the
solution would be the unconstrained optimum, which is not the same as
the Ramsey equilibrium. Hence, this option does not yield a solution
equivalent to the solution under equation (9).
Next, consider the case where the inequality constraint is written
as [less than or equal to] so that [c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] [less than or
equal to] [beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]][(1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] + 1 - [delta]]. Writing the inequality
in this way reproduces the household's first-order condition if the
household faced the constraint [k.sub.t] [less than or equal to]
[bar.k.sub.t], where [bar.k.sub.t] is an upper bound imposed on
households' capital position. In other words, the modified Euler
equation corresponds to a setting where the policy instruments available
to the planner now include the ability to set an upper limit on capital
accumulation, [bar.k.sub.t]. In that case, Marcet and Marimon (1999)
then show that the planner will actually choose allocations where the
constraint [k.sub.t] [less than or equal to] [bar.k.sub.t] does not
bind, since the equilibrium with distortional taxes is associated with
too little capital relative to the full optimum. This implies that the
government will act so that [c.sub.t.sup.-[sigma]] [less than or equal
to] [beta][c.sub.t+1.sup.-[sigma]][(1 -
[[tau].sub.t+1.sup.k])[r.sub.t+1] + 1 - [delta]] is satisfied with
equality, and the optimum is then the same as the Ramsey equilibrium.
Similar arguments can be made regarding constraint (8).
REFERENCES
Aiyagari, S. 1995. "Optimal Capital Income Taxation with
Incomplete Markets, Borrowing Constraints, and Constant
Discounting." Journal of Political Economy 103 (6): 1158-75.
Atkeson, A., V. V. Chari, and P. J. Kehoe. 1999. "Taxing
Capital Income: A Bad Idea." Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review 23 (3): 3-17.
Atkinson, A., and A. Sandmo. 1980. "Welfare Implications of
the Taxation of Savings." The Economic Journal. 90 (359): 529-49.
Blanchard, O., and C. M. Kahn. 1980. "The Solution of Linear
Difference Models under Rational Expectations." Econometrica 48
(5): 1305-12.
Chamley, C. 1986. "Optimal Taxation of Capital Income in
General Equilibrium with Infinite Lives." Econometrica 54 (3):
607-22.
Chari, V. V., L. Christiano, and P. J. Kehoe. 1994. "Optimal
Fiscal Policy in a Business Cycle Model." Journal of Political
Economy 102 (4): 617-52.
Correia, I. H. 1996. "Should Capital Income be Taxed in the
Steady State?" Journal of Public Economics 60 (1): 147-51.
Domeij, D., and J. Heathcote. 2004. "Factor Taxation with
Heterogenous Agents." International Economic Review 45 (2): 523-54.
Erosa, A., and M. Gervais. 2001. "Optimal Taxation in
Infinitely-Lived Agent and Overlapping Generations Models: A
Review." Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic Quarterly (87)
2: 23-44.
Erosa, A., and M. Gervais. 2002. "Optimal Taxation in
Life-Cycle Economies." Journal of Economic Theory 105 (2): 338-69.
Garriga, C. 1999. "Optimal Fiscal Policy in Overlapping
Generations Model." Mimeo, Universitat de Barcelona.
Jones, L. E., R. E. Manuelli, and P. Rossi. 1997. "On the
Optimal Taxation of Capital Income." Journal of Economic Theory 73
(1): 93-117.
Judd, K. L. 1985. "Redistributive Taxation in a Simple Perfect
Foresight Model." Journal of Public Economics 28: 59-83.
King, R. G., C. Plosser, and S. Rebelo. 1988. "Production,
Growth and Business Cycles: The Basic Neoclassical Model." Journal
Monetary Economics 21 (2/3): 195-232.
Kydland, F. E., and E. C. Prescott. 1980. "Dynamic Optimal
Taxation, Rational Expectations and Optimal Control." Journal of
Economic Dynamics and Control 2 (1): 79-91.
Ljungqvist, L., and T. J. Sargent. 2000. Recursive Macroeconomic Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Marcet, A., and R. Marimon. 1999. "Recursive Contracts."
Mimeo, Universitat Pompeu Fabra.
McGrattan, E., and L. Ohanian. 1999. "Does Neoclassical Theory
Account for the Effects of Big Fiscal Shocks? Evidence from World War
II." Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Research Department Staff
Report 315.
Xie, D. 1997. "On Time Inconsistency: A Technical Issue in
Stackelberg Differential Games." Journal of Economic Theory 76 (2):
412-30.
We wish to thank Andreas Hornstein, Juan Carlos Hatchondo, Alex
Wolman, and Nashat Moin for their comments. The views expressed in this
article do not necessarily represent those of the Federal Reserve Bank
of Richmond, the Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System, or
the Federal Reserve System. Any errors are my own.
(1) Exceptions to this recommendation include Correia (1996), and
Jones, Manuelli, and Rossi (1997), who show that the optimal long-run
tax on capital differs from zero when other factors of production are
either untaxed or not taxed optimally. As pointed out in Erosa and
Gervais (2001), capital income taxes in an overlapping generations
environment are not just distortionary, they involve some redistribution
among agents. Hence, optimal steady state capital income taxes need not
be zero in such a framework, as shown in the early work of Atkinson and
Sandmo (1980), and later Garriga (1999), as well as in Erosa and Gervais
(2002) with age-dependent taxes. Finally, see Aiyagari (1995) for an
environment with idiosyncratic uninsurable shocks where optimal capital
income taxes are not zero in the long run.
(2) In this case, what matters is a government's ability to
bequeath revenue-generating assets to its successor that, potentially,
render the use of future taxes unnecessary. Thus, optimal confiscatory
short-run capital taxes would behave as stated in Chamley (1986) in
environments in which the government can lend directly to firms.
Alternatively, one can also imagine optimal allocations emerging in an
environment in which the government directly owned the capital stock and
had no disadvantage in operating production directly.
(3) With this restriction in place, an exogenously imposed upper
bound on capital income tax rates is no longer necessary. Moreover, the
upper limit of 100 percent imposed by Chamley (1986) is not helpful in
creating moderate optimal tax rates since this limit turns out to be
binding in the short run.
(4) See McGrattan and Ohanian (1999).
(5) It is tempting at this point to simply solve a Lagrangian
corresponding to the policy problem we have just described. The exact
way in which to write this Lagrangian, however, is not immediately
clear. To apply Lagrangian methods to this constrained maximization
problem, and in particular, to interpret the Lagrange multipliers
associated with constraints (5), (7), (8), and (9) as nonnegative, one
must first write these constraints as inequalities that define convex
sets. See the Appendix for details.
(6) The captial stock is fixed in period 0. It then decreases
slowly while capital income tax rates are relatively high and converges
back to its long-run level.
(7) Chari, Christiano, and Kehoe (1994) present an actual numerical
solution to the problem without linearizing. The linearization in our
case involves an approximation, but the fact that optimal taxes do not
involve corner solutions in our framework does not depend on the
approximation.