Inside Terrorism.
Eland, Ivan
Inside Terrorism, by Bruce Hoffman. New York: Columbia University
Press, 1998. 288 pages, with index and bibliography. $24.95, hardcover.
Bruce Hoffman's well-written book provides useful insights
into the tactics and technologies used by terrorist groups and the
historical evolution of terrorism. As a result, the book is very much
worth reading. On the other hand, Hoffman's definition of
terrorism, typology of terrorist groups, and treatment of
terrorists' potential use of weapons of mass destruction leaves
something to be desired.
The author begins by devoting a whole chapter to defining
terrorism. Normally, books that devote that much space to defining
subject matter are sleep-inducing. Yet such a lengthy discussion is
probably warranted in the case of terrorism. As Hoffman points out,
everyone agrees that "terrorism is a pejorative term" but no
consensus exists on what acts and what groups of people are included
therein. He quotes Brian Jenkins, a noted authority on terrorism, who
states that "if one party can successfully attach the label
terrorist to its opponent, then it has indirectly persuaded others to
adopt its moral viewpoint." For example, the Nazis attempted to
label as terrorists the groups resisting Germany's occupation of
their lands. That example illustrates that the cliche "one
person's terrorist is another person's freedom fighter"
has some validity.
But shouldn't the definition of terrorism focus on what
tactics and methods are used in the attacks? Brian Jenkins and others
argue that terrorism should be defined "by the nature of the act,
not by the identity of the perpetrators or the nature of their
cause." Hoffman is not entirely satisfied with this solution
because he says that it "plays into the hands of terrorists and
their apologists" (even though he has not yet finished defining the
term "terrorist"). The author notes that Third World groups
claim that condemnations of terrorism inherently favor the strong over
the weak. They maintain that people who are trying to liberate
themselves from foreign oppression, exploitation and human-rights abuses
have a right to use any means available to them. In fact, they argue
that they have little choice but to undertake dramatic acts of
indiscriminate violence to publicize their cause because they have
little firepower and few resources compared to the security forces of
nation states. In contrast, Hoffman notes that established powers like
the NATO nations often identify with the victims in classifying violent
acts as terrorism. Although the author conducts an excellent discussion
of all points of view, he implicitly sides with the established powers.
Hoffman rejects Jenkins's simple definition because it equates
the intentional destruction of civilian populations by governments --
for example, the Luftwaffe's air raids on Warsaw and Coventry,
allied firebombing of Dresden and Tokyo, and even the "mutual
assured destruction" nuclear doctrine of Russia and the United
States, which targets civilian populations -- with similar acts by
substate groups labeled as terrorists. Even though Hoffman admits that
governments have caused many more civilian deaths over the years than
substate groups, he argues that a qualitative difference exists between
the two types of attacks. He maintains that rules of war exist (as
codified in the Geneva and Hague conventions) that protect
non-combatants from attack. Hoffman acknowledges that governments have
violated such rules by intentionally attacking civilians, but says that
those incidents are called "war crimes" and can be punished
using admittedly flawed and imperfect international and national
judicial remedies. But he contends that the "fundamental raisons
d'etre of international terrorism is a refusal to be bound by such
rules of warfare and codes of conduct." Thus, he implies that
governments occasionally deviate from the rules of war, but that such
conduct is fundamental to the practices of substate groups that
perpetrate terrorism.
Hoffman is being very selective in his use of the word terrorism.
He apparently believes that governments cannot be accused of terrorism
because they can be punished by war-crimes trials. But most terrorists
would claim that they are fighting a long-term "war" against
oppression and injustice. Furthermore, individuals and groups that have
committed terrorist acts can also be brought to justice. In fact, it may
be easier to bring individuals or groups to justice than government
leaders. In the Pan Am 103 incident, some chance exists of bringing to
justice the two Libyan intelligence agents that allegedly perpetrated
the state-sponsored act, but no one is talking about trying Libyan
leader Moammar Qadhafi for the incident. Thus, Hoffman's conclusion
seems to be that governments are evil only sometimes, but terrorists are
evil by nature.
In fact, the definition that Hoffman ultimately settles on excludes
governments. The author states that terrorism is:
(1) political in its aims;
(2) violent or threatens violence;
(3) designed to have psychological repercussions beyond the
immediate target;
(4) conducted by an organization with an identifiable chain of
command or conspiratorial cell structure;
(5) perpetrated by a subnational group or non-state entity.
The lack of consensus on a definition of terrorism and the great
effort expended by Hoffman to arrive at this one imply that defining
terrorism is difficult and complex, but it may not need to be. No one
can take the adverse moral connotation out of the word
"terrorism." Therefore, Hoffman would be wise to follow
Jenkins's general orientation, which focuses on the act of violence
rather than the perpetrators or the political cause they are promoting.
The best definition of terrorism might be: a direct act of politically
motivated violence (or threat of violence) by an individual, group or
government that intentionally targets innocent civilians to have
psychological effects beyond the immediate targets. (Falling outside
that definition are violent acts against military or governmental
targets that result in unintentional collateral civilian casualties.)
Thus, any individual, group or government that tries to instill terror
in an innocent civilian population should be said to have committed a
"terrorist" act. A substate group blowing up a crowded market
with a crude bomb should be in the same category as a government that
saturation bombs the cities of its enemies during a war. We should not
let governments off the hook just because they are established entities
in the international system, while substate groups are not. Conversely,
substate groups that strike only military or governmental targets should
not be regarded as terrorists.
Hoffman shows his bias by admitting that the armed forces of
governments have been responsible for more death and destruction than
terrorist groups could ever hope to, but then excludes governmental
terrorism from his study. That bias does not, however, negate the
author's contribution. If Hoffman had dropped the value-laden term
"terrorism" and used the term "subguerilla warfare,"
he would have more accurately described what he was studying.
(Henceforth, I will make this substitution of terms.) In his study, he
includes some subguerrilla groups that did intentionally target innocent
civilians and some that did not. His study did not cover any direct
government actions (except government sponsorship of subguerrilla
groups), whether or not they intentionally targeted civilians.
The author does an excellent job of distinguishing between
subguerrilla activity (which he labeled "terrorism") and
guerilla warfare. He notes that although guerillas often use the same
tactics as subguerrillas (for example, assassinations, bombings of
public places, hostage-taking), guerillas are a larger group of
individuals that function in the open, function as a military unit and
attack enemy military forces, and seize and hold territory (subguerrilla
groups avoid all of those tactics). In short, subguerrilla groups have
fewer resources and are weaker than guerilla groups.
Once the reader gets past the definitional problem (which is
rampant in other works in the field, including my own, but should not be
ignored), the book provides much useful information on the nature,
tactics, targets and future of subguerrilla warfare. The author's
chapter on ways that subguerrilla groups manipulate the media was very
insightful. Particularly cogent was his observation that the way the
media covers subguerrilla attacks -- especially coverage that focuses on
the human-interest aspects (for example, the emotions of the relatives
of hostages) -- makes it easier for the attacker to manipulate events
and severely constrains government options to respond to the attack. He
also shows that subguerrilla attacks many times fail to engender the
sympathy of the wider public, but they do instill fear sometimes
bordering on the irrational (for example, one terrorist incident,
although unlikely to recur, can cause mass cancellations of trips
overseas, etc.).
Hoffman does make one important assertion about the media and
subguerrilla warfare that needs some comment:
Throughout the following thirty years [starting in 1968], terrorists have
attacked American citizens and interests more often than any other
country's. While there are various reasons why terrorists find American
targets so attractive, a salient consideration has always been the
unparalleled opportunities for publicity and exposure that terrorists the
world over know they will get from the extensive U.S. news media.
Although the "American news media's worldwide
predominance" might be a factor in attacks against its citizens and
interests, America is attacked primarily for another reason. The United
States is a global superpower and the only nation that currently
conducts military interventions regularly outside its own region. Even
President Clinton and the U.S. Defense Science Board have admitted a
strong historical correlation between U.S. involvement in international
situations and an increase in terrorist attacks against the United
States. The historical record provides ample evidence of this strong
correlation.
Hoffman, like many authors, focuses on the nature, tactics and
targets of subguerrilla groups but pays insufficient attention to their
motives for launching violent attacks. Despite their frequent use of
reprehensible tactics, some of those groups may have legitimate
grievances that spur their violent acts. The author explores the nature
of subguerrilla groups by putting them into four categories: right wing,
left-wing ideological, ethno-nationalist/separatist, and religious. This
typology is useful, but it often masks the motivation behind attacks.
For example, Hoffman notes that the takeover of the U.S. embassy in
Tehran by Islamic militants in 1979 marked the advent of religious
terrorism. Yet the militants attacked the U.S. embassy because the
United States had long supported the despotic government of the shah.
Usama bin Laden is an Islamic fundamentalist, but he attacks U.S.
targets because of U.S. military presence in Saudi Arabia and U.S.
support for Israel. The Islamic fundamentalists who tried to topple the
World Trade Center did so in retaliation for U.S. policies in the Middle
East. Those groups have not attacked U.S. citizens and property because
the United States is not an Islamic country. The groups may be
religious, but they are attacking U.S. foreign policy.
Hoffman also notes that religious subguerrilla groups may have
fewer compunctions about inflicting heavy casualties, making their use
of weapons of mass destruction more likely. The author argues correctly
that with the increased willingness to use weapons of mass destruction,
many of the rules of "terrorism" may need to be rewritten
(Brian Jenkins' premise that "terrorists" want many
people watching, but only a few dead). Hoffman's argument that an
era of casualty escalation may be upon us -- as groups compete to
attract more media attention by causing more death and destruction or by
using weapons of mass destruction -- is very insightful. Yet for such an
important topic, Hoffman disappointingly devotes only a few pages to the
potential use of weapons of mass destruction by subguerrilla groups and
ignores the broader implications of this threat that are so crucial.
Before subguerrilla groups had the technology and willingness to
use weapons of mass destruction, they were merely pinpricks to the great
powers. The groups could cause a few deaths and some fear among the
populations of the most powerful states. Now the strategic environment
has shifted dramatically. Even the weakest actor on the international
stage -- the subguerrilla group -- can directly attack the homeland of a
great power and inflict casualties equivalent to that of a major war.
Even a superpower like the United States is very vulnerable and should
reduce the motivation for such retaliatory subguerrilla attacks by
confining its use of force overseas to the defense of a very narrow set
of vital interests.
Ivan Eland
Director of defense policy studies, Cato Institute