All things go in pairs, or the sharks will bite: the antithetical nature of Fijian chiefship.
Toren, Christina
In his postface to Homo Hierarchicus, Dumont argues for a theory
of hierarchy as `the encompassing of the contrary' whereby
At the superior level there is unity; at the inferior level there is
distinction ... complementariness or contradiction is contained in a
unity of superior order. But as soon as we intermingle the two levels,
we have a logical scandal, because there is identity and contradiction
at the same time. (1980:242, orig. 1966).
He contrasts his `hierarchical schema' with the `Hegelian
schema' where `transcendance is produced synthetically, instead of
pre-existing.' (ibid:243). Ideas implicate values, and for Dumont
To adopt a value is to introduce hierarchy, and a certain consensus
of values, a certain hierarchy of ideas, things and people, is
indispensable to social life (ibid:20).
So he implies that human thought is hierarchical in its nature and
thus makes hierarchy itself an ultimate value in which other values are
nested. His thesis has been influential, particularly in so far as it
has given rise to the view that the anthropologist's aim should be
to analyse the hierarchy of values that informs the behaviour of people
with whom he or she is working.[1]
But what if analysis reveals a profound resistance to the very
possibility of an encompassing value? A resistance that itself informs
those relations between people we characterise as kinship, political
economy, religion, and one that consists precisely in positing
contradictory values as equally important? At this point, far from being
`indispensable to social life' and given in the nature of mind,
Dumont's `'hierarchical schema' becomes vacuous and the
`Hegelian schema' triumphs.
This essay addresses Dumont's argument with Hegel via an
examination of ethnographic material concerning the historical and
contemporary nature of Fijian chiefship. In so doing, it deals with
hierarchy as a value and with Dumont's theory that values are
hierarchically ordered. It does not address his analysis of his Indian
data, rather it argues that in so far as his theory of hierarchy is
based on historically specific data and in so far as his `hierarchy of
values' is naive with respect to the model of mind it implies,
there are sound reasons to reject its universal application. The essay
argues that ethnic Fijians' ideas of the relation between hierarchy
and equality are Hegelian rather than Dumontian; that for them,
`transcendance can only be produced synthetically' precisely
because complementariness and contradiction cannot, ultimately, be
contained.
Fijian ideas of hierarchy are constituted through the
transformation in ritual of balanced, reciprocal exchange into tribute.
Chiefly ritual appears to contain, and thus to render non-threatening,
equally powerful notions of equality, such that Fijian villagers come to
conceive of hierarchy as given (Toren 1990). However, chiefly ritual
does not encompass the whole of life. So, for example, an analysis of
representations of compassion and desire as experienced over time by
people at different stages of life show that these two most salient
forms of love inform and are informed by hierarchical and equal
relations within and across sex, such that each kind of love becomes the
grounds of the possibility of the other (Toren, in press a). Compassion
and desire are rendered cosmogonic in various stories of the old Gods
and inform hierarchical and equal relations within and across groups;
moreover, Methodism (the religion of the vast majority of ethnic
Fijians), which contains its own inherent tension between hierarchy and
equality, is taking on a distinctively Fijian form (Toren, forthcoming).
Equality and hierarchy are the warp and woof of the fabric of
Fijian village life.[2] There is an attempt to make hierarchy contain
relations of equality and a simultaneous recognition that this hierarchy
itself depends for its very continuity on the dynamic of relations of
equality which cannot in their nature ultimately be contained by chiefly
ritual, but only by raw power -- that is to say, by superior physical
force.[3] This essay is an historical analysis of this thesis. It
concerns political rivalry between Fijian chiefs as this is apparent in
the records of the Lands Commission for the vanua of Sawaieke, on the
island of Gau.[4] The analysis also addresses A.M. Hocart's theory
of the development of Fijian hierarchy.
DUALISM AND THE TRANSFORMATION OF EQUALITY INTO HIERARCHY
In his preface to Kings and Councillors, Rodney Needham points out
that Hocart's first premise is that ritual `is a practical activity
intended to secure life' (1970:lxiii). His general purpose is to
argue that government evolves out of ritual organisation such that
equality, or a balanced organisation of functions, gives way to
centralisation and `a vertical hierachy':
If there is to be government, that is, coordination of actions,
there must
be some
to command and a majority to obey... as the regulation of conduct
becomes
the main interest rather than the control of nature, we see the
leader
become the
regulator; groups once equal acknowledge the supremacy of one; a
vertical
arrangement takes the place of a horizontal one... (1970:37)
For Hocart this process characterised the development of Fijian
chiefship. Later on in the same work, as in others, he discusses what he
calls `the dual organisation' whereby there are two kings or two
chiefs -- one whose functions are almost purely ritual, and one whose
functions are defense and war. He shows how the power of arms allowed
the war chief to usurp the position of the ritual chief who had formerly
taken precedence over him and how, in Fiji, the Tui (King or Ritual
Chief) is displaced by the Sau (War Chief) (1970:163-165, 1952:33-52,
1929:232-238).
The emphasis on Fijian dualism, on the necessity, in all
activities, for there to be `two sides' pervades Hocart's
work; in The Northern States of Fiji he quotes a Lauan informant as
saying `In Fiji all things go in pairs, or the sharks will bite'
(1952:57) and later he bemoans the excesses of dualism as
prophetic of decay, for dichotomy was becoming so common as to be
cheap... and was no longer reserved for ritual [occasions] ... [But] A
new and more solemn interest seems to have already encroached upon the
old dualism weaked by excess. That new enthusiasm was the service of the
chief ... [which] upset the old balance of paired groups ... The two
sides that used to face each other, equal except in precedence, have
begun to break up into units which all face the chief, like planets
round the sun. (1952:58)
Hocart's work on Fiji is remarkable for its ethnographic
richness and its theoretical insights, but `a vertical hierarchy'
is not, I argue, inevitable. Certainly the great war chiefs, like
Cakobau, were doing their best to bring a fixed hierarchy into being,
but they could suppress the inherent challenge of equal relations
between persons and between groups only by force of arms. With
pacification under British colonial rule, the ethos of competitive
equality that is as important to Fijians as hierarchy reasserted itself,
as it was bound to do, for in Fiji kinship implies both kinds of
relations and each is predicated on the other. A fixed hierarchy would
have required a fundamental shift in kinship and exchange relations, for
marriage is predicated on relations of equality between cross-cousins
across exogamous clans (mataqali), not only within, but also across,
sex; outside marriage, cross-cousins across sex are one another's
equals (see Toren 1990:50-52).
Hierarchy and equality in Fiji are expressed in terms of
disposition in space. So in accordance with one's status one may
sit above (i cake) or below (i ra) others when yaqona (kava) is drunk;
this above/below axis is constituted out of a transformation in ritual
of another spatial construct -- veiqaravi lit. `facing each other'
which describes the disposition of houses within the space of the
village (see Toren 1990: 74-89, 100-118). With cross-cousins one may be
on the same level (tau vata, literally `fall together'); similarly,
friends are veitau, i.e. equals and in village life, if I refer to
someone as my friend (noqu i tau), he or she is virtually always my
cross-cousin.[5]
All relationships can be conceptualised and referred to as kin
relations; at its widest extension one's kin include all other
ethnic Fijians. With the exception of the equal relation between
cross-cousins, all kinship relations are hierarchical and require
varying degrees of respect and avoidance. The antithesis between
hierarchy and competitive equality here references that between
non-marriageable kin (where the paradigmatic reference is to the
hierarchical household and clan) and marriageable kin (who as
cross-cousins are equals across households and clans).
The tension between hierarchy and equality given respectively by
relations between kin within the household and kin relations between
cross-cousins as affines across households can be historically related
to the nature of chiefship. High chiefs are associated on the one hand
with relations within the house-hold and on the other with affinity. By
virtue of drinking the installation yaqona a high chief becomes the
leader of the community, whose image in yaqona ritual is that of `the
household' writ large. At the same time, in both myth and history,
the first high chief is represented as a foreigner from over the sea who
married a daughter of the indigenous land chief and was later installed
by him as paramount. But the high chief and his descendants rule
thereafter only by consent of the landspeople; so the power that lies
with the land chief as head of the clan who `makes the chief' is
crucial. He can, and often does, refuse or delay the installation of a
putative paramount.[6]
In yaqona-drinking the paramount is seen to take precedence over
and to be above others just as, within the household, a man is seen to
take precedence over and to be above his wife. The perceived
subordination of wife to husband itself depends on the ritual
transformation of the equality of cross-cousins into the hierarchy of
marriage and is effected not only in the marriage ceremonies themselves,
but on a daily basis in the conduct of every meal (Toren 1990:52-64).
The exchange relations between spouses are complementary and balanced;
but at meals the wife sits below her husband, serves him, and eats only
when he has finished. The ritual transformation of balanced reciprocity across households into tribute to chiefs that takes place on a daily
basis in yaqona-drinking has the appearance of being fully effective
only in the ceremony of the installation yaqona, in which the chief dies
as a man to be reborn as a God `with all the ancestors at his back'
(Toren 1990: 100-118). However, in Gau, while there was, and is, a named
paramount, Takalaigau, it seems that a putative paramount is often named
and never installed and that this was also the case in the past. When I
asked people why this was so I received one of two answers: one gave
particular reasons to account for particular instances and usually
referred to the unfitness of a particular person to take office; the
other was contained in the explanation that `there is too much
veiqati' (lit. rivalry).
CHIEFSHIP AND RIVALRY IN THE HISTORY OF SAWAIEKE
Veiqati, as used by the villagers of Sawaieke, always carried
strong connotations of envy and jealousy. It was used especially in
connection with political rivalries between chiefs -- that is to say,
between the chiefs of various yavusa (group of closely connected clans)
and within yavusa between the chiefs of rival mataqali (clans).[7]
This jealous rivalry can be understood as a special instance of
the ethic of competition that pervades villagers' daily life.
Veiqati (especially between siblings) is frowned upon as `not according
to kinship' (sega ni vakaveiwekani), but friendly competition and
brinkmanship is entirely proper between cross-cousins as kin who are
affines or potentional affines (usually within, but sometimes across,
generations) where it routinely takes the form of joking and teasing
(veiwali, veisamei). This joking and teasing has an aggressive, even
confrontational, tone between people who are related as veitabani (from
countries whose founding ancestors were cross-cousins) or as veitauvu
(from countries who are descendants of the same ancestor god).[8]
Long-running instances of political veiqati are evident in the
`General History of the Country of Sawaieke' (Na i tukutuku raraba
ni vanua ko Sawaieke) recorded by the officials of the Lands Commission
in 1916.[9] The dispute addressed in this essay concerned who had a
right to the paramount chiefship, where these persons' ancestors
came from, and whether or not they were installed. The record of this
dispute at once confirms and throws into question the notion of `the
stranger chief'; it shows the twofold nature of the vasu relation
between a person and his or her mother's clan, whose focus is the
relation between Mother's Brother and Sister's Child; it shows
how ready certain people may be to challenge even an installed
paramount; and above all it makes plain that in both myth and history
Fijian hierarchy has always been in tension with competitive equality.
Below I give some extracts from this history whose time-span
begins 150 years or so before the Lands Commission and ends at the
period that Fiji was ceded to Britain (i.e. between, say, the mid-1700s
and 1874).[10] In those days the village was co-terminous with the
yavusa; the villages attended on each other in ritual and inter-married,
but they also challenged and fought each other for precedence. Today, as
in 1916, Sawaieke village is made up of several yavusa. The 1916 account
of the origins of the chiefly yavusa Nadawa was given by the leader of
Naboginbola, one of its component clans;[11] it is in many respects a
classic tale of the stranger chief from over the sea who shows himself
to be mana (lit. `effective') and thus gains the daughter of the
land chief and later the paramount chiefship which is voluntarily
surrendered to him by the older man.
Our honorific title is Nadawa. The name of our original ancestor (vu)
is Mualevu who came from Nakobuna in Gau. One time Narai -- the leader
of the Sawaieke people -- wanted to go to a place on the mainland and
went to the Nakobuna people that they might sail him there. So they
sailed him there and dropped anchor. Then Mualevu went to Dravuni in
Tai, stayed there a little while and came back ... then all those who
were with Narai returned to Gau. Afterwards [Mualevu] returned to
Dravuni and was married there, his wife was the child of KoyamaiDravuni
[a chiefly title] and a child was born to them, a boy, and his name was
Bui [sic]. Then Biu grew up until he was big and he was always making
the children in Dravuni cry and the fathers of children were angry about
this and they pronounced the name of the land of Biu's father.
After that they brought him here to Gau and he went to stay in his
village, Nakobuna, in his clan Waivolita.
One time the Waivolita clan came here ... but when they arrived
... and the thing was done that they came to do, they were returning to
Nakobuna when they met on the path with Narai, the leader of the
Sawaieke people, together with his attendants. [The Sawaieke people] had
finished eating [but] there still remained a head of saqa and Narai
called to [Biu and his company] that they should eat the head of that
saqa. But they were were afraid to eat it. Then Biu spoke to them: eat
the head of the saqa, I take on the responsibility of making a kill with
a club so as to beat down [this challenge]. So they ate it. When they
had finished eating they asked that they might return to Nakobuna where
[Biu] continued always to think about his speech to Narai.
Sometimes Biu went as a warrior and killed a few people and
brought them to Narai. After that Narai called Bui [sic] to go there to
him so the two of them might live together and then Biu was doing a
great deal of work for Narai. After that [Narai] gave his daughter Adi
Tora as wife to Biu and also his High Chief's Comb (na nona i Seru
ni Sau) and a piece of land for his village, the name of which was
Nadawa, and so Biu lived there and had children and they were four boys
...[12]
So when these children of Nadawa grew to be many they left Nadawa
and went to make a village at Navasa. They went together with their
father, Biu. After that they each got married and had children ...
And when this band of brothers was living in Navasa and had become
many they asked the chiefs of Burei for a piece of land that they might
build a village ... They made a yavu [foundation] for themselves and ...
they each built the yavu of their houses and they each settled there.
This band of four brothers then divided into three; their divisions
were: 1. Naboginibola 2. Naocomatana 3. Tabaisa ... The chiefly status
of Takalaigau [paramount chief of the eight villages of Sawaieke
country] `jumps around' (veiladeyaki) just to these three clans.
Takalaigau owes allegiance to (vakarorogo lit. listens to) the High
Chief (Vunivalu) at Bau... (See Fig.1)
Fijian chiefship, Hocart argued, was concerned to bring about and
to maintain prosperity and the story shows Biu to be an effective
warrior and provider. He accepts the challenge to eat the head of the
saqa (a fish whose eating is the prerogative of chiefs) and shows
himself a capable warrior and able to further the prosperity of his
people, for Narai gives him land to found a new village, Nadawa. However
Biu's living together with Narai and the `great deal of work'
he does for him seem to suggest bride service -- observations which do
not fit with an assumption of the stranger-chief's inherent
superiority (Sahlins 1985:78). Moreover the marriage makes the foreigner
son-in-law to the reigning chief, to whom he thus owes the utmost
respect and obedience, and cross-cousin -- and equal -- to his
wife's brothers. His children will be sister's children to his
wife's brothers and vasu to her clan; this vasu relation is twofold
in that it demands respect and obedience from the Sister's Child
(and more saliently from the Sister's Son) to the Mother's
Brother and at the same time allows the Sister's Child as vasu `to
take without asking' from the mother's people (cf.
Levi-Strauss 1984:172).
However, Biu -- whose name means `rejected' -- is not really
a stranger.[13] Indeed he has every right to be in Sawaieke vanua where
his father came from and where he thus has patrilineal rights in land.
Further Biu belongs to a clan that can be classified as `sea' and
in this respect stands in an exchange relation of balanced reciprocity
to the clan of Narai, `leader of the Sawaieke people', who is
`land'.[14] The founding ancestor of landspeople clans was given in
1916 by NaRai (once the title of the paramount and today the title of
the chief of landspeople clans) as Rokotaloko from Vuya, Bua, Vanua
Levu.
Indeed, the records of the Lands Commission investigation show
that all the ancestors of all the people of Sawaieke country came from
elsewhere.[15] But there is no suggestion in the records that an
ancestor of the NaRai who created the first paramount to hold the title
Takalaigau had wrested the chiefship from an earlier incumbent who was
the chief of another, possibly, indigenous people. Oral traditions,
however, suggest that this was So.[16] The NaRai who figures in the
story of Biu is also referred to as Na Sau, a title which Hocart says
was that of the war chief who was second in precedence to the ritual
chief or Tui. The chief of Biu's clan and yavusa, whom he
apparently revolted against, was Tui Voda who may, at that time, have
been the `ritual chief' alongside NaRai as `war chief'.[17]
Today, in Sawaieke, the title Tui is accorded to the heads of three of
the village's component yavusa, all of whom owe allegiance to
(vakarorogo vua, lit. `listen to') Takalaigau, who is also referred
to as Na Sau (cf. Hocart 1952: 34-37).
In 1916 Takalaigau, the paramount chief of Sawaieke country (vanua
i.e. eight villages of which Sawaieke is the chiefly village), was Ratu
Tomasi Tokalauvere of the chiefly Tabaisa clan (See Fig.2). In his
evidence to the Lands Commission, he at first referred only to his
Sawaieke ancestry and he was challenged by a man in a rival chiefly clan
as follows:(18)
During the time that the late Buli [Fijian official of the
colonial
administration)
was living we had already gathered together [i.e. several little
villages
had come
together to form a single chiefly village of several component
yavusa] and
it was
explained to the high chief and told to him that his line [nona
kawa] came
from
Lasakau in Bau -- that's how it is. We said therefore that
our paths were two
[divided]; he comes from Bau, we do not, but it appears from the
high chief's
account that we are just one.
Ratu Tomasi countered this by saying that he was indeed related to
the Sawaieke people through his father's father's
father's mother who had married into a Bauan family and that his
father's father, Ratu Damudamu, was of the Matanivanua in Bau. Then
another of Ratu Tomasi's rivals, the chief who had told the story
of Biu with its account of the origins of the chiefly Nadawa clan,
asserted that Tabaisa -- Ratu Tomasi's clan -- could not be
recognised as a chiefly, Nadawa clan. The Tabaisa clan is of different
origins (e ra kawa tani)' he said. The dispute continued and Ratu
Tomasi told how his ancestor Ratu Damudamu had come to Gau and been
taken in by his grandfather Veidre (FFMF) who, it is implied, was then
NaRai, chief of the landspeople, and able to install the paramount.(19)
Ratu Tomasi asserted that his grandfather had installed Ratu Damudamu as
Takalaigau and that because of this there was a quarrel; Ratu Damudamu
and his supporters had fled to a neighbouring village and from there
called to his kin in Bau for support:
Then Ratu Damudamu proclaimed war and called on Bau [to help him],
then
the warships went from Bau. Then [the chiefs of two rival clans in
the
chiefly
yavusa and the land chief] went there to intercept [the warships)
at the
opening
in the reef and there they performed the atonement with a reed [in
order to
prevent war], so that they might drink [yaqona] together to bring
about
peace.
Then Ratu Damudamu was confirmed as Takalaigau ...
The chiefs (malo, cloths) of the [chiefly] Nadawa people are
[the
leaders of
the component clans] Tabaisa, Lomanibuca, Naboginibola and
Valebalavu.
Ratu Tomasi had already described how, when presentations of feast
food (magiti) were made to the chiefly yavusa, Tabaisa clan along with
Valebalavu and Naboginibola were `accorded their share from the village
green' (e votai mai rara). Since this was infallible evidence that
Tabaisa was recognised as a clan in the chiefly yavusa, his apparent
rival, the Naboginibola chief, had to admit that Ratu Tomasi's
account of the composition of the yavusa and the ritual duties of its
component clans was correct.(20) However, Ratu Tomasi's other
evidence was again disputed, again by a member of a rival chiefly
clan:(21)
My mataqali is Naboginibola. Lomanibuca, Navakaotisau and
Vanuayalewa are
our yavu (house foundations) in Nabogini-bola and were made
significant
through the murders of Biu. The meaning of Navakaotisau is that
the reign of
Raitena was over. Vanuayalewa is because of Biu's challenge
to those above
him.
Lomanibuca is because their village stood in the centre of the
vanua. Those
in
Tabaisa have only the one yavu, Tabaisa. Buliruarua [a.k.a.
Vukicivoda, the
grandson of the founding ancestor Biu] was Takalaigau when
Damudamu
arrived here. Tabaisa dropped anchor at an opening in the reef.
Damudamu was
not installed as Takalaigau.
This account was verified by the then leader of landspeople clans,
that is to say, by the man who as holder of the title NaRai was able to
install a paramount chief:(22)
Ratu Damudamu was not installed. He just came here and lived with
the chiefs
... Those chiefs looked down on him and they quarrelled. Then he
spoke with
our elders, who moved him to [a neighbouring village]. Then war
was declared
and the Sawaieke people had no energy for it. We gave in. We
returned here,
then
Damudamu died in Sawaieke. Ratu Tomasi is already installed as
Takalaigau.
When [the previous Takalaigau] was about to die, he declared Ratu
Tomasi his
successor, and so he was installed.
At the end of this dispute it is clear that Ratu Tomasi's
claims that his yavu (house foundation) and clan were legitimately part
of the chiefly yavusa and that he was himself a properly installed
paramount chief were accepted as correct by the officers of the Lands
Commission.
The points to be noticed here are, firstly, that Tabaisa, (the
name of the house and clan of which Ratu Tomasi is head) is said to have
`dropped anchor at an opening in the reef'; this suggests a cynical
and very successful opportunism on the part of Ratu Tomasi's
ancestor Ratu Damudamu.(23)
Secondly, an attempt is made to use Ratu Tomasi's foreign
origins against him; indeed it appears from the early part of the Lands
Commission record that those who gave evidence to it may have thought
that to make good their claims to land they had to have a founding
ancestor who was born in Gau.(24) Certainly Ratu Tomasi seems to have
thought that this was what was required.
Thirdly, it appears from information not quoted here that previous
to Ratu Tomasi there had been some five holders of the title Takalaigau,
the first being Seruqaraivalu, the son of Biu whose story was told above
and who received `his High Chief's Comb' from the then
paramount NaRai; when the genealogies are matched to the places where
specific incidents took place, it would seem that Ratu Damudamu from the
island of Bau was a contemporary of the second Takalaigau, Buliruarua,
the son of Seruqaraivalu.(25) If we allow any given Takalaigau a
generous ascendancy of some 20 years, then the title came into being
some 100 to 150 years before the Lands Commission investigation. This
makes sense, for it accords with the dates when Bau was asserting its
power in Lomaiviti (central Fiji, where Gau lies) and the title
Takalaigau is originally that of Bau's representative in Gau.(26)
In the Lands Commission records Takalaigau is said `to listen to'
(owe allegiance to) the paramount chief in Bau.
Fourthly, and given Ratu Tomasi's emphasis on his Bauan
ancestor's descent through a woman who was daughter to a
lands-people chief in Sawaieke country, it seems very possible that Ratu
Damudamu made his claim on his grandfather as a vasu (sister's
child, even if at several removes); the privilege of the vasu is to
`take without asking' from the mother's people and if
`grandfather Veidre' indeed held the title NaRai, as Ratu
Tomasi's account suggests he did, then what he had to give was the
paramount chiefship -- for only Narai can install a paramount in office,
however he cannot be compelled to do so, except perhaps by the threat of
superior force of arms. Indeed this may be what happened; it is
suggestive that the Takalaigau who was in office when Ratu Damudamu
arrived is referred to as Buliruarua or Bulivakarua - meaning `Twice
Installed' -- who is elsewhere identified as being Biu's
son's son, Vukicivoda; perhaps his reign was interrupted by Ratu
Damudamu who died while Vukicivoda was still alive, so allowing him to
be installed a second time.
But what allowed Ratu Damudamu to be adopted into the chiefly
Nadawa clan so that all his descendants became legitimate members of it?
The record does not tell us, but it does suggest that he lived with `the
chiefs in Navasa' before he went to live with his grandfather, the
chief of landspeople clans. He may have married into the Nadawa clan,
but it is more likely that he was related to the Nadawa people via the
female line since Bau where his own mother came from and the mainland
village of Dravuni where Biu's mother came from are near to one
another. But, whatever the case, he certainly had close kin in Sawaieke.
Finally, the records reveal that members of another chiefly clan
appeared to have no compunction about using the Lands Commission's
investigations to undermine -- and perhaps even to try to oust -- an
installed paramount chief. Certainly the 1916 dispute contains no
challenges from persons outside the chiefly yavusa, but then they would
have nothing to gain because the position of paramount can go only to a
member of a chiefly clan. Further, the then land chief, while he is not
against Ratu Tomasi as paramount, is prepared to contradict and to
correct him.
When one analyses these records it becomes apparent that Fijian
chiefship had retained its dual nature, that in their rise to power the
war chiefs (Na Sau) had not yet managed to render hierarchy absolute,
for, as I show below, it was still predicated on its antithesis --
equality between persons who relate to one another as cross-cousins
across households, and within and across clans and other larger
collectivities.
ANTITHETICAL DUALITY AND ITS TRANSFORMATION
That hierarchy in Fiji is not an encompassing value is apparent in
the words of Hocart's Lauan informant: `In Fiji all things go in
pairs, or the sharks will bite'. Here `sharks' can refer to
fishes, to the ancestor gods as manifest in that form, or to chiefs as
dangerous and warlike persons. The saying emphasises the duality of `all
things', but what is most important here is, I suggest, the
antithesis that is captured by this duality. In other words,
`things' have to be related to one another in a reciprocal form
that allows hierarchy and equality to be at one and the same time
implicated in that relationship. This is because in Fiji the fundamental
organising concept is that of `the household' which by definition
depends on the existence of other households for its continuing
existence. People relate to one another as kin, but while kin relations
within the household are axiomatically hierarchical -- husband above
wife, older sibling above junior sibling -- kinship across households
references the equal relationship between cross-cousins. Further, all
exchange relations are competitive and ultimately those of balanced
reciprocity even while the rituals of chiefship render them as tributary
and apparently unequal.(27)
In the story of Biu, his marriage to NaRai's daughter is a
stage in his progress towards the paramount chiefship; it does not
render him superior to his father-in-law to whom he owes obedience and
respect, but it does provide him at once with a household of his own and
a wife who is subordinate to him. In the exchanges on betrothal and
marriage and at the birth of the first child, `the side of the man'
must give more than `the side of the woman'; this points not to the
inherent superiority of wife-takers but to the fact that the woman and
her future children are part of what is given by `the side of the
woman', for what I was told of these exchanges is that if the
man's side does not give more, they will be `ashamed' (see
Toren 1990: 52-56, 85-89, cf. Sahlins 1976: 24-46).
However, within the marriage relationship itself, the effective
alienation of the woman from her natal household and clan renders her
subordinate to her husband, for she eats food that is provided by the
fertile power of his ancestors whose land he gardens and whose power
sends her the fish she catches; indeed her own fertility is implicitly
sacrificed to the same source; thus, as Fijians say, `every man is a
chief in his own house' and a wife attends on her husband and
receives his largesse. Nevertheless, in terms of the division of labour,
of production and exchange, husband and wife are in a reciprocal and
equal relation of demand -- he must produce root crops and she must
fish, he must build the house and she must weave mats to furnish it, and
so on; this reciprocal and balanced relation of interdependence is
undoubtedly important for the nature of the transformations that are
evident in the marriage relationship. Before marriage a woman is the
equal of her male cross-cousin and, by definition, all marriages are
between cross-cousins. After marriage she is axiomatically subordinate
to her husband, a transform which is rendered apparently complete by the
young husband's almost routine violence towards his wife. However,
over time, this relationship is transformed yet again so that it becomes
implicitly a relation between equals, even while it is said to be
hierarchical (Toren, in press a).(28)
In marrying out a woman is, as it were, unfairly deprived of her
birthright, and this is implicit in the way her rights in her natal clan
devolve upon her children who, as vasu, may `take without asking'
from the men of their mother's clan. If one leaves the woman
herself out of the reckoning, one can argue that what the vasu takes is
his-or hers by virtue, not of what the mother has given up, but of the
massive prestation of goods to the mother's kin that secures
recognition of the vasu in the ceremony of kau mata ni gone (lit.
`carrying the face of the child') (see Sahlins (1976:29-32). But
this is to ignore the twofold nature of the relation between
mother's brother and sister's child which combines the license
that is usually proper only to people or groups who relate to one
another as cross-cousins, with the extreme respect, avoidance and
obedience that is properly shown by a real or classificatory son-in-law
to his father-in-law. The prestation of goods compensates the
woman's clan for the loss of her child who carries the blood of
their ancestors too, and so secures recognition of the child in his or
her own person; but the vasu's subsequent `snatching', the
`taking without asking' surely signifies a recognition of the
enforced loss through her marriage of the mother's natal rights and
her inalienable claim to them -- an observation that is borne out by the
fact that no other, similarly massive, prestation across groups entails
any similar entitlement just to take what one wants in return (cf.
Levi-strauss 1984:176). `Taking without asking' is, however, an
implicit possibility between cross-cousins, between persons who relate
to one another as veitabani or veitauvu (two countries -- vanua -- whose
ancestors were cross-cousins or who have their founding ancestor in
common), and does in fact occur.(29) And this is so even though no
previous prestation has `secured' such a right on behalf of
particular persons and is indeed entirely unnecessary -- precisely
because they should be treated as `equal owners' in the house or
village of their opposite numbers; the sister's child is affiliated
to its father's clan and identified with him and it is only by
virtue of a similar identification between mother and child that the
child at once retains its junior status as child and becomes an
`owner' in the mother's natal household on the same footing as
her brothers.(30)
One finds a similar set of transformations between people who
relate to one another as `land' and `sea', where exchange
relations are again at once reciprocal and balanced and where again,
from one point of view they are regarded as one another's equals,
while from another `sea' appears to be superior to `land'. The
classification is not co-terminous with that which distinguishes chiefly
from commoner yavusa; thus, while chiefly yavusa are always `sea',
certain commoner yavusa are also `sea'. In central Fiji the
relationship also obtains across countries, e.g. in relation to the
people of Batiki, all the people of Sawaieke vanua are `land'. When
sea and land people are eating together, sea-people cannot eat fish and
land-people cannot eat pork, freshwater shrimp etc.; each makes
available to the other the product of their labour.
`All things go in pairs, or the sharks will bite.' And given
that all things go in pairs, a totality consists of a pair of pairs,
which explains why, in Fiji, everything really goes in fours.(31) Thus,
even while people relate to one another as `land' and `sea',
they simultaneously relate to one another as `chief' and
`commoner'. A member of the chiefly clan is by definition
`sea' while a member of the clan that installs the chief is by
definition `land'. A putative paramount chief cannot properly claim
precedence and ritual superiority over the land chief who is to install
him. This is evident in the story of Biu who is challenged by the land
chief to show he is mana, `effective'; when Biu accepts
NaRai's challenge he locks the land chief into a competitive
exchange of mana which culminates with the land chief's apparently
final defeat since the supreme act of mana that is open to him is that
of installing a paramount -- an act which renders him ritually inferior
to the other man.(31) Thus, as the present NaRai told me:
The making of the chief is my task alone ... that is a godly gift
that is
made to
me ... it is in the blood ... that is the power that is mine ...
but if the
yaqona
is given to him [Takalaigau -- the putative paramount] everything
in the
manner
of the land is encompassed therein. It does not matter that the
yaqona is
given to
him, I am still chief; but after I have given him the yaqona I
shall address
him as
saka [`sir'], I shall act with great respect towards him.
That is after I
have given
the yaqona, after I have made him drink ... After that I shall
attend on him,
everything he tells me I shall shoulder as a burden, nor shall I
try to make
myself
great by refusing to follow him. Everything he wants done in this
country
will be
told to me ... I shall then order it to be done.'
At first reading this statement suggests that NaRai becomes
unambiguously inferior to the installed Takalaigau; but even while Narai
says that the paramount chiefship encompasses everything, he also says
that the installation `does not matter' for he is `still
chief'. He is prepared to show great respect and to attend on the
installed paramount, but at the same time implies that he could, if he
wished, refuse to `follow' him and in so doing make himself
`great'. Further it is apparent that an installed paramount cannot
himself order things to be done, for it is NaRai's prerogative to
give orders. As Hocart pointed out, the function of an installed
paramount is just to be, so that he may receive and redistribute the
people's feasts and thus promote prosperity. Moreover, in exalting the other man to a paramount position, NaRai simultaneously exalts
himself: the paramount now `has at his back all the ancestors of
Gau' but as the one who gives orders, NaRai too commands a greater
and more effective power than he had before. That NaRai retains his
effective power and even augments it is apparent in the Lands Commission
records where the man holding the title in 1916 is called as an
authority and gives evidence that is accepted and only partly in favour
of the paramount chief, Ratu Tomasi. He is not cowed by his
counterpart's precedence in ritual.
Of course the question remains as to why a chief who is able to do
so does not install a putative paramount. I had previously thought that
this was because the paramount would thus attain an unambiguously
superior position with respect to the installing chief. However I now
think that this reluctance arises in circumstances where the rivalries
between particular persons in the chiefly clan itself are as important
as the relationship between the land chief and the putative paramount.
In other words, the land chief's relationship with other members of
the chiefly clan and with the chiefs of other clans governs his decision
to install or not to install a particular person.
Here it is interesting to look at the story of Biu as `stranger
chief' alongside the story of Damudamu as `stranger chief' and
the attitudes and effective powers of the persons who gave evidence to
the Lands Commission. That Biu was indeed paramount and his son the
first Takalaigau is accepted, but Ratu Tomasi's claim that his
ancestor Ratu Damudamu was installed as paramount remains in question
with conflicting evidence being adduced by everyone concerned. If Ratu
Damudamu was installed it seems he must have gained the chiefship by
virtue of being able to call on his Bauan kin to aid him in war; he is
not said to have performed any acts that were mana, `effective'.
Those opposing Ratu Tomasi represent Ratu Damudamu as an illegitimate
claimant precisely because he came from elsewhere and tried to usurp the
title by force; they ignore the fact that he could be classified as vasu
to the land chief, NaRai, and that he was clearly related to the chiefs
of Nadawa. Thus the opponents of Ratu Tomasi are implying that he, as
Damudamu's descendant, cannot himself be regarded as a legitimate
Takalaigau even though he is already installed. Ratu Tomasi has great
difficulty in countering these implications and has to rely on his
counterpart, the land chief, to support him; this the land chief does --
but only up to a point.
One asks oneself what Ratu Tomasi lacks to make good his claim and
the answer is clear -- he lacks warriors, he commands no physical force,
no terrifying reputation. The colonial administration had long done away
with both warriors and the priests whose godhead, in the dual person of
the land chief and the installed paramount, demanded cannibal feasts.
Ratu Tomasi had his ancestors to call on, as does any installed chief,
whose power automatically punishes any dereliction from duty on the part
of those who owe allegiance to him, but these ancestors were now under
the sway of the Christian god and `no one attended on them
anymore'.(33) Further Ratu Tomasi could not now call on his Bauan
kin to support him in war against any rival claimant. He was an
installed chief and as such he would have received all those ritual
attentions that were still possible, be seen to take precedence over
others and to sit above them in yaqona-drinking, to receive feasts whose
distribution was presided over by his counterpart the land chief, and to
be accorded all the formal appearances of respect. Ratu Tomasi reigned,
but he could not rule; only command of physical force would allow him to
rule, because the dual nature of Fijian chiefship inevitably works
against the institution of `a vertical hierarchy'.
The main point here is that, when the records of the Lands
Commission for Gau are analysed in light of relations within and across
groups, it is apparent that in 1916 hierarchy could not be said to be an
encompassing value; it is not Dumontian in its nature because it always
simultaneously implies competitive equality as an equally important and
antithetical value. Here my view differs from that put forward by
Sahlins in his various works, and more particularly in Sahlins (1985)
and (1991). In the latter essay, where he develops his notion of Fijian
history as `heroic' he writes:
`Of course everybody's actions signify, are meaningful. But
what
distinguishes
social-historical individuals is that their acts transcend
self-reference
-- by
far
and in a twofold way. Their acts engage social totalities, in the
first place
by
virtue of the structures of hierarchy in which as chiefs they
encompass
others.
This is logical as well as sociological; the chief represents the
logical
class of
which the people are members (Dumont 1970).' (Sahlins
1991:63)
Up to a point I agree with this, the great chiefs of the large
confederations did manage to encompass others, but this was not by
virtue of the `structures of hierarchy' for Fijian hierarchy was
never simply that, it never became `a vertical hierarchy' for it
was always, even in Bau, in tension with the antithetical value of
equality. It was force of arms and terror that allowed the various Sau
(war chiefs) to usurp the Tui (ritual chiefs) in the first place and it
was terror and force of arms that allowed them to maintain and
consolidate their position. Certainly, had their rise to power not been
interrupted by European imperialism, they might have managed over time
to achieve an instituted vertical hierarchy that, at least within their
own countries, not only effectively contained notions of equality across
persons, and clans, but even rendered Fijian social organisation as
`caste-like'. That they had not nearly achieved this is evident not
only in my own material, but in Hocart's remarks, quoted above, on
what he regarded as a degenerate efflorescence of dualism, whereby
ritual practices of competitive equality were extended into other
activities.
This efflorescence of practices of competitive equality may, I
suggest, be attributed to the chiefs' loss of their warrior forces.
Freed from the terror that was inspired by cannibalism and endemic
warfare, people in general -- including those who, as members of chiefly
clans, were classified as chiefs and those who were chiefs of the
various clans and vanua -- were able once again to assert the dual
nature of their values, to show that balanced reciprocity and
competitive equality are as salient, and as important, as tribute and
hierarchy.
But if hierarchy is not and cannot be an encompassing value for
Fijians, neither can equality achieve the ascendancy, for equal
relations too always implicate their opposite value. Marriage is
predicated on the equal relation between cross-cousins, but marriage
brings the household into being and with it the hierarchy of husband and
wife, the authority of the first-born, and the seniority of siblings.
The logic of Fijian social relations, of the relation between land and
sea, husband and wife, brother and sister, cross-cousins, mother's
brother and sister's children, commoner and chief, is always a
twofold logic where hierarchy and equality are in tension with one
another and dependent on one another for their very continuity. The
rituals of chiefship are explicitly understood to promote prosperity,
but they do so by virtue of projecting onto the collectivity -- the
vanua (country) -- an image of the hierarchical household; this image
implies the necessity for its own transformation because marriage is not
possible within but only across households; in other words one has
always to posit the existence of at least two households `facing each
other'. So Fijian chiefship has to be dual, has to be made up of
land and sea, of the executive powers of the land chief and the ritual
precedence of the paramount; only thus can it project an image of the
hierarchical household as existing alongside other households in the
relation of balanced reciprocity and equality that makes marriage
possible. In other words, the logic of Fijian chiefship is such that it
can promote prosperity only if it is dual.(34)
If balanced reciprocity and equality are denied, then powerful war
chiefs can `bite' -- as they evidently did during the late 18th and
19th centuries. They ceased merely to preside over the redistribution of
feasts and began to extract them, they exploited the rights of the vasu,
they promoted not general prosperity but sought to augment the power of
their own house and clan, but even so they could not eradicate equality
and balanced reciprocity, for these are enshrined in the very same
ritual practices that constitute hierarchy: veiqaravi, which denotes
`attendance on chiefs' means literally `facing each other' or
`attendance on each other'. Hocart's informant was undoubtedly
right; `in Fiji all things go in pairs, or the sharks will bite'.
CONCLUSION
Dumont's representation of the argument between himself and
Hegel asserts that he is concerned with `structure' while Hegel is
concerned with `dialectic'. However, Dumont does not address the
implicit suggestion that while Hegel could be said to be concerned with
the analysis of the nature of the categories of mind as a function of
`historical shifts, Dumont is only implicitly concerned with mind as a
function of `ideology'. Hegel's Phenomenology contains an
implicit notion of progress in respect of the `historical
development' of categories of mind, and this is surely disputable;
nevertheless he was just as surely right to emphasise history and to
insist that mind constitutes its categories and is constituted by them.
In this perspective, transcendance is given by Hegel's notion of
mind as the totality that is materially manifest in its products, even
while this very notion cannot be posited in the absence of an antithesis
between mind and matter.(35)
Hegel's ideas remain useful precisely in so far as he
attempted to come to grips with the subject/object relation between
persons and their historically constituted notions about the world they
inhabit; by contrast Dumont avoids this challenge by implicitly locating
categories that are the product of mind in some abstract space between
persons. In so doing, he makes `ideology' the source of the
categories, but `an ideology' only comes into existence as the
artefact of sociological analysis and as such it cannot be assumed to
allow transparent access to the workings of mind.
My point here is that that mind can be located only in the
embodied cognitive processes of particular persons whose cognitive
constitution of meaning is mediated by their relations with one another;
thus meaning is never received `readymade' (for cognitive processes
are inherently dynamic) but neither can meaning be made in isolation.
Rather the categorical products of mind have always to be constituted
anew by particular persons and this process is always informed by the
meanings already made by those particular others with whom any given
person interacts. So meaning is inevitably historically constituted and
inevitably transformed. This suggests that Dumont's `ideology'
as a system of hierarchically ranked values has little explanatory
value, for it implies that meaning is received; indeed he takes ideology
to be immanent in language and language itself to be transparent, to
declare its own meaning and thus implicitly to be a-historical: `It is
obvious that there is a basic ideology, a kind of germinal ideology tied
to common language and hence to the linguistic group or the global
society' (1980:343).(36)
But when we focus on the person in relation to other persons, it
becomes clear that any given person is the locus of the relations in
which he or she engages with others, and that in the course of this
engagement the nature of any given relationship is itself cognitively
constituted by each of the persons involved.
Any Fijian person is the locus of relations which are mutually
constituted as either hierarchical or equal; however, given their
different histories as particular persons, each one has somewhat
different ideas about the nature of those hierarchical or equal
relationships, and any given person's engagement in such
relationships begins at birth. For the Fijian child the very process of
learning kinship' constitutes relations with non-marriageable kin
as hierarchical and with marriageable kin as equal. Further, this
process does not implicate an axiomatic distinction between power and
status, for material power is inherent in the process in and through
which any given child learns that this person's status is manifest
in command over him or her and that person's status in a mutual,
competitive equality. Neither is there any point at which one can say
that, for any given Fijian person, hierarchy acquires a greater value
than equality -- for, on an everyday basis, one may even say from moment
to moment, the person is engaged in constituting the one and the other
as equally crucial to the nature of existence. Further, given that it is
through inter-subjectivity that the notion of the self as subject is
constituted, it becomes apparent that both hierarchy and equality will
be implicated in Fijian notions of the self and personhood. It is
precisely this antithesis that makes it possible for a person to be yalo
qaqa (of determined mind, courageous) and so respond to a challenge that
comes from one who is far superior in status and power; thus Biu, in the
story with which I began, is able as a young man to rise to the
challenge from the then paramount NaRai and, over time, to prove himself
worthy of the paramount chiefship, even though his initial structural
position would seem to disqualify him from doing so.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
This paper is based on one presented to the International Conference
on Leadership in the Pacific in honour of Sir Raymond Firth, December
1991. It was rewritten for publication in 1992/93 during my tenure, as
Research Fellow in the Politics of Tradition in the Pacific, funded by
Macquarie University, Sydney, Australia and by the Australian Research
Council.
NOTES
(1.) See Barnes, de Coppet & Parkin eds. (1985) for a debate on
this issue. Dumont's thesis has also informed analyses of political
hierarchy outside India - see e.g. Sahlins (1985 & 1991) on Fiji and
Valeri (1985) on Hawaii; other scholars of Austronesia have argued
against it (see e.g. Mosko & Jolly, forthcoming) but, so far as I
know, none have taken the pro-Hegelian stance that I argue in this
paper.
(2.) So, for example, the ritualized drinking of yaqona (kava) and of
alcohol refer to the antithesis between hierarchical and equal
relations, between tribute and balanced reciprocity (Toren, in press b).
Here the contrast suggests that these equal relations are not
Fijian' - a sleight of hand that is evident too in the contrast
drawn between 'the gift' and 'the commodity' (Toren,
1989) - and which is possible because neither alcohol drinking nor
commodity exchange can take on the form of chiefly ritual.
(3.) Cf. Jolly (forthcoming) who, in her comparison of hierarchy in
Vanuatu and Fiji, remarks that `Hierarchy is a pervasive feature of both
symbolic systems and of socio-political relations, but there is no
overarching principle which establishes the hierarchical ordering of all
elements in any social `whole'.' My own position is rather
different, for I am arguing here that, at least for Fijians, hierarchy
and equality are always and inevitably posited together and counterposed
such that the existence of each is dependent on that of its opposite,
and neither hierarchy nor equality can become an encompassing value.
(4.) Fieldwork from June 1981 to March 1983 was financed by an award
from the Social Science Research Council and from May - September 1990
by a Brief Award from Brunel University. In 1981-83 the population of
Sawaieke vanua (country) was about 1400 and of the village, 260; by 1990
the population of the vanua had risen to 1700-1800 and the population of
the village to about 290. About half Fiji's population
(approximately 750,000 people) are of Indian descent; there is no Indian
community on Gau.
(5.) Veitau is also used to denote friendly competition as in veitau
cici, a foot race; cf. veiqati which denotes a more jealous rivalry.
(6.) In the country (vanua) of Sawaieke, chiefs are usually no richer
and no poorer than commoners and this is so even if we use `chiefs'
in its narrowest sense to refer only to those men who are chiefs of
yavusa (na malo lit. `the cloths') -- a yavusa being a group of
clans connected by affinal and ritual-cum-political ties; in
pre-colonial days the yavusa was co-terminous with the village.
(7.) In previous works I have translated yavusa as 'clan'
and mataqali as `lineage'; here the latter term is translated as
'clan' while yavusa, derived from yavu (house foundation),
denotes a group of related `houses'. In part I agree with Shelley
Sayes' thesis that yavusa are not so much `descent groups' as
`a group of mataqali who have remained together in the same locality ...
kinship through intermarriage often might have been their only
ties' (Sayes 1983:87). However, in Fiji marriage is the foundation
for the constitution of kinship, just as kinship (i.e. the relation
between brother and sister) creates the possibility of marriage (i.e.
between the respective children of the brother and sister, or their
children's children, who are affines). In other words, affinal ties
are explicitly encompassed by kinship.
(8.) I was told many times in Sawaieke that a person with whom one is
veitauvu was `just the same as an owner of the village' and that
his or her every want would not only be attended to at once, but even
anticipated; however, when people spoke of visiting places where they
were tauvu, they always emphasised how important they were to be
recognised as such because of the aggressive, if welcoming, attention
this recognition entails.
(9.) Enquiries into land holdings began in the late 19th century but
those that were ultimately recognised were established by the Lands
Commissions of 1912 onwards. I am grateful to the present Takalaigau,
Ratu Marika Uluinadawa, who gave me access to his personal copy of the
records for Gau, which are also held in the I Taba ni Veitarogi Vanua in
Suva.
(10.) To avoid the confusion produced by too many unfamiliar names, I
have at times paraphrased the text.
(11.) This was Ratu Marika Lewanavanua, then the Buli for Gau. This
office was created by the British administration; in any given area, the
Buli was usually selected from the chiefly clan.
(12.) The name of Biu's first son, Seruqaraivalu, means Comb
Warrior' or, more literally `Comb facing war' and the name of
Seruqaraivalu's son, Vukicivoda, means Revolted against
Voda'; these names are significant because Seruqaraivalu as one
whose father gained status through his warlike prowess was the first
holder of the title Takalaigau; the name of his son refers to Biu's
revolt against the chief of his own yavusa, Tui Voda. Till today,
children may be named after an important event in the lives of their
parents or grandparents.
(13.) In the I tukutuku raraba ni vanua ko Sawaieke Biu's name
is also sometimes given as Bui, but I take this to be a typing error since Bui means `grandmother' and Biu meaning `rejected' is
consistent with the story of his dismissal by his mother's people.
(14.) As Na Sau, the paramount, NaRai would initially be `sea',
as would Biu who `went to stay in his village Nakobuna, in his clan
Waivolita'. The Nakobuna chief `listened to' (vakarorogo vua
i.e. owed allegiance to) Tui Voda - then and today the chief of
fisher-people clans - whose founding ancestor is recorded as having come
from Kaba, Tailevu. The story shows that the Nakobuna people were
navigators to the Sau - war chief - NaRai (also known as Na Raitena);
Nakobuna village still existed in 1916, though not today. NaRai's
giving of the chiefship to Biu transforms him into `land' and makes
Biu take on the association with `sea' that belongs to the
paramount.
(15.) A similar point is made by Deryck Scarr (1976) for Bau and by
Shelley Sayes (1983: xxviii, 36, 57ff, 65, 74, 87) in her history of the
Cakaudrove chiefship; see also Nicholas Thomas (1986).
(16.) Rokotaloko, the founding ancestor of the Na Raitena people, is
sometimes referred to as the owner of Na Ivinivini, a large mound which
stands on the outskirts of Sawaieke village - the foundation of a bure
kalou, god house, `in the time of the devils'(e na gauna
vakatevoro). For an analysis of the story of Radikedike, a.k.a.
Rokotaloko, see Toren (in press c). Rokotaloko is variously said to have
come from Vuya or from Dama, in Bua, Vanua Levu; Radikedike is said to
have come from Dama.
(17.) The story makes it appear that NaRai as Sau may have taken
precedence over Tui Voda, but this may be an artifact of the
account's being given by a chief whose ideas of the ritual duties
of the two yavusa are those of 1916, rather than of an earlier era.
(18.) This was Orisi Qaraiwalu, of Naocomatana; the paramount Ratu
Tomasi asserts that Naocomatana is a subdivision of Naboginibola clan,
rather than a clan in its own right. The speaker, Orisi Qaraiwalu was at
the time turaga ni koro -- `village chief', a position created by
the colonial administration. The post is not a high-status one and today
is often held by a relatively young man in his 30s or 40s, who is
elected by his fellow villagers.
(19.) At one point, Ratu Tomasi says that Veidre (whom he had first
stated to be his vu or founding ancestor was himself installed as
Takalaigau, but since other evidence suggests that Veidre was a land
chief (not a member of the chiefly clan) this seems unlikely to have
been the case.
(20.) The Naboginibola chief also leaves another chiefly clan,
Valebalavu, out of his account. This suggests he saw Valebalavu as a
threat and that another clan, Naocomatana, which his account implicitly
exalts, were his allies.
(21.) His name was Akariva Beraateri.
(22.) His name was Vilikesa Kalou.
(23.) Chiefs may be metaphorically identified with na vesi or na waqa
vakaturaga -- both terms for the chiefly canoe.
(24.) This is clearly the case for the Naboginibola chief who tells
the story of Biu; in fact, Biu's father, Mualevu turns out to be
the only vu who is said to have come from Gau; but if we accept the
story of Biu, then Mualevu's own origins have to be those accorded
to the Waivolita people in Nakobuna - i.e. his vu is from Kaba in
Tailevu.
(25.) In calculating the genealogies, I have allowed for a use of the
term `grandfather' to refer to anyone who is senior in the line of
FF or FM.
(26.) See Capell (1973: 213). By the early 1800s Bau had achieved
ascendancy throughout much of Central and Eastern Fiji (Scarr, 1976).
(27.) Cf Thomas (forthcoming) who argues that `[e]ncompassment is ...
not a structural condition - a one to one identification between king
and society -- but an effect of efficacy that is open to being
undermined or challenged.'
(28.) Thus, while all children take `mother' to be below
`father' within the household, those who are at an age where they
have begun to have an enlightened understanding of status distinctions,
simultaneously take husbands and wives to be one another's peers
within that collectivity at large (Toren 1990:202-205). Yet older
children, those who have constituted the `mature' concept of
hierarchy as arising out of an interaction between gender, rank and
seniority, represent women as an undifferentiated group as having a
lower status than married men; however, while for boys women may
generally be said to be `lower' even than young (i.e. unmarried)
men, for girls married women have a status that is higher or equal to
that of young men.
(29.) Persons who relate to one another as cross-cousins, or as
veitabani or veitauvu are not explicitly said to be able to `take
without asking' from their opposite numbers, but I was told of many
instances of such behaviour, especially between cross-cousins. When the
telling was a complaint and I asked why my informant had made no
protest, he or she would routinely say that it would not be right to
protest `because we are cross-cousins' (or veitabani or veitauvu)
(cf Hocart 1952: 41-46).
(30.) The Sister's child is cross-cousin to Mother's
Brother's children, and while today marriage is possible between
immediate cross-cousins it used not to be so; thus with respect to
Mother's Brother's children, the Sister's children were
neither in an incest category nor in a marriage category, neither within
the same household nor fully outside it; they mediated between
marriageable and non-marriageable kin and so their rights as vasu
reference the relation between Brother and Sister in the ascending generation and that between cross-cousins in ego's generation.
(31.) Thus Sahlins (1976:28) notes that: Four is the Lauan numerical
concept of a totality'; cf. Hocart (1952:29).
(32.) Given that Narai was `leader of the Sawaieke people' at
the time of the story of Biu, he would himself have been `sea', as
were the Nakobuna people who were his navigators; other clans, such as
Navure, would have been classified as `land' in relation to the
Sawaieke clan as `sea'. But the sea/land distinction is inherently
transformable, so when Biu comes on the scene as the `stranger from over
the sea' he is `sea' and the indigenous chief NaRai becomes
`land' by virtue of the outcome of their subsequent encounter.
(33.) Attendance on a god or a chief is explicitly said to empower
them; note that everyone has ancestors to call on and that witchcraft
consists in the solitary offering of libations of yaqona to one's
own or someone else's ancestors, in order at once to empower them
and to direct this power to one's own selfish ends.
(34.) The apparent success of parliamentary democracy in Fiji and the
inevitability of the coups of 1987 can be explained by virtue of this
same logic. Democracy worked well enough when it was seen to be under
the aegis of Fijian chiefs, but the egalitarian ethic could not be
allowed to become an encompassing form -- as it would be if chiefs can
no longer be seen to take precedence in government.
(35.) Given that cognitive processes are inevitably micro-historical
and dynamic and that each one of us manifests the biology of cognition as historically located subjects, this antithesis between mind and
matter can be collapsed (see Toren 1993).
(36.) This passage from Dumont is a slippery one; implicitly it
refers to Saussure's distinction between langue and parole with
langage as the product of their interaction. I follow Volosinov (1986
[19291) in rejecting the formalism of Saussurean theory and its
anti-phenomenological and anti-materialist stance.
REFERENCES
BARNES, R.H., Daniel de Coppet & R.J. Parkin eds) 1985. Contexts
and Levels. Anthropological essays on hierarchy, JASO Occasional Papers
No. 4, Oxford 1985.
CAPELL, A. 1973 [19411 A New Fijian Dictionary. Suva: Government
Printer.
DAVIDSON, JW & SCARR, D. (eds) 1976 Pacific Island Portraits.
Canberra, Australian National University.
DUMONT, L. 1980 [19661 Homo Hierarchicus: The Caste System and its
Implications. Chicago, London: The University of Chicago Press.
HOCART, A.M. 1929 Lau Islands, Fiji. Bulletin of the Berenice P.
Bishop Museum.
HOCART, A.M. 1970 [1936] Kings and Councillors. Chicago, London: The
University of Chicago Press.
HOCART, A.M. 1952 The Northern States of Fiji. Occasional Publication
No. 11, London: The Royal Anthropological institute.
JOLLY, M. (forthcoming) Hierarchy and encompassment: Rank, Gender
and Place in North Vanuatu and Fiji'. In Mark Mosko and Margaret
Jolly (eds), Transformations of Hierarchy: Structure, History and
Horizon in the Austronesian World.
LEVI-STRAUSS, C. 1983 [1979] The Way of the Masks. London, Jonathan
Cape.
LEVI-STRAUSS, C. 1984 Anthropology and Myth. Lectures 19.51-1982.
Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
MOSKO, M. and JOLLY M. (eds). (forthcoming). Transformations of
Hierarchy: Structure, History and Horizon in the Austronesian World.
SAHLINS, M. 1976 Culture and Practical Reason. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
SAHLINS, M. 1985 Islands of History. London & New York: Tavistock
Publications.
SAHLINS, M. 1991. The return of the event, again; with reflections on
the beginnings of the great Fijian war of 1843 to 1855 between the
kingdoms of Bau and Rewa. In Aletta Biersack (ed.) Clio in Oceania.
Towards a Historical Anthropology. Washington & London: Smithsonian
Institution Press.
SAYES, S. 1984 Cakaudrove.: Ideology and Reality in a Fijian
Confederation. PhD Thesis, Canberra, Australia National University.
SCARR, D. 1976 Cakobau and Ma'afu: Contenders for Pre-eminence
in Fiji. in J.W. Davidson & D. Scarr (eds), Pacific Island
Portraits. Canberra: Australian National University.
THOMAS, N. 1986 Planets Around the Sun. Sydney: Oceania Monographs.
THOMAS, N. (forthcoming) Kingship and Hierarchy: Transformations of
Polities and Ritual in Eastern Oceania. In Mark Mosko and Margaret Jolly
(eds), Transformations of Hierarchy: Structure, History and Horizon in
the Austronesian World.
TOREN, C. 1988, Making the Present, Revealing the Past: the
Mutability and Continuity of Tradition as Process. Man (N.S) 23:
696-717.
TOREN, C. 1989, Drinking Cash: the Purification of Money through
Ceremonial Exchange in Fiji. In J.Parry & M. Bloch (eds), Money and
the Morality of Exchange, Cambridge University Press.
TOREN, C. 1990, Making Sense of Hierarchy. Cognition as social
Process in Fiji. London School of Economics, Monographs in Social
Anthropology 61, Athlone Press.
TOREN, C. (in press (a)), Transforming Love: the Experience of Fijian
Hierarchy. In P.Gow and P.Harvey (eds), Sexuality and Violence. London:
Routledge.
TOREN, C. (in press (b)), The Drinker as Chief and Rebel: Kava and
Alcohol in Fiji. In M.Macdonald (ed.), Gender, Drink and Drugs. Oxford
and New York, Berg.
TOREN, C. (in press (c)), Seeing the Ancestral Sites: Transformations
in Fijian Topography. in E.Hirsch & M.O'Hanlon (eds),
Anthropology of the Landscape. Oxford University Press.
TOREN, C. 1993. Making History: the Significance of Childhood
Cognition for a Comparative Anthropology of Mind. Man, September, 1993.
TOREN, C. (forthcoming (a)), Cosmogonic Aspects of Desire and
Compassion in Fiji. In D.Coppet and Alteanu eds), Society and
Cosmology.
VOLOSINOV, V.N. 1986 [1929] Marxism and the Philosophy of Language.
Cambridge Mass. & London: Harvard University Press.